adam@398
|
1 (* Copyright (c) 2008-2012, Adam Chlipala
|
adamc@26
|
2 *
|
adamc@26
|
3 * This work is licensed under a
|
adamc@26
|
4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
|
adamc@26
|
5 * Unported License.
|
adamc@26
|
6 * The license text is available at:
|
adamc@26
|
7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
|
adamc@26
|
8 *)
|
adamc@26
|
9
|
adamc@26
|
10 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@26
|
11 Require Import List.
|
adamc@26
|
12
|
adam@314
|
13 Require Import CpdtTactics.
|
adamc@26
|
14
|
adamc@26
|
15 Set Implicit Arguments.
|
adamc@26
|
16 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@26
|
17
|
adamc@26
|
18
|
adamc@74
|
19 (** %\part{Basic Programming and Proving}
|
adamc@74
|
20
|
adamc@74
|
21 \chapter{Introducing Inductive Types}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
22
|
adam@315
|
23 (** In a sense, CIC is built from just two relatively straightforward features: function types and inductive types. From this modest foundation, we can prove effectively all of the theorems of math and carry out effectively all program verifications, with enough effort expended. This chapter introduces induction and recursion for functional programming in Coq. Most of our examples reproduce functionality from the Coq standard library, and we have tried to copy the standard library's choices of identifiers, where possible, so many of the definitions here are already available in the default Coq environment.
|
adam@315
|
24
|
adam@315
|
25 The last chapter took a deep dive into some of the more advanced Coq features, to highlight the unusual approach that I advocate in this book. However, from this point on, we will rewind and go back to basics, presenting the relevant features of Coq in a more bottom-up manner. A useful first step is a discussion of the differences and relationships between proofs and programs in Coq. *)
|
adam@315
|
26
|
adam@315
|
27
|
adam@315
|
28 (** * Proof Terms *)
|
adam@315
|
29
|
adam@315
|
30 (** Mainstream presentations of mathematics treat proofs as objects that exist outside of the universe of mathematical objects. However, for a variety of reasoning, it is convenient to encode proofs, traditional mathematical objects, and programs within a single formal language. Validity checks on mathematical objects are useful in any setting, to catch typoes and other uninteresting errors. The benefits of static typing for programs are widely recognized, and Coq brings those benefits to both mathematical objects and programs via a uniform mechanism. In fact, from this point on, we will not bother to distinguish between programs and mathematical objects. Many mathematical formalisms are most easily encoded in terms of programs.
|
adam@315
|
31
|
adam@398
|
32 Proofs are fundamentally different from programs, because any two proofs of a theorem are considered equivalent, from a formal standpoint if not from an engineering standpoint. However, we can use the same type-checking technology to check proofs as we use to validate our programs. This is the %\index{Curry-Howard correspondence}%_Curry-Howard correspondence_ %\cite{Curry,Howard}%, an approach for relating proofs and programs. We represent mathematical theorems as types, such that a theorem's proofs are exactly those programs that type-check at the corresponding type.
|
adam@315
|
33
|
adam@315
|
34 The last chapter's example already snuck in an instance of Curry-Howard. We used the token [->] to stand for both function types and logical implications. One reasonable conclusion upon seeing this might be that some fancy overloading of notations is at work. In fact, functions and implications are precisely identical according to Curry-Howard! That is, they are just two ways of describing the same computational phenomenon.
|
adam@315
|
35
|
adam@315
|
36 A short demonstration should explain how this can be. The identity function over the natural numbers is certainly not a controversial program. *)
|
adam@315
|
37
|
adam@315
|
38 Check (fun x : nat => x).
|
adam@315
|
39 (** [: nat -> nat] *)
|
adam@315
|
40
|
adam@315
|
41 (** Consider this alternate program, which is almost identical to the last one. *)
|
adam@315
|
42
|
adam@315
|
43 Check (fun x : True => x).
|
adam@315
|
44 (** [: True -> True] *)
|
adam@315
|
45
|
adam@315
|
46 (** The identity program is interpreted as a proof that %\index{Gallina terms!True}%[True], the always-true proposition, implies itself! What we see is that Curry-Howard interprets implications as functions, where an input is a proposition being assumed and an output is a proposition being deduced. This intuition is not too far from a common one for informal theorem proving, where we might already think of an implication proof as a process for transforming a hypothesis into a conclusion.
|
adam@315
|
47
|
adam@315
|
48 There are also more primitive proof forms available. For instance, the term %\index{Gallina terms!I}%[I] is the single proof of [True], applicable in any context. *)
|
adam@315
|
49
|
adam@315
|
50 Check I.
|
adam@315
|
51 (** [: True] *)
|
adam@315
|
52
|
adam@315
|
53 (** With [I], we can prove another simple propositional theorem. *)
|
adam@315
|
54
|
adam@315
|
55 Check (fun _ : False => I).
|
adam@315
|
56 (** [: False -> True] *)
|
adam@315
|
57
|
adam@315
|
58 (** No proofs of %\index{Gallina terms!False}%[False] exist in the top-level context, but the implication-as-function analogy gives us an easy way to, for example, show that [False] implies itself. *)
|
adam@315
|
59
|
adam@315
|
60 Check (fun x : False => x).
|
adam@315
|
61 (** [: False -> False] *)
|
adam@315
|
62
|
adam@315
|
63 (** In fact, [False] implies anything, and we can take advantage of this fact with an odd looking [match] expression that has no branches. Since there are no rules for deducing [False], there are no cases to consider! *)
|
adam@315
|
64
|
adam@315
|
65 Check (fun x : False => match x with end : True).
|
adam@315
|
66 (** [: False -> True] *)
|
adam@315
|
67
|
adam@398
|
68 (** Every one of these example programs whose type looks like a logical formula is a %\index{proof term}%_proof term_. We use that name for any Gallina term of a logical type, and we will elaborate shortly on what makes a type logical.
|
adam@315
|
69
|
adam@317
|
70 In the rest of this chapter, we will introduce different ways of defining types. Every example type can be interpreted alternatively as a type of programs or %\index{proposition}%propositions (i.e., formulas or theorem statements).
|
adam@317
|
71
|
adam@398
|
72 One of the first types we introduce will be [bool], with constructors [true] and [false]. Newcomers to Coq often wonder about the distinction between [True] and [true] and the distinction between [False] and [false]. One glib answer is that [True] and [False] are types, but [true] and [false] are not. A more useful answer is that Coq's metatheory guarantees that any term of type [bool] _evaluates_ to either [true] or [false]. This means that we have an _algorithm_ for answering any question phrased as an expression of type [bool]. Conversely, most propositions do not evaluate to [True] or [False]; the language of inductively defined propositions is much richer than that. We ought to be glad that we have no algorithm for deciding mathematical truth, since otherwise it would be clear that we could not formalize undecidable properties, like most any properties of general-purpose programs. *)
|
adamc@26
|
73
|
adamc@26
|
74
|
adamc@26
|
75 (** * Enumerations *)
|
adamc@26
|
76
|
adam@315
|
77 (** Coq inductive types generalize the %\index{algebraic datatypes}%algebraic datatypes found in %\index{Haskell}%Haskell and %\index{ML}%ML. Confusingly enough, inductive types also generalize %\index{generalized algebraic datatypes}%generalized algebraic datatypes (GADTs), by adding the possibility for type dependency. Even so, it is worth backing up from the examples of the last chapter and going over basic, algebraic datatype uses of inductive datatypes, because the chance to prove things about the values of these types adds new wrinkles beyond usual practice in Haskell and ML.
|
adamc@26
|
78
|
adam@315
|
79 The singleton type [unit] is an inductive type:%\index{Gallina terms!unit}\index{Gallina terms!tt}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
80
|
adamc@26
|
81 Inductive unit : Set :=
|
adamc@26
|
82 | tt.
|
adamc@26
|
83
|
adamc@26
|
84 (** This vernacular command defines a new inductive type [unit] whose only value is [tt], as we can see by checking the types of the two identifiers: *)
|
adamc@26
|
85
|
adamc@26
|
86 Check unit.
|
adamc@208
|
87 (** [unit : Set] *)
|
adamc@26
|
88
|
adamc@26
|
89 Check tt.
|
adamc@208
|
90 (** [tt : unit] *)
|
adamc@26
|
91
|
adamc@26
|
92 (** We can prove that [unit] is a genuine singleton type. *)
|
adamc@26
|
93
|
adamc@26
|
94 Theorem unit_singleton : forall x : unit, x = tt.
|
adamc@208
|
95
|
adam@315
|
96 (** The important thing about an inductive type is, unsurprisingly, that you can do induction over its values, and induction is the key to proving this theorem. We ask to proceed by induction on the variable [x].%\index{tactics!induction}% *)
|
adamc@208
|
97
|
adamc@41
|
98 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@26
|
99 induction x.
|
adamc@26
|
100
|
adamc@208
|
101 (** The goal changes to:
|
adamc@208
|
102 [[
|
adamc@26
|
103 tt = tt
|
adam@302
|
104 ]]
|
adam@302
|
105 *)
|
adamc@208
|
106
|
adamc@26
|
107 (** ...which we can discharge trivially. *)
|
adamc@208
|
108
|
adamc@26
|
109 reflexivity.
|
adamc@26
|
110 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
111 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@26
|
112
|
adam@315
|
113 (** It seems kind of odd to write a proof by induction with no inductive hypotheses. We could have arrived at the same result by beginning the proof with:%\index{tactics!destruct}% [[
|
adamc@26
|
114
|
adamc@26
|
115 destruct x.
|
adamc@205
|
116
|
adamc@205
|
117 ]]
|
adamc@205
|
118
|
adam@292
|
119 %\noindent%...which corresponds to %``%#"#proof by case analysis#"#%''% in classical math. For non-recursive inductive types, the two tactics will always have identical behavior. Often case analysis is sufficient, even in proofs about recursive types, and it is nice to avoid introducing unneeded induction hypotheses.
|
adamc@26
|
120
|
adam@398
|
121 What exactly _is_ the %\index{induction principles}%induction principle for [unit]? We can ask Coq: *)
|
adamc@26
|
122
|
adamc@26
|
123 Check unit_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
124 (** [unit_ind : forall P : unit -> Prop, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u] *)
|
adamc@26
|
125
|
adam@315
|
126 (** Every [Inductive] command defining a type [T] also defines an induction principle named [T_ind]. Recall from the last section that our type, operations over it, and principles for reasoning about it all live in the same language and are described by the same type system. The key to telling what is a program and what is a proof lies in the distinction between the type %\index{Gallina terms!Prop}%[Prop], which appears in our induction principle; and the type %\index{Gallina terms!Set}%[Set], which we have seen a few times already.
|
adamc@26
|
127
|
adam@315
|
128 The convention goes like this: [Set] is the type of normal types used in programming, and the values of such types are programs. [Prop] is the type of logical propositions, and the values of such types are proofs. Thus, an induction principle has a type that shows us that it is a function for building proofs.
|
adamc@26
|
129
|
adam@315
|
130 Specifically, [unit_ind] quantifies over a predicate [P] over [unit] values. If we can present a proof that [P] holds of [tt], then we are rewarded with a proof that [P] holds for any value [u] of type [unit]. In our last proof, the predicate was [(][fun u : unit => u = tt)].
|
adam@315
|
131
|
adam@315
|
132 The definition of [unit] places the type in [Set]. By replacing [Set] with [Prop], [unit] with [True], and [tt] with [I], we arrive at precisely the definition of [True] that the Coq standard library employs! The program type [unit] is the Curry-Howard equivalent of the proposition [True]. We might make the tongue-in-cheek claim that, while philosophers have expended much ink on the nature of truth, we have now determined that truth is the [unit] type of functional programming.
|
adamc@26
|
133
|
adamc@26
|
134 %\medskip%
|
adamc@26
|
135
|
adam@315
|
136 We can define an inductive type even simpler than [unit]:%\index{Gallina terms!Empty\_set}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
137
|
adamc@26
|
138 Inductive Empty_set : Set := .
|
adamc@26
|
139
|
adamc@26
|
140 (** [Empty_set] has no elements. We can prove fun theorems about it: *)
|
adamc@26
|
141
|
adamc@26
|
142 Theorem the_sky_is_falling : forall x : Empty_set, 2 + 2 = 5.
|
adamc@41
|
143 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@26
|
144 destruct 1.
|
adamc@26
|
145 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
146 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@26
|
147
|
adam@317
|
148 (** Because [Empty_set] has no elements, the fact of having an element of this type implies anything. We use [destruct 1] instead of [destruct x] in the proof because unused quantified variables are relegated to being referred to by number. (There is a good reason for this, related to the unity of quantifiers and implication. At least within Coq's logical foundation of %\index{constructive logic}%constructive logic, which we elaborate on more in the next chapter, an implication is just a quantification over a proof, where the quantified variable is never used. It generally makes more sense to refer to implication hypotheses by number than by name, and Coq treats our quantifier over an unused variable as an implication in determining the proper behavior.)
|
adamc@26
|
149
|
adamc@26
|
150 We can see the induction principle that made this proof so easy: *)
|
adamc@26
|
151
|
adamc@26
|
152 Check Empty_set_ind.
|
adam@315
|
153 (** [Empty_set_ind : forall (][P : Empty_set -> Prop) (e : Empty_set), P e] *)
|
adamc@26
|
154
|
adam@315
|
155 (** In other words, any predicate over values from the empty set holds vacuously of every such element. In the last proof, we chose the predicate [(][fun _ : Empty_set => 2 + 2 = 5)].
|
adamc@26
|
156
|
adamc@26
|
157 We can also apply this get-out-of-jail-free card programmatically. Here is a lazy way of converting values of [Empty_set] to values of [unit]: *)
|
adamc@26
|
158
|
adamc@26
|
159 Definition e2u (e : Empty_set) : unit := match e with end.
|
adamc@26
|
160
|
adam@315
|
161 (** We employ [match] pattern matching as in the last chapter. Since we match on a value whose type has no constructors, there is no need to provide any branches. This idiom may look familiar; we employed it with proofs of [False] in the last section. In fact, [Empty_set] is the Curry-Howard equivalent of [False]. As for why [Empty_set] starts with a capital letter and not a lowercase letter like [unit] does, we must refer the reader to the authors of the Coq standard library, to which we try to be faithful.
|
adamc@26
|
162
|
adamc@26
|
163 %\medskip%
|
adamc@26
|
164
|
adam@315
|
165 Moving up the ladder of complexity, we can define the booleans:%\index{Gallina terms!bool}\index{Gallina terms!true}\index{Gallina terms!false}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
166
|
adamc@26
|
167 Inductive bool : Set :=
|
adamc@26
|
168 | true
|
adamc@26
|
169 | false.
|
adamc@26
|
170
|
adam@316
|
171 (** We can use less vacuous pattern matching to define boolean negation.%\index{Gallina terms!negb}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
172
|
adam@279
|
173 Definition negb (b : bool) : bool :=
|
adamc@26
|
174 match b with
|
adamc@26
|
175 | true => false
|
adamc@26
|
176 | false => true
|
adamc@26
|
177 end.
|
adamc@26
|
178
|
adam@317
|
179 (** An alternative definition desugars to the above, thanks to an %\index{Gallina terms!if}%[if] notation overloaded to work with any inductive type that has exactly two constructors: *)
|
adamc@27
|
180
|
adam@279
|
181 Definition negb' (b : bool) : bool :=
|
adamc@27
|
182 if b then false else true.
|
adamc@27
|
183
|
adam@279
|
184 (** We might want to prove that [negb] is its own inverse operation. *)
|
adamc@26
|
185
|
adam@279
|
186 Theorem negb_inverse : forall b : bool, negb (negb b) = b.
|
adamc@41
|
187 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@26
|
188 destruct b.
|
adamc@26
|
189
|
adamc@208
|
190 (** After we case-analyze on [b], we are left with one subgoal for each constructor of [bool].
|
adamc@26
|
191
|
adam@315
|
192 %\vspace{.1in} \noindent 2 \coqdockw{subgoals}\vspace{-.1in}%#<tt>2 subgoals</tt>#
|
adam@315
|
193
|
adamc@26
|
194 [[
|
adamc@26
|
195 ============================
|
adam@279
|
196 negb (negb true) = true
|
adamc@26
|
197 ]]
|
adam@315
|
198 %\noindent \coqdockw{subgoal} 2 \coqdockw{is}:%#<tt>subgoal 2 is</tt>#
|
adamc@26
|
199 [[
|
adam@279
|
200 negb (negb false) = false
|
adamc@208
|
201
|
adamc@26
|
202 ]]
|
adamc@26
|
203
|
adamc@26
|
204 The first subgoal follows by Coq's rules of computation, so we can dispatch it easily: *)
|
adamc@26
|
205
|
adamc@26
|
206 reflexivity.
|
adamc@26
|
207
|
adam@315
|
208 (** Likewise for the second subgoal, so we can restart the proof and give a very compact justification.%\index{Vernacular commands!Restart}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
209
|
adam@315
|
210 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@26
|
211 Restart.
|
adam@315
|
212 (* end hide *)
|
adam@315
|
213 (** %\noindent \coqdockw{Restart}%#<tt>Restart</tt>#. *)
|
adam@315
|
214
|
adamc@26
|
215 destruct b; reflexivity.
|
adamc@26
|
216 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
217 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@27
|
218
|
adam@315
|
219 (** Another theorem about booleans illustrates another useful tactic.%\index{tactics!discriminate}% *)
|
adamc@27
|
220
|
adam@279
|
221 Theorem negb_ineq : forall b : bool, negb b <> b.
|
adamc@41
|
222 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@27
|
223 destruct b; discriminate.
|
adamc@27
|
224 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
225 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@27
|
226
|
adamc@27
|
227 (** [discriminate] is used to prove that two values of an inductive type are not equal, whenever the values are formed with different constructors. In this case, the different constructors are [true] and [false].
|
adamc@27
|
228
|
adamc@27
|
229 At this point, it is probably not hard to guess what the underlying induction principle for [bool] is. *)
|
adamc@27
|
230
|
adamc@27
|
231 Check bool_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
232 (** [bool_ind : forall P : bool -> Prop, P true -> P false -> forall b : bool, P b] *)
|
adamc@28
|
233
|
adam@315
|
234 (** That is, to prove that a property describes all [bool]s, prove that it describes both [true] and [false].
|
adam@315
|
235
|
adam@392
|
236 There is no interesting Curry-Howard analogue of [bool]. Of course, we can define such a type by replacing [Set] by [Prop] above, but the proposition we arrive at is not very useful. It is logically equivalent to [True], but it provides two indistinguishable primitive proofs, [true] and [false]. In the rest of the chapter, we will skip commenting on Curry-Howard versions of inductive definitions where such versions are not interesting. *)
|
adam@315
|
237
|
adamc@28
|
238
|
adamc@28
|
239 (** * Simple Recursive Types *)
|
adamc@28
|
240
|
adam@315
|
241 (** The natural numbers are the simplest common example of an inductive type that actually deserves the name.%\index{Gallina terms!nat}\index{Gallina terms!O}\index{Gallina terms!S}% *)
|
adamc@28
|
242
|
adamc@28
|
243 Inductive nat : Set :=
|
adamc@28
|
244 | O : nat
|
adamc@28
|
245 | S : nat -> nat.
|
adamc@28
|
246
|
adam@315
|
247 (** [O] is zero, and [S] is the successor function, so that [0] is syntactic sugar for [O], [1] for [S O], [2] for [S (][S O)], and so on.
|
adamc@28
|
248
|
adam@316
|
249 Pattern matching works as we demonstrated in the last chapter:%\index{Gallina terms!pred}% *)
|
adamc@28
|
250
|
adamc@28
|
251 Definition isZero (n : nat) : bool :=
|
adamc@28
|
252 match n with
|
adamc@28
|
253 | O => true
|
adamc@28
|
254 | S _ => false
|
adamc@28
|
255 end.
|
adamc@28
|
256
|
adamc@28
|
257 Definition pred (n : nat) : nat :=
|
adamc@28
|
258 match n with
|
adamc@28
|
259 | O => O
|
adamc@28
|
260 | S n' => n'
|
adamc@28
|
261 end.
|
adamc@28
|
262
|
adamc@28
|
263 (** We can prove theorems by case analysis: *)
|
adamc@28
|
264
|
adamc@28
|
265 Theorem S_isZero : forall n : nat, isZero (pred (S (S n))) = false.
|
adamc@41
|
266 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
267 destruct n; reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
268 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
269 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
270
|
adam@316
|
271 (** We can also now get into genuine inductive theorems. First, we will need a recursive function, to make things interesting.%\index{Gallina terms!plus}% *)
|
adamc@28
|
272
|
adamc@208
|
273 Fixpoint plus (n m : nat) : nat :=
|
adamc@28
|
274 match n with
|
adamc@28
|
275 | O => m
|
adamc@28
|
276 | S n' => S (plus n' m)
|
adamc@28
|
277 end.
|
adamc@28
|
278
|
adamc@208
|
279 (** Recall that [Fixpoint] is Coq's mechanism for recursive function definitions. Some theorems about [plus] can be proved without induction. *)
|
adamc@28
|
280
|
adamc@28
|
281 Theorem O_plus_n : forall n : nat, plus O n = n.
|
adamc@41
|
282 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
283 intro; reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
284 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
285 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
286
|
adamc@208
|
287 (** Coq's computation rules automatically simplify the application of [plus], because unfolding the definition of [plus] gives us a [match] expression where the branch to be taken is obvious from syntax alone. If we just reverse the order of the arguments, though, this no longer works, and we need induction. *)
|
adamc@28
|
288
|
adamc@28
|
289 Theorem n_plus_O : forall n : nat, plus n O = n.
|
adamc@41
|
290 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
291 induction n.
|
adamc@28
|
292
|
adam@398
|
293 (** Our first subgoal is [plus O O = O], which _is_ trivial by computation. *)
|
adamc@28
|
294
|
adamc@28
|
295 reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
296
|
adamc@28
|
297 (** Our second subgoal is more work and also demonstrates our first inductive hypothesis.
|
adamc@28
|
298
|
adamc@28
|
299 [[
|
adamc@28
|
300 n : nat
|
adamc@28
|
301 IHn : plus n O = n
|
adamc@28
|
302 ============================
|
adamc@28
|
303 plus (S n) O = S n
|
adamc@208
|
304
|
adamc@28
|
305 ]]
|
adamc@28
|
306
|
adam@315
|
307 We can start out by using computation to simplify the goal as far as we can.%\index{tactics!simpl}% *)
|
adamc@28
|
308
|
adamc@28
|
309 simpl.
|
adamc@28
|
310
|
adam@315
|
311 (** Now the conclusion is [S (][plus n O) = S n]. Using our inductive hypothesis: *)
|
adamc@28
|
312
|
adamc@28
|
313 rewrite IHn.
|
adamc@28
|
314
|
adamc@28
|
315 (** ...we get a trivial conclusion [S n = S n]. *)
|
adamc@28
|
316
|
adamc@28
|
317 reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
318
|
adam@315
|
319 (** Not much really went on in this proof, so the [crush] tactic from the [CpdtTactics] module can prove this theorem automatically. *)
|
adamc@28
|
320
|
adam@315
|
321 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@28
|
322 Restart.
|
adam@315
|
323 (* end hide *)
|
adam@315
|
324 (** %\noindent \coqdockw{Restart}%#<tt>Restart</tt>#. *)
|
adam@315
|
325
|
adamc@28
|
326 induction n; crush.
|
adamc@28
|
327 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
328 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
329
|
adamc@28
|
330 (** We can check out the induction principle at work here: *)
|
adamc@28
|
331
|
adamc@28
|
332 Check nat_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
333 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
334 nat_ind : forall P : nat -> Prop,
|
adamc@208
|
335 P O -> (forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) -> forall n : nat, P n
|
adamc@208
|
336
|
adamc@208
|
337 ]]
|
adamc@28
|
338
|
adam@315
|
339 Each of the two cases of our last proof came from the type of one of the arguments to [nat_ind]. We chose [P] to be [(][fun n : nat => plus n O = n)]. The first proof case corresponded to [P O] and the second case to [(][forall n : nat, P n -> P (][S n))]. The free variable [n] and inductive hypothesis [IHn] came from the argument types given here.
|
adamc@28
|
340
|
adam@315
|
341 Since [nat] has a constructor that takes an argument, we may sometimes need to know that that constructor is injective.%\index{tactics!injection}\index{tactics!trivial}% *)
|
adamc@28
|
342
|
adamc@28
|
343 Theorem S_inj : forall n m : nat, S n = S m -> n = m.
|
adamc@41
|
344 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
345 injection 1; trivial.
|
adamc@28
|
346 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
347 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
348
|
adamc@28
|
349 (** [injection] refers to a premise by number, adding new equalities between the corresponding arguments of equated terms that are formed with the same constructor. We end up needing to prove [n = m -> n = m], so it is unsurprising that a tactic named [trivial] is able to finish the proof.
|
adamc@28
|
350
|
adam@398
|
351 There is also a very useful tactic called %\index{tactics!congruence}%[congruence] that can prove this theorem immediately. [congruence] generalizes [discriminate] and [injection], and it also adds reasoning about the general properties of equality, such as that a function returns equal results on equal arguments. That is, [congruence] is a %\index{theory of equality and uninterpreted functions}%_complete decision procedure for the theory of equality and uninterpreted functions_, plus some smarts about inductive types.
|
adamc@29
|
352
|
adamc@29
|
353 %\medskip%
|
adamc@29
|
354
|
adamc@29
|
355 We can define a type of lists of natural numbers. *)
|
adamc@29
|
356
|
adamc@29
|
357 Inductive nat_list : Set :=
|
adamc@29
|
358 | NNil : nat_list
|
adamc@29
|
359 | NCons : nat -> nat_list -> nat_list.
|
adamc@29
|
360
|
adamc@29
|
361 (** Recursive definitions are straightforward extensions of what we have seen before. *)
|
adamc@29
|
362
|
adamc@29
|
363 Fixpoint nlength (ls : nat_list) : nat :=
|
adamc@29
|
364 match ls with
|
adamc@29
|
365 | NNil => O
|
adamc@29
|
366 | NCons _ ls' => S (nlength ls')
|
adamc@29
|
367 end.
|
adamc@29
|
368
|
adamc@208
|
369 Fixpoint napp (ls1 ls2 : nat_list) : nat_list :=
|
adamc@29
|
370 match ls1 with
|
adamc@29
|
371 | NNil => ls2
|
adamc@29
|
372 | NCons n ls1' => NCons n (napp ls1' ls2)
|
adamc@29
|
373 end.
|
adamc@29
|
374
|
adamc@29
|
375 (** Inductive theorem proving can again be automated quite effectively. *)
|
adamc@29
|
376
|
adamc@29
|
377 Theorem nlength_napp : forall ls1 ls2 : nat_list, nlength (napp ls1 ls2)
|
adamc@29
|
378 = plus (nlength ls1) (nlength ls2).
|
adamc@41
|
379 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@29
|
380 induction ls1; crush.
|
adamc@29
|
381 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
382 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@29
|
383
|
adamc@29
|
384 Check nat_list_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
385 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
386 nat_list_ind
|
adamc@29
|
387 : forall P : nat_list -> Prop,
|
adamc@29
|
388 P NNil ->
|
adamc@29
|
389 (forall (n : nat) (n0 : nat_list), P n0 -> P (NCons n n0)) ->
|
adamc@29
|
390 forall n : nat_list, P n
|
adamc@29
|
391 ]]
|
adamc@29
|
392
|
adamc@29
|
393 %\medskip%
|
adamc@29
|
394
|
adam@292
|
395 In general, we can implement any %``%#"#tree#"#%''% types as inductive types. For example, here are binary trees of naturals. *)
|
adamc@29
|
396
|
adamc@29
|
397 Inductive nat_btree : Set :=
|
adamc@29
|
398 | NLeaf : nat_btree
|
adamc@29
|
399 | NNode : nat_btree -> nat -> nat_btree -> nat_btree.
|
adamc@29
|
400
|
adamc@29
|
401 Fixpoint nsize (tr : nat_btree) : nat :=
|
adamc@29
|
402 match tr with
|
adamc@35
|
403 | NLeaf => S O
|
adamc@29
|
404 | NNode tr1 _ tr2 => plus (nsize tr1) (nsize tr2)
|
adamc@29
|
405 end.
|
adamc@29
|
406
|
adamc@208
|
407 Fixpoint nsplice (tr1 tr2 : nat_btree) : nat_btree :=
|
adamc@29
|
408 match tr1 with
|
adamc@35
|
409 | NLeaf => NNode tr2 O NLeaf
|
adamc@29
|
410 | NNode tr1' n tr2' => NNode (nsplice tr1' tr2) n tr2'
|
adamc@29
|
411 end.
|
adamc@29
|
412
|
adamc@29
|
413 Theorem plus_assoc : forall n1 n2 n3 : nat, plus (plus n1 n2) n3 = plus n1 (plus n2 n3).
|
adamc@41
|
414 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@29
|
415 induction n1; crush.
|
adamc@29
|
416 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
417 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@29
|
418
|
adamc@29
|
419 Theorem nsize_nsplice : forall tr1 tr2 : nat_btree, nsize (nsplice tr1 tr2)
|
adamc@29
|
420 = plus (nsize tr2) (nsize tr1).
|
adamc@41
|
421 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@315
|
422 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@375
|
423 Hint Rewrite n_plus_O plus_assoc.
|
adam@315
|
424 (* end hide *)
|
adam@375
|
425 (** [Hint] %\coqdockw{%#<tt>#Rewrite#</tt>#%}% [n_plus_O plus_assoc.] *)
|
adamc@29
|
426
|
adamc@29
|
427 induction tr1; crush.
|
adamc@29
|
428 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
429 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@29
|
430
|
adam@315
|
431 (** It is convenient that these proofs go through so easily, but it is useful to check that the tree induction principle works as usual. *)
|
adam@315
|
432
|
adamc@29
|
433 Check nat_btree_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
434 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
435 nat_btree_ind
|
adamc@29
|
436 : forall P : nat_btree -> Prop,
|
adamc@29
|
437 P NLeaf ->
|
adamc@29
|
438 (forall n : nat_btree,
|
adamc@29
|
439 P n -> forall (n0 : nat) (n1 : nat_btree), P n1 -> P (NNode n n0 n1)) ->
|
adamc@29
|
440 forall n : nat_btree, P n
|
adam@302
|
441 ]]
|
adam@315
|
442
|
adam@315
|
443 We have the usual two cases, one for each constructor of [nat_btree]. *)
|
adamc@30
|
444
|
adamc@30
|
445
|
adamc@30
|
446 (** * Parameterized Types *)
|
adamc@30
|
447
|
adam@316
|
448 (** We can also define %\index{polymorphism}%polymorphic inductive types, as with algebraic datatypes in Haskell and ML.%\index{Gallina terms!list}\index{Gallina terms!Nil}\index{Gallina terms!Cons}\index{Gallina terms!length}\index{Gallina terms!app}% *)
|
adamc@30
|
449
|
adamc@30
|
450 Inductive list (T : Set) : Set :=
|
adamc@30
|
451 | Nil : list T
|
adamc@30
|
452 | Cons : T -> list T -> list T.
|
adamc@30
|
453
|
adamc@30
|
454 Fixpoint length T (ls : list T) : nat :=
|
adamc@30
|
455 match ls with
|
adamc@30
|
456 | Nil => O
|
adamc@30
|
457 | Cons _ ls' => S (length ls')
|
adamc@30
|
458 end.
|
adamc@30
|
459
|
adamc@208
|
460 Fixpoint app T (ls1 ls2 : list T) : list T :=
|
adamc@30
|
461 match ls1 with
|
adamc@30
|
462 | Nil => ls2
|
adamc@30
|
463 | Cons x ls1' => Cons x (app ls1' ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
464 end.
|
adamc@30
|
465
|
adamc@30
|
466 Theorem length_app : forall T (ls1 ls2 : list T), length (app ls1 ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
467 = plus (length ls1) (length ls2).
|
adamc@41
|
468 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@30
|
469 induction ls1; crush.
|
adamc@30
|
470 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
471 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@30
|
472
|
adam@398
|
473 (** There is a useful shorthand for writing many definitions that share the same parameter, based on Coq's %\index{sections}\index{Vernacular commands!Section}\index{Vernacular commands!Variable}%_section_ mechanism. The following block of code is equivalent to the above: *)
|
adamc@30
|
474
|
adamc@30
|
475 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@30
|
476 Reset list.
|
adamc@30
|
477 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@30
|
478
|
adamc@30
|
479 Section list.
|
adamc@30
|
480 Variable T : Set.
|
adamc@30
|
481
|
adamc@30
|
482 Inductive list : Set :=
|
adamc@30
|
483 | Nil : list
|
adamc@30
|
484 | Cons : T -> list -> list.
|
adamc@30
|
485
|
adamc@30
|
486 Fixpoint length (ls : list) : nat :=
|
adamc@30
|
487 match ls with
|
adamc@30
|
488 | Nil => O
|
adamc@30
|
489 | Cons _ ls' => S (length ls')
|
adamc@30
|
490 end.
|
adamc@30
|
491
|
adamc@208
|
492 Fixpoint app (ls1 ls2 : list) : list :=
|
adamc@30
|
493 match ls1 with
|
adamc@30
|
494 | Nil => ls2
|
adamc@30
|
495 | Cons x ls1' => Cons x (app ls1' ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
496 end.
|
adamc@30
|
497
|
adamc@30
|
498 Theorem length_app : forall ls1 ls2 : list, length (app ls1 ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
499 = plus (length ls1) (length ls2).
|
adamc@41
|
500 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@30
|
501 induction ls1; crush.
|
adamc@30
|
502 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
503 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@30
|
504 End list.
|
adamc@30
|
505
|
adamc@35
|
506 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@35
|
507 Implicit Arguments Nil [T].
|
adamc@35
|
508 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@35
|
509
|
adamc@210
|
510 (** After we end the section, the [Variable]s we used are added as extra function parameters for each defined identifier, as needed. We verify that this has happened using the [Print] command, a cousin of [Check] which shows the definition of a symbol, rather than just its type. *)
|
adamc@30
|
511
|
adamc@202
|
512 Print list.
|
adamc@208
|
513 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
514 Inductive list (T : Set) : Set :=
|
adam@316
|
515 Nil : list T | Cons : T -> list T -> list T
|
adamc@208
|
516
|
adamc@202
|
517 ]]
|
adamc@30
|
518
|
adamc@202
|
519 The final definition is the same as what we wrote manually before. The other elements of the section are altered similarly, turning out exactly as they were before, though we managed to write their definitions more succinctly. *)
|
adamc@30
|
520
|
adamc@30
|
521 Check length.
|
adamc@208
|
522 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
523 length
|
adamc@30
|
524 : forall T : Set, list T -> nat
|
adamc@30
|
525 ]]
|
adamc@30
|
526
|
adamc@202
|
527 The parameter [T] is treated as a new argument to the induction principle, too. *)
|
adamc@30
|
528
|
adamc@30
|
529 Check list_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
530 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
531 list_ind
|
adamc@30
|
532 : forall (T : Set) (P : list T -> Prop),
|
adamc@30
|
533 P (Nil T) ->
|
adamc@30
|
534 (forall (t : T) (l : list T), P l -> P (Cons t l)) ->
|
adamc@30
|
535 forall l : list T, P l
|
adamc@30
|
536 ]]
|
adamc@30
|
537
|
adamc@30
|
538 Thus, even though we just saw that [T] is added as an extra argument to the constructor [Cons], there is no quantifier for [T] in the type of the inductive case like there is for each of the other arguments. *)
|
adamc@31
|
539
|
adamc@31
|
540
|
adamc@31
|
541 (** * Mutually Inductive Types *)
|
adamc@31
|
542
|
adamc@31
|
543 (** We can define inductive types that refer to each other: *)
|
adamc@31
|
544
|
adamc@31
|
545 Inductive even_list : Set :=
|
adamc@31
|
546 | ENil : even_list
|
adamc@31
|
547 | ECons : nat -> odd_list -> even_list
|
adamc@31
|
548
|
adamc@31
|
549 with odd_list : Set :=
|
adamc@31
|
550 | OCons : nat -> even_list -> odd_list.
|
adamc@31
|
551
|
adamc@31
|
552 Fixpoint elength (el : even_list) : nat :=
|
adamc@31
|
553 match el with
|
adamc@31
|
554 | ENil => O
|
adamc@31
|
555 | ECons _ ol => S (olength ol)
|
adamc@31
|
556 end
|
adamc@31
|
557
|
adamc@31
|
558 with olength (ol : odd_list) : nat :=
|
adamc@31
|
559 match ol with
|
adamc@31
|
560 | OCons _ el => S (elength el)
|
adamc@31
|
561 end.
|
adamc@31
|
562
|
adamc@208
|
563 Fixpoint eapp (el1 el2 : even_list) : even_list :=
|
adamc@31
|
564 match el1 with
|
adamc@31
|
565 | ENil => el2
|
adamc@31
|
566 | ECons n ol => ECons n (oapp ol el2)
|
adamc@31
|
567 end
|
adamc@31
|
568
|
adamc@208
|
569 with oapp (ol : odd_list) (el : even_list) : odd_list :=
|
adamc@31
|
570 match ol with
|
adamc@31
|
571 | OCons n el' => OCons n (eapp el' el)
|
adamc@31
|
572 end.
|
adamc@31
|
573
|
adamc@31
|
574 (** Everything is going roughly the same as in past examples, until we try to prove a theorem similar to those that came before. *)
|
adamc@31
|
575
|
adamc@31
|
576 Theorem elength_eapp : forall el1 el2 : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
577 elength (eapp el1 el2) = plus (elength el1) (elength el2).
|
adamc@41
|
578 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@31
|
579 induction el1; crush.
|
adamc@31
|
580
|
adamc@31
|
581 (** One goal remains: [[
|
adamc@31
|
582
|
adamc@31
|
583 n : nat
|
adamc@31
|
584 o : odd_list
|
adamc@31
|
585 el2 : even_list
|
adamc@31
|
586 ============================
|
adamc@31
|
587 S (olength (oapp o el2)) = S (plus (olength o) (elength el2))
|
adamc@31
|
588 ]]
|
adamc@31
|
589
|
adamc@31
|
590 We have no induction hypothesis, so we cannot prove this goal without starting another induction, which would reach a similar point, sending us into a futile infinite chain of inductions. The problem is that Coq's generation of [T_ind] principles is incomplete. We only get non-mutual induction principles generated by default. *)
|
adamc@31
|
591
|
adamc@31
|
592 Abort.
|
adamc@31
|
593 Check even_list_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
594 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
595 even_list_ind
|
adamc@31
|
596 : forall P : even_list -> Prop,
|
adamc@31
|
597 P ENil ->
|
adamc@31
|
598 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P (ECons n o)) ->
|
adamc@31
|
599 forall e : even_list, P e
|
adamc@208
|
600
|
adamc@31
|
601 ]]
|
adamc@31
|
602
|
adam@316
|
603 We see that no inductive hypotheses are included anywhere in the type. To get them, we must ask for mutual principles as we need them, using the %\index{Vernacular commands!Scheme}%[Scheme] command. *)
|
adamc@31
|
604
|
adamc@31
|
605 Scheme even_list_mut := Induction for even_list Sort Prop
|
adamc@31
|
606 with odd_list_mut := Induction for odd_list Sort Prop.
|
adamc@31
|
607
|
adam@316
|
608 (** This invocation of [Scheme] asks for the creation of induction principles [even_list_mut] for the type [even_list] and [odd_list_mut] for the type [odd_list]. The [Induction] keyword says we want standard induction schemes, since [Scheme] supports more exotic choices. Finally, [Sort Prop] establishes that we really want induction schemes, not recursion schemes, which are the same according to Curry-Howard, save for the [Prop]/[Set] distinction. *)
|
adam@316
|
609
|
adamc@31
|
610 Check even_list_mut.
|
adamc@208
|
611 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
612 even_list_mut
|
adamc@31
|
613 : forall (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop),
|
adamc@31
|
614 P ENil ->
|
adamc@31
|
615 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) ->
|
adamc@31
|
616 (forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) ->
|
adamc@31
|
617 forall e : even_list, P e
|
adamc@208
|
618
|
adamc@31
|
619 ]]
|
adamc@31
|
620
|
adam@316
|
621 This is the principle we wanted in the first place. There is one more wrinkle left in using it: the [induction] tactic will not apply it for us automatically. It will be helpful to look at how to prove one of our past examples without using [induction], so that we can then generalize the technique to mutual inductive types.%\index{tactics!apply}% *)
|
adamc@31
|
622
|
adamc@31
|
623 Theorem n_plus_O' : forall n : nat, plus n O = n.
|
adamc@31
|
624 apply (nat_ind (fun n => plus n O = n)); crush.
|
adamc@31
|
625 Qed.
|
adamc@31
|
626
|
adamc@31
|
627 (** From this example, we can see that [induction] is not magic. It only does some bookkeeping for us to make it easy to apply a theorem, which we can do directly with the [apply] tactic. We apply not just an identifier but a partial application of it, specifying the predicate we mean to prove holds for all naturals.
|
adamc@31
|
628
|
adamc@31
|
629 This technique generalizes to our mutual example: *)
|
adamc@31
|
630
|
adamc@31
|
631 Theorem elength_eapp : forall el1 el2 : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
632 elength (eapp el1 el2) = plus (elength el1) (elength el2).
|
adamc@41
|
633
|
adamc@31
|
634 apply (even_list_mut
|
adamc@31
|
635 (fun el1 : even_list => forall el2 : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
636 elength (eapp el1 el2) = plus (elength el1) (elength el2))
|
adamc@31
|
637 (fun ol : odd_list => forall el : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
638 olength (oapp ol el) = plus (olength ol) (elength el))); crush.
|
adamc@31
|
639 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
640 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@31
|
641
|
adamc@31
|
642 (** We simply need to specify two predicates, one for each of the mutually inductive types. In general, it would not be a good idea to assume that a proof assistant could infer extra predicates, so this way of applying mutual induction is about as straightforward as we could hope for. *)
|
adamc@33
|
643
|
adamc@33
|
644
|
adamc@33
|
645 (** * Reflexive Types *)
|
adamc@33
|
646
|
adam@398
|
647 (** A kind of inductive type called a _reflexive type_ is defined in terms of functions that have the type being defined as their range. One very useful class of examples is in modeling variable binders. Our example will be an encoding of the syntax of first-order logic. Since the idea of syntactic encodings of logic may require a bit of acclimation, let us first consider a simpler formula type for a subset of propositional logic. *)
|
adam@316
|
648
|
adam@316
|
649 Inductive pformula : Set :=
|
adam@316
|
650 | Truth : pformula
|
adam@316
|
651 | Falsehood : pformula
|
adam@316
|
652 | Conjunction : pformula -> pformula -> pformula.
|
adam@316
|
653
|
adam@398
|
654 (** A key distinction here is between, for instance, the _syntax_ [Truth] and its _semantics_ [True]. We can make the semantics explicit with a recursive function. This function uses the infix operator %\index{Gallina operators!/\textbackslash}%[/\], which desugars to uses of the type family %\index{Gallina terms!and}%[and] from the standard library. The family [and] implements conjunction, the [Prop] Curry-Howard analogue of the usual pair type from functional programming (which is the type family %\index{Gallina terms!prod}%[prod] in Coq's standard library). *)
|
adam@316
|
655
|
adam@316
|
656 Fixpoint pformulaDenote (f : pformula) : Prop :=
|
adam@316
|
657 match f with
|
adam@316
|
658 | Truth => True
|
adam@316
|
659 | Falsehood => False
|
adam@316
|
660 | Conjunction f1 f2 => pformulaDenote f1 /\ pformulaDenote f2
|
adam@316
|
661 end.
|
adam@316
|
662
|
adam@392
|
663 (** This is just a warm-up that does not use reflexive types, the new feature we mean to introduce. When we set our sights on first-order logic instead, it becomes very handy to give constructors recursive arguments that are functions. *)
|
adamc@33
|
664
|
adamc@33
|
665 Inductive formula : Set :=
|
adamc@33
|
666 | Eq : nat -> nat -> formula
|
adamc@33
|
667 | And : formula -> formula -> formula
|
adamc@33
|
668 | Forall : (nat -> formula) -> formula.
|
adamc@33
|
669
|
adam@316
|
670 (** Our kinds of formulas are equalities between naturals, conjunction, and universal quantification over natural numbers. We avoid needing to include a notion of %``%#"#variables#"#%''% in our type, by using Coq functions to encode quantification. For instance, here is the encoding of [forall x : nat, x = x]:%\index{Vernacular commands!Example}% *)
|
adamc@33
|
671
|
adamc@33
|
672 Example forall_refl : formula := Forall (fun x => Eq x x).
|
adamc@33
|
673
|
adamc@33
|
674 (** We can write recursive functions over reflexive types quite naturally. Here is one translating our formulas into native Coq propositions. *)
|
adamc@33
|
675
|
adamc@33
|
676 Fixpoint formulaDenote (f : formula) : Prop :=
|
adamc@33
|
677 match f with
|
adamc@33
|
678 | Eq n1 n2 => n1 = n2
|
adamc@33
|
679 | And f1 f2 => formulaDenote f1 /\ formulaDenote f2
|
adamc@33
|
680 | Forall f' => forall n : nat, formulaDenote (f' n)
|
adamc@33
|
681 end.
|
adamc@33
|
682
|
adamc@33
|
683 (** We can also encode a trivial formula transformation that swaps the order of equality and conjunction operands. *)
|
adamc@33
|
684
|
adamc@33
|
685 Fixpoint swapper (f : formula) : formula :=
|
adamc@33
|
686 match f with
|
adamc@33
|
687 | Eq n1 n2 => Eq n2 n1
|
adamc@33
|
688 | And f1 f2 => And (swapper f2) (swapper f1)
|
adamc@33
|
689 | Forall f' => Forall (fun n => swapper (f' n))
|
adamc@33
|
690 end.
|
adamc@33
|
691
|
adamc@33
|
692 (** It is helpful to prove that this transformation does not make true formulas false. *)
|
adamc@33
|
693
|
adamc@33
|
694 Theorem swapper_preserves_truth : forall f, formulaDenote f -> formulaDenote (swapper f).
|
adamc@41
|
695 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@33
|
696 induction f; crush.
|
adamc@33
|
697 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
698 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@33
|
699
|
adamc@33
|
700 (** We can take a look at the induction principle behind this proof. *)
|
adamc@33
|
701
|
adamc@33
|
702 Check formula_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
703 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
704 formula_ind
|
adamc@33
|
705 : forall P : formula -> Prop,
|
adamc@33
|
706 (forall n n0 : nat, P (Eq n n0)) ->
|
adamc@33
|
707 (forall f0 : formula,
|
adamc@33
|
708 P f0 -> forall f1 : formula, P f1 -> P (And f0 f1)) ->
|
adamc@33
|
709 (forall f1 : nat -> formula,
|
adamc@33
|
710 (forall n : nat, P (f1 n)) -> P (Forall f1)) ->
|
adamc@33
|
711 forall f2 : formula, P f2
|
adamc@208
|
712
|
adamc@208
|
713 ]]
|
adamc@33
|
714
|
adam@398
|
715 Focusing on the [Forall] case, which comes third, we see that we are allowed to assume that the theorem holds _for any application of the argument function [f1]_. That is, Coq induction principles do not follow a simple rule that the textual representations of induction variables must get shorter in appeals to induction hypotheses. Luckily for us, the people behind the metatheory of Coq have verified that this flexibility does not introduce unsoundness.
|
adamc@33
|
716
|
adamc@33
|
717 %\medskip%
|
adamc@33
|
718
|
adam@316
|
719 Up to this point, we have seen how to encode in Coq more and more of what is possible with algebraic datatypes in %\index{Haskell}%Haskell and %\index{ML}%ML. This may have given the inaccurate impression that inductive types are a strict extension of algebraic datatypes. In fact, Coq must rule out some types allowed by Haskell and ML, for reasons of soundness. Reflexive types provide our first good example of such a case.
|
adamc@33
|
720
|
adam@398
|
721 Given our last example of an inductive type, many readers are probably eager to try encoding the syntax of %\index{lambda calculus}%lambda calculus. Indeed, the function-based representation technique that we just used, called %\index{higher-order abstract syntax}\index{HOAS|see{higher-order abstract syntax}}%_higher-order abstract syntax (HOAS)_ %\cite{HOAS}%, is the representation of choice for lambda calculi in %\index{Twelf}%Twelf and in many applications implemented in Haskell and ML. Let us try to import that choice to Coq: *)
|
adamc@33
|
722 (** [[
|
adamc@33
|
723 Inductive term : Set :=
|
adamc@33
|
724 | App : term -> term -> term
|
adamc@33
|
725 | Abs : (term -> term) -> term.
|
adamc@33
|
726 ]]
|
adamc@33
|
727
|
adam@316
|
728 <<
|
adam@316
|
729 Error: Non strictly positive occurrence of "term" in "(term -> term) -> term"
|
adam@316
|
730 >>
|
adam@316
|
731
|
adam@398
|
732 We have run afoul of the %\index{strict positivity requirement}\index{positivity requirement}%_strict positivity requirement_ for inductive definitions, which says that the type being defined may not occur to the left of an arrow in the type of a constructor argument. It is important that the type of a constructor is viewed in terms of a series of arguments and a result, since obviously we need recursive occurrences to the lefts of the outermost arrows if we are to have recursive occurrences at all. Our candidate definition above violates the positivity requirement because it involves an argument of type [term -> term], where the type [term] that we are defining appears to the left of an arrow. The candidate type of [App] is fine, however, since every occurrence of [term] is either a constructor argument or the final result type.
|
adamc@33
|
733
|
adamc@33
|
734 Why must Coq enforce this restriction? Imagine that our last definition had been accepted, allowing us to write this function:
|
adamc@33
|
735
|
adamc@33
|
736 [[
|
adamc@33
|
737 Definition uhoh (t : term) : term :=
|
adamc@33
|
738 match t with
|
adamc@33
|
739 | Abs f => f t
|
adamc@33
|
740 | _ => t
|
adamc@33
|
741 end.
|
adamc@33
|
742
|
adamc@205
|
743 ]]
|
adamc@205
|
744
|
adamc@33
|
745 Using an informal idea of Coq's semantics, it is easy to verify that the application [uhoh (Abs uhoh)] will run forever. This would be a mere curiosity in OCaml and Haskell, where non-termination is commonplace, though the fact that we have a non-terminating program without explicit recursive function definitions is unusual.
|
adamc@33
|
746
|
adam@316
|
747 %\index{termination checking}%For Coq, however, this would be a disaster. The possibility of writing such a function would destroy all our confidence that proving a theorem means anything. Since Coq combines programs and proofs in one language, we would be able to prove every theorem with an infinite loop.
|
adamc@33
|
748
|
adamc@33
|
749 Nonetheless, the basic insight of HOAS is a very useful one, and there are ways to realize most benefits of HOAS in Coq. We will study a particular technique of this kind in the later chapters on programming language syntax and semantics. *)
|
adamc@34
|
750
|
adamc@34
|
751
|
adam@317
|
752 (** * An Interlude on Induction Principles *)
|
adamc@34
|
753
|
adam@317
|
754 (** As we have emphasized a few times already, Coq proofs are actually programs, written in the same language we have been using in our examples all along. We can get a first sense of what this means by taking a look at the definitions of some of the %\index{induction principles}%induction principles we have used. A close look at the details here will help us construct induction principles manually, which we will see is necessary for some more advanced inductive definitions. *)
|
adamc@34
|
755
|
adam@317
|
756 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@34
|
757 Print unit_ind.
|
adam@317
|
758 (* end hide *)
|
adam@317
|
759 (** %\noindent%[Print] [unit_ind.] *)
|
adam@317
|
760 (** [[
|
adamc@208
|
761 unit_ind =
|
adamc@208
|
762 fun P : unit -> Prop => unit_rect P
|
adamc@34
|
763 : forall P : unit -> Prop, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@208
|
764
|
adamc@34
|
765 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
766
|
adam@317
|
767 We see that this induction principle is defined in terms of a more general principle, [unit_rect]. The %\texttt{%#<tt>#rec#</tt>#%}% stands for %``%#"#recursion principle,#"#%''% and the %\texttt{%#<tt>#t#</tt>#%}% at the end stands for [Type]. *)
|
adamc@34
|
768
|
adamc@34
|
769 Check unit_rect.
|
adamc@208
|
770 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
771 unit_rect
|
adamc@34
|
772 : forall P : unit -> Type, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@208
|
773
|
adamc@34
|
774 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
775
|
adamc@34
|
776 [unit_rect] gives [P] type [unit -> Type] instead of [unit -> Prop]. [Type] is another universe, like [Set] and [Prop]. In fact, it is a common supertype of both. Later on, we will discuss exactly what the significances of the different universes are. For now, it is just important that we can use [Type] as a sort of meta-universe that may turn out to be either [Set] or [Prop]. We can see the symmetry inherent in the subtyping relationship by printing the definition of another principle that was generated for [unit] automatically: *)
|
adamc@34
|
777
|
adam@317
|
778 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@34
|
779 Print unit_rec.
|
adam@317
|
780 (* end hide *)
|
adam@317
|
781 (** %\noindent%[Print] [unit_rec.] *)
|
adam@317
|
782 (** [[
|
adamc@208
|
783 unit_rec =
|
adamc@208
|
784 fun P : unit -> Set => unit_rect P
|
adamc@34
|
785 : forall P : unit -> Set, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@208
|
786
|
adamc@34
|
787 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
788
|
adam@317
|
789 This is identical to the definition for [unit_ind], except that we have substituted [Set] for [Prop]. For most inductive types [T], then, we get not just induction principles [T_ind], but also %\index{recursion principles}%recursion principles [T_rec]. We can use [T_rec] to write recursive definitions without explicit [Fixpoint] recursion. For instance, the following two definitions are equivalent: *)
|
adamc@34
|
790
|
adamc@34
|
791 Definition always_O (u : unit) : nat :=
|
adamc@34
|
792 match u with
|
adamc@34
|
793 | tt => O
|
adamc@34
|
794 end.
|
adamc@34
|
795
|
adamc@34
|
796 Definition always_O' (u : unit) : nat :=
|
adamc@34
|
797 unit_rec (fun _ : unit => nat) O u.
|
adamc@34
|
798
|
adamc@34
|
799 (** Going even further down the rabbit hole, [unit_rect] itself is not even a primitive. It is a functional program that we can write manually. *)
|
adamc@34
|
800
|
adam@317
|
801 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@34
|
802 Print unit_rect.
|
adam@317
|
803 (* end hide *)
|
adam@317
|
804 (** %\noindent%[Print] [unit_rect.] *)
|
adam@317
|
805 (** [[
|
adamc@208
|
806 unit_rect =
|
adamc@208
|
807 fun (P : unit -> Type) (f : P tt) (u : unit) =>
|
adamc@208
|
808 match u as u0 return (P u0) with
|
adamc@208
|
809 | tt => f
|
adamc@208
|
810 end
|
adamc@34
|
811 : forall P : unit -> Type, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@208
|
812
|
adamc@34
|
813 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
814
|
adam@398
|
815 The only new wrinkle here is the annotations on the [match] expression. This is a %\index{dependent pattern matching}%_dependently typed_ pattern match, because the _type_ of the expression depends on the _value_ being matched on. Of course, for this example, the dependency is degenerate; the value being matched on has type [unit], so it may only take on a single known value, [tt]. We will meet more involved examples later, especially in Part II of the book.
|
adam@317
|
816
|
adam@317
|
817 %\index{type inference}%Type inference for dependent pattern matching is undecidable, which can be proved by reduction from %\index{higher-order unification}%higher-order unification%~\cite{HOU}%. Thus, we often find ourselves needing to annotate our programs in a way that explains dependencies to the type checker. In the example of [unit_rect], we have an %\index{Gallina terms!as}%[as] clause, which binds a name for the discriminee; and a %\index{Gallina terms!return}%[return] clause, which gives a way to compute the [match] result type as a function of the discriminee.
|
adamc@34
|
818
|
adamc@34
|
819 To prove that [unit_rect] is nothing special, we can reimplement it manually. *)
|
adamc@34
|
820
|
adamc@34
|
821 Definition unit_rect' (P : unit -> Type) (f : P tt) (u : unit) :=
|
adamc@208
|
822 match u with
|
adamc@34
|
823 | tt => f
|
adamc@34
|
824 end.
|
adamc@34
|
825
|
adam@317
|
826 (** We rely on Coq's heuristics for inferring [match] annotations, which are not consulted in the pretty-printing of terms.
|
adamc@34
|
827
|
adam@317
|
828 We can check the implementation of %\coqdocdefinition{%#<tt>#nat_rect#</tt>#%}% as well: *)
|
adamc@34
|
829
|
adam@317
|
830 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@34
|
831 Print nat_rect.
|
adam@317
|
832 (* end hide *)
|
adam@317
|
833 (** %\noindent%[Print] %\coqdocdefinition{%#<tt>#nat_rect#</tt>#%}%[.] *)
|
adam@317
|
834
|
adam@317
|
835 (** %\hspace{-.05in}\coqdocdefinition{%#<tt>#nat_rect#</tt>#%}% [=] *)
|
adam@317
|
836 (** %\vspace{-.05in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
837 fun (P : nat -> Type) (f : P O) (f0 : forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) =>
|
adamc@208
|
838 fix F (n : nat) : P n :=
|
adamc@208
|
839 match n as n0 return (P n0) with
|
adamc@208
|
840 | O => f
|
adamc@208
|
841 | S n0 => f0 n0 (F n0)
|
adamc@208
|
842 end
|
adamc@208
|
843 : forall P : nat -> Type,
|
adamc@208
|
844 P O -> (forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) -> forall n : nat, P n
|
adamc@208
|
845 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
846
|
adam@317
|
847 Now we have an actual recursive definition. %\index{Gallina terms!fix}%[fix] expressions are an anonymous form of [Fixpoint], just as [fun] expressions stand for anonymous non-recursive functions. Beyond that, the syntax of [fix] mirrors that of [Fixpoint]. We can understand the definition of %\coqdocdefinition{%#<tt>#nat_rect#</tt>#%}% better by reimplementing [nat_ind] using sections. *)
|
adamc@34
|
848
|
adam@317
|
849 Section nat_ind'.
|
adamc@208
|
850 (** First, we have the property of natural numbers that we aim to prove. *)
|
adamc@34
|
851
|
adam@317
|
852 Variable P : nat -> Prop.
|
adamc@34
|
853
|
adam@317
|
854 (** Then we require a proof of the [O] case, which we declare with the command %\index{Vernacular commands!Hypothesis}%[Hypothesis], which is a synonym for [Variable] that, by convention, is used for variables whose types are propositions. *)
|
adamc@34
|
855
|
adam@317
|
856 Hypothesis O_case : P O.
|
adamc@34
|
857
|
adamc@208
|
858 (** Next is a proof of the [S] case, which may assume an inductive hypothesis. *)
|
adamc@34
|
859
|
adam@317
|
860 Hypothesis S_case : forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n).
|
adamc@34
|
861
|
adamc@208
|
862 (** Finally, we define a recursive function to tie the pieces together. *)
|
adamc@34
|
863
|
adam@317
|
864 Fixpoint nat_ind' (n : nat) : P n :=
|
adam@317
|
865 match n with
|
adam@317
|
866 | O => O_case
|
adam@317
|
867 | S n' => S_case (nat_ind' n')
|
adam@317
|
868 end.
|
adam@317
|
869 End nat_ind'.
|
adamc@34
|
870
|
adam@317
|
871 (** Closing the section adds the [Variable]s and [Hypothesis]es as new [fun]-bound arguments to [nat_ind'], and, modulo the use of [Prop] instead of [Type], we end up with the exact same definition that was generated automatically for %\coqdocdefinition{%#<tt>#nat_rect#</tt>#%}%.
|
adamc@34
|
872
|
adam@317
|
873 %\medskip%
|
adamc@34
|
874
|
adam@317
|
875 We can also examine the definition of [even_list_mut], which we generated with [Scheme] for a mutually recursive type. *)
|
adamc@34
|
876
|
adam@317
|
877 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@317
|
878 Print even_list_mut.
|
adam@317
|
879 (* end hide *)
|
adam@317
|
880 (** %\noindent%[Print] %\coqdocdefinition{%#<tt>#even_list_mut#</tt>#%}%[.] *)
|
adam@317
|
881 (** [[
|
adam@317
|
882 even_list_mut =
|
adam@317
|
883 fun (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop)
|
adam@317
|
884 (f : P ENil) (f0 : forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o))
|
adam@317
|
885 (f1 : forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) =>
|
adam@317
|
886 fix F (e : even_list) : P e :=
|
adam@317
|
887 match e as e0 return (P e0) with
|
adam@317
|
888 | ENil => f
|
adam@317
|
889 | ECons n o => f0 n o (F0 o)
|
adam@317
|
890 end
|
adam@317
|
891 with F0 (o : odd_list) : P0 o :=
|
adam@317
|
892 match o as o0 return (P0 o0) with
|
adam@317
|
893 | OCons n e => f1 n e (F e)
|
adam@317
|
894 end
|
adam@317
|
895 for F
|
adam@317
|
896 : forall (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop),
|
adam@317
|
897 P ENil ->
|
adam@317
|
898 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) ->
|
adam@317
|
899 (forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) ->
|
adam@317
|
900 forall e : even_list, P e
|
adamc@34
|
901
|
adam@317
|
902 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
903
|
adam@317
|
904 We see a mutually recursive [fix], with the different functions separated by %\index{Gallina terms!with}%[with] in the same way that they would be separated by %\texttt{%#<tt>#and#</tt>#%}% in ML. A final %\index{Gallina terms!for}%[for] clause identifies which of the mutually recursive functions should be the final value of the [fix] expression. Using this definition as a template, we can reimplement [even_list_mut] directly. *)
|
adamc@208
|
905
|
adam@317
|
906 Section even_list_mut'.
|
adam@317
|
907 (** First, we need the properties that we are proving. *)
|
adamc@208
|
908
|
adam@317
|
909 Variable Peven : even_list -> Prop.
|
adam@317
|
910 Variable Podd : odd_list -> Prop.
|
adamc@208
|
911
|
adam@317
|
912 (** Next, we need proofs of the three cases. *)
|
adamc@208
|
913
|
adam@317
|
914 Hypothesis ENil_case : Peven ENil.
|
adam@317
|
915 Hypothesis ECons_case : forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), Podd o -> Peven (ECons n o).
|
adam@317
|
916 Hypothesis OCons_case : forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), Peven e -> Podd (OCons n e).
|
adamc@208
|
917
|
adam@317
|
918 (** Finally, we define the recursive functions. *)
|
adamc@208
|
919
|
adam@317
|
920 Fixpoint even_list_mut' (e : even_list) : Peven e :=
|
adam@317
|
921 match e with
|
adam@317
|
922 | ENil => ENil_case
|
adam@317
|
923 | ECons n o => ECons_case n (odd_list_mut' o)
|
adam@317
|
924 end
|
adam@317
|
925 with odd_list_mut' (o : odd_list) : Podd o :=
|
adam@317
|
926 match o with
|
adam@317
|
927 | OCons n e => OCons_case n (even_list_mut' e)
|
adam@317
|
928 end.
|
adamc@34
|
929 End even_list_mut'.
|
adamc@34
|
930
|
adamc@34
|
931 (** Even induction principles for reflexive types are easy to implement directly. For our [formula] type, we can use a recursive definition much like those we wrote above. *)
|
adamc@34
|
932
|
adamc@34
|
933 Section formula_ind'.
|
adamc@34
|
934 Variable P : formula -> Prop.
|
adamc@38
|
935 Hypothesis Eq_case : forall n1 n2 : nat, P (Eq n1 n2).
|
adamc@38
|
936 Hypothesis And_case : forall f1 f2 : formula,
|
adamc@34
|
937 P f1 -> P f2 -> P (And f1 f2).
|
adamc@38
|
938 Hypothesis Forall_case : forall f : nat -> formula,
|
adamc@34
|
939 (forall n : nat, P (f n)) -> P (Forall f).
|
adamc@34
|
940
|
adamc@34
|
941 Fixpoint formula_ind' (f : formula) : P f :=
|
adamc@208
|
942 match f with
|
adamc@34
|
943 | Eq n1 n2 => Eq_case n1 n2
|
adamc@34
|
944 | And f1 f2 => And_case (formula_ind' f1) (formula_ind' f2)
|
adamc@34
|
945 | Forall f' => Forall_case f' (fun n => formula_ind' (f' n))
|
adamc@34
|
946 end.
|
adamc@34
|
947 End formula_ind'.
|
adamc@34
|
948
|
adam@317
|
949 (** It is apparent that induction principle implementations involve some tedium but not terribly much creativity. *)
|
adam@317
|
950
|
adamc@35
|
951
|
adamc@35
|
952 (** * Nested Inductive Types *)
|
adamc@35
|
953
|
adamc@35
|
954 (** Suppose we want to extend our earlier type of binary trees to trees with arbitrary finite branching. We can use lists to give a simple definition. *)
|
adamc@35
|
955
|
adamc@35
|
956 Inductive nat_tree : Set :=
|
adamc@35
|
957 | NLeaf' : nat_tree
|
adamc@35
|
958 | NNode' : nat -> list nat_tree -> nat_tree.
|
adamc@35
|
959
|
adam@398
|
960 (** This is an example of a %\index{nested inductive type}%_nested_ inductive type definition, because we use the type we are defining as an argument to a parametrized type family. Coq will not allow all such definitions; it effectively pretends that we are defining [nat_tree] mutually with a version of [list] specialized to [nat_tree], checking that the resulting expanded definition satisfies the usual rules. For instance, if we replaced [list] with a type family that used its parameter as a function argument, then the definition would be rejected as violating the positivity restriction.
|
adamc@35
|
961
|
adam@317
|
962 Like we encountered for mutual inductive types, we find that the automatically generated induction principle for [nat_tree] is too weak. *)
|
adamc@35
|
963
|
adamc@35
|
964 Check nat_tree_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
965 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
966 nat_tree_ind
|
adamc@35
|
967 : forall P : nat_tree -> Prop,
|
adamc@35
|
968 P NLeaf' ->
|
adamc@35
|
969 (forall (n : nat) (l : list nat_tree), P (NNode' n l)) ->
|
adamc@35
|
970 forall n : nat_tree, P n
|
adamc@208
|
971
|
adamc@35
|
972 ]]
|
adamc@35
|
973
|
adam@317
|
974 There is no command like [Scheme] that will implement an improved principle for us. In general, it takes creativity to figure out how to incorporate nested uses of different type families. This is roughly the same creativity employed in the traditional task of strengthening an induction hypothesis. Now that we know how to implement induction principles manually, we are in a position to apply just such creativity to this problem.
|
adamc@35
|
975
|
adamc@35
|
976 First, we will need an auxiliary definition, characterizing what it means for a property to hold of every element of a list. *)
|
adamc@35
|
977
|
adamc@35
|
978 Section All.
|
adamc@35
|
979 Variable T : Set.
|
adamc@35
|
980 Variable P : T -> Prop.
|
adamc@35
|
981
|
adamc@35
|
982 Fixpoint All (ls : list T) : Prop :=
|
adamc@35
|
983 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
984 | Nil => True
|
adamc@35
|
985 | Cons h t => P h /\ All t
|
adamc@35
|
986 end.
|
adamc@35
|
987 End All.
|
adamc@35
|
988
|
adam@317
|
989 (** It will be useful to review the definitions of [True] and [/\], since we will want to write manual proofs of them below. *)
|
adamc@35
|
990
|
adam@317
|
991 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@35
|
992 Print True.
|
adam@317
|
993 (* end hide *)
|
adam@317
|
994 (** %\noindent%[Print] %\coqdocinductive{%#<tt>#True#</tt>#%}%[.] *)
|
adam@317
|
995 (** [[
|
adamc@208
|
996 Inductive True : Prop := I : True
|
adamc@208
|
997 ]]
|
adamc@35
|
998
|
adamc@35
|
999 That is, [True] is a proposition with exactly one proof, [I], which we may always supply trivially.
|
adamc@35
|
1000
|
adam@317
|
1001 Finding the definition of [/\] takes a little more work. Coq supports user registration of arbitrary parsing rules, and it is such a rule that is letting us write [/\] instead of an application of some inductive type family. We can find the underlying inductive type with the %\index{Vernacular commands!Locate}\coqdockw{%#<tt>#Locate#</tt>#%}% command, whose argument may be a parsing token.%\index{Gallina terms!and}% *)
|
adamc@35
|
1002
|
adam@317
|
1003 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@35
|
1004 Locate "/\".
|
adam@317
|
1005 (* end hide *)
|
adam@317
|
1006 (** %\noindent \coqdockw{Locate}%#<tt>Locate</tt># ["/\".] *)
|
adam@317
|
1007 (** [[
|
adam@317
|
1008 "A /\ B" := and A B : type_scope (default interpretation)
|
adam@302
|
1009 ]]
|
adam@302
|
1010 *)
|
adamc@35
|
1011
|
adam@317
|
1012 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@35
|
1013 Print and.
|
adam@317
|
1014 (* end hide *)
|
adam@317
|
1015 (** %\noindent%[Print] %\coqdocinductive{%#<tt>#and#</tt>#%}%[.] *)
|
adam@317
|
1016 (** [[
|
adamc@208
|
1017 Inductive and (A : Prop) (B : Prop) : Prop := conj : A -> B -> A /\ B
|
adam@317
|
1018 ]]
|
adam@317
|
1019 %\vspace{-.1in}%
|
adam@317
|
1020 <<
|
adamc@208
|
1021 For conj: Arguments A, B are implicit
|
adam@317
|
1022 >>
|
adamc@35
|
1023
|
adam@317
|
1024 In addition to the definition of %\coqdocinductive{%#<tt>#and#</tt>#%}% itself, we get information on %\index{implicit arguments}%implicit arguments (and some other information that we omit here). The implicit argument information tells us that we build a proof of a conjunction by calling the constructor [conj] on proofs of the conjuncts, with no need to include the types of those proofs as explicit arguments.
|
adamc@35
|
1025
|
adamc@35
|
1026 %\medskip%
|
adamc@35
|
1027
|
adamc@35
|
1028 Now we create a section for our induction principle, following the same basic plan as in the last section of this chapter. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1029
|
adamc@35
|
1030 Section nat_tree_ind'.
|
adamc@35
|
1031 Variable P : nat_tree -> Prop.
|
adamc@35
|
1032
|
adamc@38
|
1033 Hypothesis NLeaf'_case : P NLeaf'.
|
adamc@38
|
1034 Hypothesis NNode'_case : forall (n : nat) (ls : list nat_tree),
|
adamc@35
|
1035 All P ls -> P (NNode' n ls).
|
adamc@35
|
1036
|
adamc@35
|
1037 (** A first attempt at writing the induction principle itself follows the intuition that nested inductive type definitions are expanded into mutual inductive definitions.
|
adamc@35
|
1038
|
adamc@35
|
1039 [[
|
adamc@35
|
1040 Fixpoint nat_tree_ind' (tr : nat_tree) : P tr :=
|
adamc@208
|
1041 match tr with
|
adamc@35
|
1042 | NLeaf' => NLeaf'_case
|
adamc@35
|
1043 | NNode' n ls => NNode'_case n ls (list_nat_tree_ind ls)
|
adamc@35
|
1044 end
|
adamc@35
|
1045
|
adamc@35
|
1046 with list_nat_tree_ind (ls : list nat_tree) : All P ls :=
|
adamc@208
|
1047 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
1048 | Nil => I
|
adamc@35
|
1049 | Cons tr rest => conj (nat_tree_ind' tr) (list_nat_tree_ind rest)
|
adamc@35
|
1050 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1051
|
adamc@205
|
1052 ]]
|
adamc@205
|
1053
|
adam@317
|
1054 Coq rejects this definition, saying
|
adam@317
|
1055 <<
|
adam@317
|
1056 Recursive call to nat_tree_ind' has principal argument equal to "tr"
|
adam@317
|
1057 instead of rest.
|
adam@317
|
1058 >>
|
adam@317
|
1059
|
adam@317
|
1060 There is no deep theoretical reason why this program should be rejected; Coq applies incomplete termination-checking heuristics, and it is necessary to learn a few of the most important rules. The term %``%#"#nested inductive type#"#%''% hints at the solution to this particular problem. Just like true mutually inductive types require mutually recursive induction principles, nested types require nested recursion. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1061
|
adamc@35
|
1062 Fixpoint nat_tree_ind' (tr : nat_tree) : P tr :=
|
adamc@208
|
1063 match tr with
|
adamc@35
|
1064 | NLeaf' => NLeaf'_case
|
adamc@35
|
1065 | NNode' n ls => NNode'_case n ls
|
adamc@35
|
1066 ((fix list_nat_tree_ind (ls : list nat_tree) : All P ls :=
|
adamc@208
|
1067 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
1068 | Nil => I
|
adamc@35
|
1069 | Cons tr rest => conj (nat_tree_ind' tr) (list_nat_tree_ind rest)
|
adamc@35
|
1070 end) ls)
|
adamc@35
|
1071 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1072
|
adam@398
|
1073 (** We include an anonymous [fix] version of [list_nat_tree_ind] that is literally _nested_ inside the definition of the recursive function corresponding to the inductive definition that had the nested use of [list]. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1074
|
adamc@35
|
1075 End nat_tree_ind'.
|
adamc@35
|
1076
|
adamc@35
|
1077 (** We can try our induction principle out by defining some recursive functions on [nat_tree]s and proving a theorem about them. First, we define some helper functions that operate on lists. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1078
|
adamc@35
|
1079 Section map.
|
adamc@35
|
1080 Variables T T' : Set.
|
adam@317
|
1081 Variable F : T -> T'.
|
adamc@35
|
1082
|
adamc@35
|
1083 Fixpoint map (ls : list T) : list T' :=
|
adamc@35
|
1084 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
1085 | Nil => Nil
|
adam@317
|
1086 | Cons h t => Cons (F h) (map t)
|
adamc@35
|
1087 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1088 End map.
|
adamc@35
|
1089
|
adamc@35
|
1090 Fixpoint sum (ls : list nat) : nat :=
|
adamc@35
|
1091 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
1092 | Nil => O
|
adamc@35
|
1093 | Cons h t => plus h (sum t)
|
adamc@35
|
1094 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1095
|
adamc@35
|
1096 (** Now we can define a size function over our trees. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1097
|
adamc@35
|
1098 Fixpoint ntsize (tr : nat_tree) : nat :=
|
adamc@35
|
1099 match tr with
|
adamc@35
|
1100 | NLeaf' => S O
|
adamc@35
|
1101 | NNode' _ trs => S (sum (map ntsize trs))
|
adamc@35
|
1102 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1103
|
adamc@35
|
1104 (** Notice that Coq was smart enough to expand the definition of [map] to verify that we are using proper nested recursion, even through a use of a higher-order function. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1105
|
adamc@208
|
1106 Fixpoint ntsplice (tr1 tr2 : nat_tree) : nat_tree :=
|
adamc@35
|
1107 match tr1 with
|
adamc@35
|
1108 | NLeaf' => NNode' O (Cons tr2 Nil)
|
adamc@35
|
1109 | NNode' n Nil => NNode' n (Cons tr2 Nil)
|
adamc@35
|
1110 | NNode' n (Cons tr trs) => NNode' n (Cons (ntsplice tr tr2) trs)
|
adamc@35
|
1111 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1112
|
adamc@35
|
1113 (** We have defined another arbitrary notion of tree splicing, similar to before, and we can prove an analogous theorem about its relationship with tree size. We start with a useful lemma about addition. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1114
|
adamc@41
|
1115 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@35
|
1116 Lemma plus_S : forall n1 n2 : nat,
|
adamc@35
|
1117 plus n1 (S n2) = S (plus n1 n2).
|
adamc@35
|
1118 induction n1; crush.
|
adamc@35
|
1119 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
1120 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@35
|
1121
|
adamc@35
|
1122 (** Now we begin the proof of the theorem, adding the lemma [plus_S] as a hint. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1123
|
adamc@35
|
1124 Theorem ntsize_ntsplice : forall tr1 tr2 : nat_tree, ntsize (ntsplice tr1 tr2)
|
adamc@35
|
1125 = plus (ntsize tr2) (ntsize tr1).
|
adamc@41
|
1126 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@317
|
1127 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@375
|
1128 Hint Rewrite plus_S.
|
adam@317
|
1129 (* end hide *)
|
adam@375
|
1130 (** [Hint] %\coqdockw{%#<tt>#Rewrite#</tt>#%}% [plus_S.] *)
|
adamc@35
|
1131
|
adam@317
|
1132 (** We know that the standard induction principle is insufficient for the task, so we need to provide a %\index{tactics!using}%[using] clause for the [induction] tactic to specify our alternate principle. *)
|
adamc@208
|
1133
|
adamc@35
|
1134 induction tr1 using nat_tree_ind'; crush.
|
adamc@35
|
1135
|
adamc@35
|
1136 (** One subgoal remains: [[
|
adamc@35
|
1137 n : nat
|
adamc@35
|
1138 ls : list nat_tree
|
adamc@35
|
1139 H : All
|
adamc@35
|
1140 (fun tr1 : nat_tree =>
|
adamc@35
|
1141 forall tr2 : nat_tree,
|
adamc@35
|
1142 ntsize (ntsplice tr1 tr2) = plus (ntsize tr2) (ntsize tr1)) ls
|
adamc@35
|
1143 tr2 : nat_tree
|
adamc@35
|
1144 ============================
|
adamc@35
|
1145 ntsize
|
adamc@35
|
1146 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
1147 | Nil => NNode' n (Cons tr2 Nil)
|
adamc@35
|
1148 | Cons tr trs => NNode' n (Cons (ntsplice tr tr2) trs)
|
adamc@35
|
1149 end = S (plus (ntsize tr2) (sum (map ntsize ls)))
|
adamc@208
|
1150
|
adamc@35
|
1151 ]]
|
adamc@35
|
1152
|
adamc@35
|
1153 After a few moments of squinting at this goal, it becomes apparent that we need to do a case analysis on the structure of [ls]. The rest is routine. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1154
|
adamc@35
|
1155 destruct ls; crush.
|
adamc@35
|
1156
|
adam@317
|
1157 (** We can go further in automating the proof by exploiting the hint mechanism.%\index{Vernacular commands!Hint Extern}% *)
|
adamc@35
|
1158
|
adam@317
|
1159 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@35
|
1160 Restart.
|
adam@317
|
1161 (* end hide *)
|
adam@317
|
1162 (** %\hspace{-.075in}\coqdockw{%#<tt>#Restart#</tt>#%}%[.] *)
|
adam@317
|
1163
|
adamc@35
|
1164 Hint Extern 1 (ntsize (match ?LS with Nil => _ | Cons _ _ => _ end) = _) =>
|
adamc@35
|
1165 destruct LS; crush.
|
adamc@35
|
1166 induction tr1 using nat_tree_ind'; crush.
|
adamc@35
|
1167 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
1168 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@35
|
1169
|
adamc@35
|
1170 (** We will go into great detail on hints in a later chapter, but the only important thing to note here is that we register a pattern that describes a conclusion we expect to encounter during the proof. The pattern may contain unification variables, whose names are prefixed with question marks, and we may refer to those bound variables in a tactic that we ask to have run whenever the pattern matches.
|
adamc@35
|
1171
|
adam@317
|
1172 The advantage of using the hint is not very clear here, because the original proof was so short. However, the hint has fundamentally improved the readability of our proof. Before, the proof referred to the local variable [ls], which has an automatically generated name. To a human reading the proof script without stepping through it interactively, it was not clear where [ls] came from. The hint explains to the reader the process for choosing which variables to case analyze, and the hint can continue working even if the rest of the proof structure changes significantly. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1173
|
adamc@36
|
1174
|
adamc@36
|
1175 (** * Manual Proofs About Constructors *)
|
adamc@36
|
1176
|
adam@317
|
1177 (** It can be useful to understand how tactics like %\index{tactics!discriminate}%[discriminate] and %\index{tactics!injection}%[injection] work, so it is worth stepping through a manual proof of each kind. We will start with a proof fit for [discriminate]. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1178
|
adamc@36
|
1179 Theorem true_neq_false : true <> false.
|
adamc@208
|
1180
|
adamc@41
|
1181 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@317
|
1182 (** We begin with the tactic %\index{tactics!red}%[red], which is short for %``%#"#one step of reduction,#"#%''% to unfold the definition of logical negation. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1183
|
adamc@36
|
1184 red.
|
adamc@36
|
1185 (** [[
|
adamc@36
|
1186 ============================
|
adamc@36
|
1187 true = false -> False
|
adamc@208
|
1188
|
adamc@36
|
1189 ]]
|
adamc@36
|
1190
|
adam@317
|
1191 The negation is replaced with an implication of falsehood. We use the tactic %\index{tactics!intro}%[intro H] to change the assumption of the implication into a hypothesis named [H]. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1192
|
adamc@36
|
1193 intro H.
|
adamc@36
|
1194 (** [[
|
adamc@36
|
1195 H : true = false
|
adamc@36
|
1196 ============================
|
adamc@36
|
1197 False
|
adamc@208
|
1198
|
adamc@36
|
1199 ]]
|
adamc@36
|
1200
|
adamc@36
|
1201 This is the point in the proof where we apply some creativity. We define a function whose utility will become clear soon. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1202
|
adam@317
|
1203 Definition toProp (b : bool) := if b then True else False.
|
adamc@36
|
1204
|
adam@317
|
1205 (** It is worth recalling the difference between the lowercase and uppercase versions of truth and falsehood: [True] and [False] are logical propositions, while [true] and [false] are boolean values that we can case-analyze. We have defined [toProp] such that our conclusion of [False] is computationally equivalent to [toProp false]. Thus, the %\index{tactics!change}\coqdockw{%#<tt>#change#</tt>#%}% tactic will let us change the conclusion to [toProp false]. The general form %\coqdockw{%#<tt>#change#</tt>#%}% [e] replaces the conclusion with [e], whenever Coq's built-in computation rules suffice to establish the equivalence of [e] with the original conclusion. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1206
|
adam@317
|
1207 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@317
|
1208 change (toProp false).
|
adam@317
|
1209 (* end hide *)
|
adam@317
|
1210 (** %\hspace{-.075in}\coqdockw{%#<tt>#change#</tt>#%}% [(][toProp false).] *)
|
adamc@36
|
1211 (** [[
|
adamc@36
|
1212 H : true = false
|
adamc@36
|
1213 ============================
|
adam@317
|
1214 toProp false
|
adamc@208
|
1215
|
adamc@36
|
1216 ]]
|
adamc@36
|
1217
|
adam@317
|
1218 Now the righthand side of [H]'s equality appears in the conclusion, so we can rewrite, using the notation [<-] to request to replace the righthand side the equality with the lefthand side.%\index{tactics!rewrite}% *)
|
adamc@36
|
1219
|
adamc@36
|
1220 rewrite <- H.
|
adamc@36
|
1221 (** [[
|
adamc@36
|
1222 H : true = false
|
adamc@36
|
1223 ============================
|
adam@317
|
1224 toProp true
|
adamc@208
|
1225
|
adamc@36
|
1226 ]]
|
adamc@36
|
1227
|
adamc@36
|
1228 We are almost done. Just how close we are to done is revealed by computational simplification. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1229
|
adamc@36
|
1230 simpl.
|
adamc@36
|
1231 (** [[
|
adamc@36
|
1232 H : true = false
|
adamc@36
|
1233 ============================
|
adamc@36
|
1234 True
|
adamc@208
|
1235
|
adam@302
|
1236 ]]
|
adam@302
|
1237 *)
|
adamc@36
|
1238
|
adamc@36
|
1239 trivial.
|
adamc@36
|
1240 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
1241 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@36
|
1242
|
adamc@36
|
1243 (** I have no trivial automated version of this proof to suggest, beyond using [discriminate] or [congruence] in the first place.
|
adamc@36
|
1244
|
adamc@36
|
1245 %\medskip%
|
adamc@36
|
1246
|
adamc@36
|
1247 We can perform a similar manual proof of injectivity of the constructor [S]. I leave a walk-through of the details to curious readers who want to run the proof script interactively. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1248
|
adamc@36
|
1249 Theorem S_inj' : forall n m : nat, S n = S m -> n = m.
|
adamc@41
|
1250 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@36
|
1251 intros n m H.
|
adam@317
|
1252 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@36
|
1253 change (pred (S n) = pred (S m)).
|
adam@317
|
1254 (* end hide *)
|
adam@317
|
1255 (** %\hspace{-.075in}\coqdockw{%#<tt>#change#</tt>#%}% [(][pred (][S n) = pred (][S m)).] *)
|
adam@317
|
1256
|
adamc@36
|
1257 rewrite H.
|
adamc@36
|
1258 reflexivity.
|
adamc@36
|
1259 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
1260 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@36
|
1261
|
adam@317
|
1262 (** The key piece of creativity in this theorem comes in the use of the natural number predecessor function [pred]. Embodied in the implementation of %\coqdockw{%#<tt>#injectivity#</tt>#%}% is a generic recipe for writing such type-specific functions.
|
adam@317
|
1263
|
adam@317
|
1264 The examples in this section illustrate an important aspect of the design philosophy behind Coq. We could certainly design a Gallina replacement that built in rules for constructor discrimination and injectivity, but a simpler alternative is to include a few carefully chosen rules that enable the desired reasoning patterns and many others. A key benefit of this philosophy is that the complexity of proof checking is minimized, which bolsters our confidence that proved theorems are really true. *)
|