adam@297
|
1 (* Copyright (c) 2008-2011, Adam Chlipala
|
adamc@132
|
2 *
|
adamc@132
|
3 * This work is licensed under a
|
adamc@132
|
4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
|
adamc@132
|
5 * Unported License.
|
adamc@132
|
6 * The license text is available at:
|
adamc@132
|
7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
|
adamc@132
|
8 *)
|
adamc@132
|
9
|
adamc@132
|
10 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@132
|
11 Require Import List.
|
adamc@132
|
12
|
adam@314
|
13 Require Import CpdtTactics.
|
adamc@132
|
14
|
adamc@132
|
15 Set Implicit Arguments.
|
adamc@132
|
16 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@132
|
17
|
adamc@132
|
18
|
adam@324
|
19 (** %\chapter{Proof Search in Ltac}% *)
|
adamc@132
|
20
|
adamc@132
|
21 (** We have seen many examples of proof automation so far. This chapter aims to give a principled presentation of the features of Ltac, focusing in particular on the Ltac [match] construct, which supports a novel approach to backtracking search. First, though, we will run through some useful automation tactics that are built into Coq. They are described in detail in the manual, so we only outline what is possible. *)
|
adamc@132
|
22
|
adamc@132
|
23 (** * Some Built-In Automation Tactics *)
|
adamc@132
|
24
|
adamc@132
|
25 (** A number of tactics are called repeatedly by [crush]. [intuition] simplifies propositional structure of goals. [congruence] applies the rules of equality and congruence closure, plus properties of constructors of inductive types. The [omega] tactic provides a complete decision procedure for a theory that is called quantifier-free linear arithmetic or Presburger arithmetic, depending on whom you ask. That is, [omega] proves any goal that follows from looking only at parts of that goal that can be interpreted as propositional formulas whose atomic formulas are basic comparison operations on natural numbers or integers.
|
adamc@132
|
26
|
adamc@132
|
27 The [ring] tactic solves goals by appealing to the axioms of rings or semi-rings (as in algebra), depending on the type involved. Coq developments may declare new types to be parts of rings and semi-rings by proving the associated axioms. There is a simlar tactic [field] for simplifying values in fields by conversion to fractions over rings. Both [ring] and [field] can only solve goals that are equalities. The [fourier] tactic uses Fourier's method to prove inequalities over real numbers, which are axiomatized in the Coq standard library.
|
adamc@132
|
28
|
adam@288
|
29 The %\textit{%#<i>#setoid#</i>#%}% facility makes it possible to register new equivalence relations to be understood by tactics like [rewrite]. For instance, [Prop] is registered as a setoid with the equivalence relation %``%#"#if and only if.#"#%''% The ability to register new setoids can be very useful in proofs of a kind common in math, where all reasoning is done after %``%#"#modding out by a relation.#"#%''% *)
|
adamc@132
|
30
|
adamc@132
|
31
|
adamc@135
|
32 (** * Ltac Programming Basics *)
|
adamc@135
|
33
|
adamc@135
|
34 (** We have already seen many examples of Ltac programs. In the rest of this chapter, we attempt to give a more principled introduction to the important features and design patterns.
|
adamc@135
|
35
|
adamc@135
|
36 One common use for [match] tactics is identification of subjects for case analysis, as we see in this tactic definition. *)
|
adamc@135
|
37
|
adamc@141
|
38 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
39 Ltac find_if :=
|
adamc@135
|
40 match goal with
|
adamc@135
|
41 | [ |- if ?X then _ else _ ] => destruct X
|
adamc@135
|
42 end.
|
adamc@141
|
43 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
44
|
adamc@135
|
45 (** The tactic checks if the conclusion is an [if], [destruct]ing the test expression if so. Certain classes of theorem are trivial to prove automatically with such a tactic. *)
|
adamc@135
|
46
|
adamc@135
|
47 Theorem hmm : forall (a b c : bool),
|
adamc@135
|
48 if a
|
adamc@135
|
49 then if b
|
adamc@135
|
50 then True
|
adamc@135
|
51 else True
|
adamc@135
|
52 else if c
|
adamc@135
|
53 then True
|
adamc@135
|
54 else True.
|
adamc@141
|
55 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
56 intros; repeat find_if; constructor.
|
adamc@135
|
57 Qed.
|
adamc@141
|
58 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
59
|
adamc@135
|
60 (** The [repeat] that we use here is called a %\textit{%#<i>#tactical#</i>#%}%, or tactic combinator. The behavior of [repeat t] is to loop through running [t], running [t] on all generated subgoals, running [t] on %\textit{%#<i>#their#</i>#%}% generated subgoals, and so on. When [t] fails at any point in this search tree, that particular subgoal is left to be handled by later tactics. Thus, it is important never to use [repeat] with a tactic that always succeeds.
|
adamc@135
|
61
|
adamc@135
|
62 Another very useful Ltac building block is %\textit{%#<i>#context patterns#</i>#%}%. *)
|
adamc@135
|
63
|
adamc@141
|
64 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
65 Ltac find_if_inside :=
|
adamc@135
|
66 match goal with
|
adamc@135
|
67 | [ |- context[if ?X then _ else _] ] => destruct X
|
adamc@135
|
68 end.
|
adamc@141
|
69 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
70
|
adamc@135
|
71 (** The behavior of this tactic is to find any subterm of the conclusion that is an [if] and then [destruct] the test expression. This version subsumes [find_if]. *)
|
adamc@135
|
72
|
adamc@135
|
73 Theorem hmm' : forall (a b c : bool),
|
adamc@135
|
74 if a
|
adamc@135
|
75 then if b
|
adamc@135
|
76 then True
|
adamc@135
|
77 else True
|
adamc@135
|
78 else if c
|
adamc@135
|
79 then True
|
adamc@135
|
80 else True.
|
adamc@141
|
81 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
82 intros; repeat find_if_inside; constructor.
|
adamc@135
|
83 Qed.
|
adamc@141
|
84 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
85
|
adamc@135
|
86 (** We can also use [find_if_inside] to prove goals that [find_if] does not simplify sufficiently. *)
|
adamc@135
|
87
|
adamc@141
|
88 Theorem hmm2 : forall (a b : bool),
|
adamc@135
|
89 (if a then 42 else 42) = (if b then 42 else 42).
|
adamc@141
|
90 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
91 intros; repeat find_if_inside; reflexivity.
|
adamc@135
|
92 Qed.
|
adamc@141
|
93 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
94
|
adam@288
|
95 (** Many decision procedures can be coded in Ltac via %``%#"#[repeat match] loops.#"#%''% For instance, we can implement a subset of the functionality of [tauto]. *)
|
adamc@135
|
96
|
adamc@141
|
97 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
98 Ltac my_tauto :=
|
adamc@135
|
99 repeat match goal with
|
adamc@135
|
100 | [ H : ?P |- ?P ] => exact H
|
adamc@135
|
101
|
adamc@135
|
102 | [ |- True ] => constructor
|
adamc@135
|
103 | [ |- _ /\ _ ] => constructor
|
adamc@135
|
104 | [ |- _ -> _ ] => intro
|
adamc@135
|
105
|
adamc@135
|
106 | [ H : False |- _ ] => destruct H
|
adamc@135
|
107 | [ H : _ /\ _ |- _ ] => destruct H
|
adamc@135
|
108 | [ H : _ \/ _ |- _ ] => destruct H
|
adamc@135
|
109
|
adamc@135
|
110 | [ H1 : ?P -> ?Q, H2 : ?P |- _ ] =>
|
adamc@135
|
111 let H := fresh "H" in
|
adamc@135
|
112 generalize (H1 H2); clear H1; intro H
|
adamc@135
|
113 end.
|
adamc@141
|
114 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
115
|
adamc@135
|
116 (** Since [match] patterns can share unification variables between hypothesis and conclusion patterns, it is easy to figure out when the conclusion matches a hypothesis. The [exact] tactic solves a goal completely when given a proof term of the proper type.
|
adamc@135
|
117
|
adam@288
|
118 It is also trivial to implement the %``%#"#introduction rules#"#%''% for a few of the connectives. Implementing elimination rules is only a little more work, since we must give a name for a hypothesis to [destruct].
|
adamc@135
|
119
|
adamc@135
|
120 The last rule implements modus ponens. The most interesting part is the use of the Ltac-level [let] with a [fresh] expression. [fresh] takes in a name base and returns a fresh hypothesis variable based on that name. We use the new name variable [H] as the name we assign to the result of modus ponens. The use of [generalize] changes our conclusion to be an implication from [Q]. We clear the original hypothesis and move [Q] into the context with name [H]. *)
|
adamc@135
|
121
|
adamc@135
|
122 Section propositional.
|
adamc@135
|
123 Variables P Q R : Prop.
|
adamc@135
|
124
|
adamc@138
|
125 Theorem propositional : (P \/ Q \/ False) /\ (P -> Q) -> True /\ Q.
|
adamc@141
|
126 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
127 my_tauto.
|
adamc@135
|
128 Qed.
|
adamc@141
|
129 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
130 End propositional.
|
adamc@135
|
131
|
adamc@135
|
132 (** It was relatively easy to implement modus ponens, because we do not lose information by clearing every implication that we use. If we want to implement a similarly-complete procedure for quantifier instantiation, we need a way to ensure that a particular proposition is not already included among our hypotheses. To do that effectively, we first need to learn a bit more about the semantics of [match].
|
adamc@135
|
133
|
adamc@135
|
134 It is tempting to assume that [match] works like it does in ML. In fact, there are a few critical differences in its behavior. One is that we may include arbitrary expressions in patterns, instead of being restricted to variables and constructors. Another is that the same variable may appear multiple times, inducing an implicit equality constraint.
|
adamc@135
|
135
|
adamc@135
|
136 There is a related pair of two other differences that are much more important than the others. [match] has a %\textit{%#<i>#backtracking semantics for failure#</i>#%}%. In ML, pattern matching works by finding the first pattern to match and then executing its body. If the body raises an exception, then the overall match raises the same exception. In Coq, failures in case bodies instead trigger continued search through the list of cases.
|
adamc@135
|
137
|
adamc@135
|
138 For instance, this (unnecessarily verbose) proof script works: *)
|
adamc@135
|
139
|
adamc@135
|
140 Theorem m1 : True.
|
adamc@135
|
141 match goal with
|
adamc@135
|
142 | [ |- _ ] => intro
|
adamc@135
|
143 | [ |- True ] => constructor
|
adamc@135
|
144 end.
|
adamc@141
|
145 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
146 Qed.
|
adamc@141
|
147 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
148
|
adamc@135
|
149 (** The first case matches trivially, but its body tactic fails, since the conclusion does not begin with a quantifier or implication. In a similar ML match, that would mean that the whole pattern-match fails. In Coq, we backtrack and try the next pattern, which also matches. Its body tactic succeeds, so the overall tactic succeeds as well.
|
adamc@135
|
150
|
adamc@135
|
151 The example shows how failure can move to a different pattern within a [match]. Failure can also trigger an attempt to find %\textit{%#<i>#a different way of matching a single pattern#</i>#%}%. Consider another example: *)
|
adamc@135
|
152
|
adamc@135
|
153 Theorem m2 : forall P Q R : Prop, P -> Q -> R -> Q.
|
adamc@135
|
154 intros; match goal with
|
adamc@220
|
155 | [ H : _ |- _ ] => idtac H
|
adamc@135
|
156 end.
|
adamc@135
|
157
|
adam@288
|
158 (** Coq prints %``%#"#[H1]#"#%''%. By applying [idtac] with an argument, a convenient debugging tool for %``%#"#leaking information out of [match]es,#"#%''% we see that this [match] first tries binding [H] to [H1], which cannot be used to prove [Q]. Nonetheless, the following variation on the tactic succeeds at proving the goal: *)
|
adamc@135
|
159
|
adamc@141
|
160 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
161 match goal with
|
adamc@135
|
162 | [ H : _ |- _ ] => exact H
|
adamc@135
|
163 end.
|
adamc@135
|
164 Qed.
|
adamc@141
|
165 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
166
|
adamc@135
|
167 (** The tactic first unifies [H] with [H1], as before, but [exact H] fails in that case, so the tactic engine searches for more possible values of [H]. Eventually, it arrives at the correct value, so that [exact H] and the overall tactic succeed. *)
|
adamc@135
|
168
|
adamc@135
|
169 (** Now we are equipped to implement a tactic for checking that a proposition is not among our hypotheses: *)
|
adamc@135
|
170
|
adamc@141
|
171 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
172 Ltac notHyp P :=
|
adamc@135
|
173 match goal with
|
adamc@135
|
174 | [ _ : P |- _ ] => fail 1
|
adamc@135
|
175 | _ =>
|
adamc@135
|
176 match P with
|
adamc@135
|
177 | ?P1 /\ ?P2 => first [ notHyp P1 | notHyp P2 | fail 2 ]
|
adamc@135
|
178 | _ => idtac
|
adamc@135
|
179 end
|
adamc@135
|
180 end.
|
adamc@141
|
181 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
182
|
adam@288
|
183 (** We use the equality checking that is built into pattern-matching to see if there is a hypothesis that matches the proposition exactly. If so, we use the [fail] tactic. Without arguments, [fail] signals normal tactic failure, as you might expect. When [fail] is passed an argument [n], [n] is used to count outwards through the enclosing cases of backtracking search. In this case, [fail 1] says %``%#"#fail not just in this pattern-matching branch, but for the whole [match].#"#%''% The second case will never be tried when the [fail 1] is reached.
|
adamc@135
|
184
|
adamc@135
|
185 This second case, used when [P] matches no hypothesis, checks if [P] is a conjunction. Other simplifications may have split conjunctions into their component formulas, so we need to check that at least one of those components is also not represented. To achieve this, we apply the [first] tactical, which takes a list of tactics and continues down the list until one of them does not fail. The [fail 2] at the end says to [fail] both the [first] and the [match] wrapped around it.
|
adamc@135
|
186
|
adamc@135
|
187 The body of the [?P1 /\ ?P2] case guarantees that, if it is reached, we either succeed completely or fail completely. Thus, if we reach the wildcard case, [P] is not a conjunction. We use [idtac], a tactic that would be silly to apply on its own, since its effect is to succeed at doing nothing. Nonetheless, [idtac] is a useful placeholder for cases like what we see here.
|
adamc@135
|
188
|
adamc@135
|
189 With the non-presence check implemented, it is easy to build a tactic that takes as input a proof term and adds its conclusion as a new hypothesis, only if that conclusion is not already present, failing otherwise. *)
|
adamc@135
|
190
|
adamc@141
|
191 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
192 Ltac extend pf :=
|
adamc@135
|
193 let t := type of pf in
|
adamc@135
|
194 notHyp t; generalize pf; intro.
|
adamc@141
|
195 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
196
|
adamc@135
|
197 (** We see the useful [type of] operator of Ltac. This operator could not be implemented in Gallina, but it is easy to support in Ltac. We end up with [t] bound to the type of [pf]. We check that [t] is not already present. If so, we use a [generalize]/[intro] combo to add a new hypothesis proved by [pf].
|
adamc@135
|
198
|
adamc@135
|
199 With these tactics defined, we can write a tactic [completer] for adding to the context all consequences of a set of simple first-order formulas. *)
|
adamc@135
|
200
|
adamc@141
|
201 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
202 Ltac completer :=
|
adamc@135
|
203 repeat match goal with
|
adamc@135
|
204 | [ |- _ /\ _ ] => constructor
|
adamc@135
|
205 | [ H : _ /\ _ |- _ ] => destruct H
|
adamc@135
|
206 | [ H : ?P -> ?Q, H' : ?P |- _ ] =>
|
adamc@135
|
207 generalize (H H'); clear H; intro H
|
adamc@135
|
208 | [ |- forall x, _ ] => intro
|
adamc@135
|
209
|
adamc@135
|
210 | [ H : forall x, ?P x -> _, H' : ?P ?X |- _ ] =>
|
adamc@135
|
211 extend (H X H')
|
adamc@135
|
212 end.
|
adamc@141
|
213 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
214
|
adamc@135
|
215 (** We use the same kind of conjunction and implication handling as previously. Note that, since [->] is the special non-dependent case of [forall], the fourth rule handles [intro] for implications, too.
|
adamc@135
|
216
|
adamc@135
|
217 In the fifth rule, when we find a [forall] fact [H] with a premise matching one of our hypotheses, we add the appropriate instantiation of [H]'s conclusion, if we have not already added it.
|
adamc@135
|
218
|
adamc@135
|
219 We can check that [completer] is working properly: *)
|
adamc@135
|
220
|
adamc@135
|
221 Section firstorder.
|
adamc@135
|
222 Variable A : Set.
|
adamc@135
|
223 Variables P Q R S : A -> Prop.
|
adamc@135
|
224
|
adamc@135
|
225 Hypothesis H1 : forall x, P x -> Q x /\ R x.
|
adamc@135
|
226 Hypothesis H2 : forall x, R x -> S x.
|
adamc@135
|
227
|
adamc@135
|
228 Theorem fo : forall x, P x -> S x.
|
adamc@141
|
229 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
230 completer.
|
adamc@135
|
231 (** [[
|
adamc@135
|
232 x : A
|
adamc@135
|
233 H : P x
|
adamc@135
|
234 H0 : Q x
|
adamc@135
|
235 H3 : R x
|
adamc@135
|
236 H4 : S x
|
adamc@135
|
237 ============================
|
adamc@135
|
238 S x
|
adam@302
|
239 ]]
|
adam@302
|
240 *)
|
adamc@135
|
241
|
adamc@135
|
242 assumption.
|
adamc@135
|
243 Qed.
|
adamc@141
|
244 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
245 End firstorder.
|
adamc@135
|
246
|
adamc@135
|
247 (** We narrowly avoided a subtle pitfall in our definition of [completer]. Let us try another definition that even seems preferable to the original, to the untrained eye. *)
|
adamc@135
|
248
|
adamc@141
|
249 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
250 Ltac completer' :=
|
adamc@135
|
251 repeat match goal with
|
adamc@135
|
252 | [ |- _ /\ _ ] => constructor
|
adamc@135
|
253 | [ H : _ /\ _ |- _ ] => destruct H
|
adamc@135
|
254 | [ H : ?P -> _, H' : ?P |- _ ] =>
|
adamc@135
|
255 generalize (H H'); clear H; intro H
|
adamc@135
|
256 | [ |- forall x, _ ] => intro
|
adamc@135
|
257
|
adamc@135
|
258 | [ H : forall x, ?P x -> _, H' : ?P ?X |- _ ] =>
|
adamc@135
|
259 extend (H X H')
|
adamc@135
|
260 end.
|
adamc@141
|
261 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
262
|
adamc@135
|
263 (** The only difference is in the modus ponens rule, where we have replaced an unused unification variable [?Q] with a wildcard. Let us try our example again with this version: *)
|
adamc@135
|
264
|
adamc@135
|
265 Section firstorder'.
|
adamc@135
|
266 Variable A : Set.
|
adamc@135
|
267 Variables P Q R S : A -> Prop.
|
adamc@135
|
268
|
adamc@135
|
269 Hypothesis H1 : forall x, P x -> Q x /\ R x.
|
adamc@135
|
270 Hypothesis H2 : forall x, R x -> S x.
|
adamc@135
|
271
|
adamc@135
|
272 Theorem fo' : forall x, P x -> S x.
|
adamc@141
|
273 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
274 (** [[
|
adamc@135
|
275 completer'.
|
adamc@220
|
276
|
adamc@205
|
277 ]]
|
adamc@205
|
278
|
adamc@135
|
279 Coq loops forever at this point. What went wrong? *)
|
adamc@220
|
280
|
adamc@135
|
281 Abort.
|
adamc@141
|
282 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@135
|
283 End firstorder'.
|
adamc@136
|
284
|
adamc@136
|
285 (** A few examples should illustrate the issue. Here we see a [match]-based proof that works fine: *)
|
adamc@136
|
286
|
adamc@136
|
287 Theorem t1 : forall x : nat, x = x.
|
adamc@136
|
288 match goal with
|
adamc@136
|
289 | [ |- forall x, _ ] => trivial
|
adamc@136
|
290 end.
|
adamc@141
|
291 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@136
|
292 Qed.
|
adamc@141
|
293 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@136
|
294
|
adamc@136
|
295 (** This one fails. *)
|
adamc@136
|
296
|
adamc@141
|
297 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@136
|
298 Theorem t1' : forall x : nat, x = x.
|
adamc@136
|
299 (** [[
|
adamc@136
|
300 match goal with
|
adamc@136
|
301 | [ |- forall x, ?P ] => trivial
|
adamc@136
|
302 end.
|
adamc@136
|
303
|
adamc@136
|
304 User error: No matching clauses for match goal
|
adam@302
|
305 ]]
|
adam@302
|
306 *)
|
adamc@220
|
307
|
adamc@136
|
308 Abort.
|
adamc@141
|
309 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@136
|
310
|
adam@288
|
311 (** The problem is that unification variables may not contain locally-bound variables. In this case, [?P] would need to be bound to [x = x], which contains the local quantified variable [x]. By using a wildcard in the earlier version, we avoided this restriction. To understand why this applies to the [completer] tactics, recall that, in Coq, implication is shorthand for degenerate universal quantification where the quantified variable is not used. Nonetheless, in an Ltac pattern, Coq is happy to match a wildcard implication against a universal quantification.
|
adamc@136
|
312
|
adam@288
|
313 The Coq 8.2 release includes a special pattern form for a unification variable with an explicit set of free variables. That unification variable is then bound to a function from the free variables to the %``%#"#real#"#%''% value. In Coq 8.1 and earlier, there is no such workaround.
|
adamc@136
|
314
|
adam@288
|
315 No matter which version you use, it is important to be aware of this restriction. As we have alluded to, the restriction is the culprit behind the infinite-looping behavior of [completer']. We unintentionally match quantified facts with the modus ponens rule, circumventing the %``%#"#already present#"#%''% check and leading to different behavior, where the same fact may be added to the context repeatedly in an infinite loop. Our earlier [completer] tactic uses a modus ponens rule that matches the implication conclusion with a variable, which blocks matching against non-trivial universal quantifiers. *)
|
adamc@137
|
316
|
adamc@137
|
317
|
adamc@137
|
318 (** * Functional Programming in Ltac *)
|
adamc@137
|
319
|
adamc@141
|
320 (* EX: Write a list length function in Ltac. *)
|
adamc@141
|
321
|
adamc@137
|
322 (** Ltac supports quite convenient functional programming, with a Lisp-with-syntax kind of flavor. However, there are a few syntactic conventions involved in getting programs to be accepted. The Ltac syntax is optimized for tactic-writing, so one has to deal with some inconveniences in writing more standard functional programs.
|
adamc@137
|
323
|
adamc@137
|
324 To illustrate, let us try to write a simple list length function. We start out writing it just like in Gallina, simply replacing [Fixpoint] (and its annotations) with [Ltac].
|
adamc@137
|
325
|
adamc@137
|
326 [[
|
adamc@137
|
327 Ltac length ls :=
|
adamc@137
|
328 match ls with
|
adamc@137
|
329 | nil => O
|
adamc@137
|
330 | _ :: ls' => S (length ls')
|
adamc@137
|
331 end.
|
adamc@137
|
332
|
adamc@137
|
333 Error: The reference ls' was not found in the current environment
|
adamc@220
|
334
|
adamc@137
|
335 ]]
|
adamc@137
|
336
|
adamc@137
|
337 At this point, we hopefully remember that pattern variable names must be prefixed by question marks in Ltac.
|
adamc@137
|
338
|
adamc@137
|
339 [[
|
adamc@137
|
340 Ltac length ls :=
|
adamc@137
|
341 match ls with
|
adamc@137
|
342 | nil => O
|
adamc@137
|
343 | _ :: ?ls' => S (length ls')
|
adamc@137
|
344 end.
|
adamc@137
|
345
|
adamc@137
|
346 Error: The reference S was not found in the current environment
|
adamc@220
|
347
|
adamc@137
|
348 ]]
|
adamc@137
|
349
|
adam@288
|
350 The problem is that Ltac treats the expression [S (length ls')] as an invocation of a tactic [S] with argument [length ls']. We need to use a special annotation to %``%#"#escape into#"#%''% the Gallina parsing nonterminal. *)
|
adamc@137
|
351
|
adamc@141
|
352 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@137
|
353 Ltac length ls :=
|
adamc@137
|
354 match ls with
|
adamc@137
|
355 | nil => O
|
adamc@137
|
356 | _ :: ?ls' => constr:(S (length ls'))
|
adamc@137
|
357 end.
|
adamc@137
|
358
|
adamc@137
|
359 (** This definition is accepted. It can be a little awkward to test Ltac definitions like this. Here is one method. *)
|
adamc@137
|
360
|
adamc@137
|
361 Goal False.
|
adamc@137
|
362 let n := length (1 :: 2 :: 3 :: nil) in
|
adamc@137
|
363 pose n.
|
adamc@137
|
364 (** [[
|
adamc@137
|
365 n := S (length (2 :: 3 :: nil)) : nat
|
adamc@137
|
366 ============================
|
adamc@137
|
367 False
|
adamc@220
|
368
|
adamc@137
|
369 ]]
|
adamc@137
|
370
|
adam@301
|
371 We use the [pose] tactic, which extends the proof context with a new variable that is set equal to a particular term. We could also have used [idtac n] in place of [pose n], which would have printed the result without changing the context.
|
adamc@220
|
372
|
adamc@220
|
373 [n] only has the length calculation unrolled one step. What has happened here is that, by escaping into the [constr] nonterminal, we referred to the [length] function of Gallina, rather than the [length] Ltac function that we are defining. *)
|
adamc@220
|
374
|
adamc@220
|
375 Abort.
|
adamc@137
|
376
|
adamc@137
|
377 Reset length.
|
adamc@137
|
378
|
adamc@137
|
379 (** The thing to remember is that Gallina terms built by tactics must be bound explicitly via [let] or a similar technique, rather than inserting Ltac calls directly in other Gallina terms. *)
|
adamc@137
|
380
|
adamc@137
|
381 Ltac length ls :=
|
adamc@137
|
382 match ls with
|
adamc@137
|
383 | nil => O
|
adamc@137
|
384 | _ :: ?ls' =>
|
adamc@137
|
385 let ls'' := length ls' in
|
adamc@137
|
386 constr:(S ls'')
|
adamc@137
|
387 end.
|
adamc@137
|
388
|
adamc@137
|
389 Goal False.
|
adamc@137
|
390 let n := length (1 :: 2 :: 3 :: nil) in
|
adamc@137
|
391 pose n.
|
adamc@137
|
392 (** [[
|
adamc@137
|
393 n := 3 : nat
|
adamc@137
|
394 ============================
|
adamc@137
|
395 False
|
adam@302
|
396 ]]
|
adam@302
|
397 *)
|
adamc@220
|
398
|
adamc@137
|
399 Abort.
|
adamc@141
|
400 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@141
|
401
|
adamc@141
|
402 (* EX: Write a list map function in Ltac. *)
|
adamc@137
|
403
|
adamc@137
|
404 (** We can also use anonymous function expressions and local function definitions in Ltac, as this example of a standard list [map] function shows. *)
|
adamc@137
|
405
|
adamc@141
|
406 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@137
|
407 Ltac map T f :=
|
adamc@137
|
408 let rec map' ls :=
|
adamc@137
|
409 match ls with
|
adam@288
|
410 | nil => constr:( @nil T)
|
adamc@137
|
411 | ?x :: ?ls' =>
|
adamc@137
|
412 let x' := f x in
|
adamc@137
|
413 let ls'' := map' ls' in
|
adam@288
|
414 constr:( x' :: ls'')
|
adamc@137
|
415 end in
|
adamc@137
|
416 map'.
|
adamc@137
|
417
|
adam@288
|
418 (** Ltac functions can have no implicit arguments. It may seem surprising that we need to pass [T], the carried type of the output list, explicitly. We cannot just use [type of f], because [f] is an Ltac term, not a Gallina term, and Ltac programs are dynamically typed. [f] could use very syntactic methods to decide to return differently typed terms for different inputs. We also could not replace [constr:( @nil T)] with [constr: nil], because we have no strongly-typed context to use to infer the parameter to [nil]. Luckily, we do have sufficient context within [constr:( x' :: ls'')].
|
adamc@137
|
419
|
adam@288
|
420 Sometimes we need to employ the opposite direction of %``%#"#nonterminal escape,#"#%''% when we want to pass a complicated tactic expression as an argument to another tactic, as we might want to do in invoking [map]. *)
|
adamc@137
|
421
|
adamc@137
|
422 Goal False.
|
adam@288
|
423 let ls := map (nat * nat)%type ltac:(fun x => constr:( x, x)) (1 :: 2 :: 3 :: nil) in
|
adamc@137
|
424 pose ls.
|
adamc@137
|
425 (** [[
|
adamc@137
|
426 l := (1, 1) :: (2, 2) :: (3, 3) :: nil : list (nat * nat)
|
adamc@137
|
427 ============================
|
adamc@137
|
428 False
|
adam@302
|
429 ]]
|
adam@302
|
430 *)
|
adamc@220
|
431
|
adamc@137
|
432 Abort.
|
adamc@141
|
433 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@137
|
434
|
adamc@138
|
435
|
adamc@139
|
436 (** * Recursive Proof Search *)
|
adamc@139
|
437
|
adamc@139
|
438 (** Deciding how to instantiate quantifiers is one of the hardest parts of automated first-order theorem proving. For a given problem, we can consider all possible bounded-length sequences of quantifier instantiations, applying only propositional reasoning at the end. This is probably a bad idea for almost all goals, but it makes for a nice example of recursive proof search procedures in Ltac.
|
adamc@139
|
439
|
adam@288
|
440 We can consider the maximum %``%#"#dependency chain#"#%''% length for a first-order proof. We define the chain length for a hypothesis to be 0, and the chain length for an instantiation of a quantified fact to be one greater than the length for that fact. The tactic [inster n] is meant to try all possible proofs with chain length at most [n]. *)
|
adamc@139
|
441
|
adamc@141
|
442 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@139
|
443 Ltac inster n :=
|
adamc@139
|
444 intuition;
|
adamc@139
|
445 match n with
|
adamc@139
|
446 | S ?n' =>
|
adamc@139
|
447 match goal with
|
adamc@139
|
448 | [ H : forall x : ?T, _, x : ?T |- _ ] => generalize (H x); inster n'
|
adamc@139
|
449 end
|
adamc@139
|
450 end.
|
adamc@141
|
451 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@139
|
452
|
adamc@139
|
453 (** [inster] begins by applying propositional simplification. Next, it checks if any chain length remains. If so, it tries all possible ways of instantiating quantified hypotheses with properly-typed local variables. It is critical to realize that, if the recursive call [inster n'] fails, then the [match goal] just seeks out another way of unifying its pattern against proof state. Thus, this small amount of code provides an elegant demonstration of how backtracking [match] enables exhaustive search.
|
adamc@139
|
454
|
adamc@139
|
455 We can verify the efficacy of [inster] with two short examples. The built-in [firstorder] tactic (with no extra arguments) is able to prove the first but not the second. *)
|
adamc@139
|
456
|
adamc@139
|
457 Section test_inster.
|
adamc@139
|
458 Variable A : Set.
|
adamc@139
|
459 Variables P Q : A -> Prop.
|
adamc@139
|
460 Variable f : A -> A.
|
adamc@139
|
461 Variable g : A -> A -> A.
|
adamc@139
|
462
|
adamc@139
|
463 Hypothesis H1 : forall x y, P (g x y) -> Q (f x).
|
adamc@139
|
464
|
adamc@139
|
465 Theorem test_inster : forall x y, P (g x y) -> Q (f x).
|
adamc@220
|
466 inster 2.
|
adamc@139
|
467 Qed.
|
adamc@139
|
468
|
adamc@139
|
469 Hypothesis H3 : forall u v, P u /\ P v /\ u <> v -> P (g u v).
|
adamc@139
|
470 Hypothesis H4 : forall u, Q (f u) -> P u /\ P (f u).
|
adamc@139
|
471
|
adamc@139
|
472 Theorem test_inster2 : forall x y, x <> y -> P x -> Q (f y) -> Q (f x).
|
adamc@220
|
473 inster 3.
|
adamc@139
|
474 Qed.
|
adamc@139
|
475 End test_inster.
|
adamc@139
|
476
|
adam@288
|
477 (** The style employed in the definition of [inster] can seem very counterintuitive to functional programmers. Usually, functional programs accumulate state changes in explicit arguments to recursive functions. In Ltac, the state of the current subgoal is always implicit. Nonetheless, in contrast to general imperative programming, it is easy to undo any changes to this state, and indeed such %``%#"#undoing#"#%''% happens automatically at failures within [match]es. In this way, Ltac programming is similar to programming in Haskell with a stateful failure monad that supports a composition operator along the lines of the [first] tactical.
|
adamc@140
|
478
|
adam@288
|
479 Functional programming purists may react indignantly to the suggestion of programming this way. Nonetheless, as with other kinds of %``%#"#monadic programming,#"#%''% many problems are much simpler to solve with Ltac than they would be with explicit, pure proof manipulation in ML or Haskell. To demonstrate, we will write a basic simplification procedure for logical implications.
|
adamc@140
|
480
|
adam@288
|
481 This procedure is inspired by one for separation logic, where conjuncts in formulas are thought of as %``%#"#resources,#"#%''% such that we lose no completeness by %``%#"#crossing out#"#%''% equal conjuncts on the two sides of an implication. This process is complicated by the fact that, for reasons of modularity, our formulas can have arbitrary nested tree structure (branching at conjunctions) and may include existential quantifiers. It is helpful for the matching process to %``%#"#go under#"#%''% quantifiers and in fact decide how to instantiate existential quantifiers in the conclusion.
|
adamc@140
|
482
|
adam@288
|
483 To distinguish the implications that our tactic handles from the implications that will show up as %``%#"#plumbing#"#%''% in various lemmas, we define a wrapper definition, a notation, and a tactic. *)
|
adamc@138
|
484
|
adamc@138
|
485 Definition imp (P1 P2 : Prop) := P1 -> P2.
|
adamc@140
|
486 Infix "-->" := imp (no associativity, at level 95).
|
adamc@140
|
487 Ltac imp := unfold imp; firstorder.
|
adamc@138
|
488
|
adamc@140
|
489 (** These lemmas about [imp] will be useful in the tactic that we will write. *)
|
adamc@138
|
490
|
adamc@138
|
491 Theorem and_True_prem : forall P Q,
|
adamc@138
|
492 (P /\ True --> Q)
|
adamc@138
|
493 -> (P --> Q).
|
adamc@138
|
494 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
495 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
496
|
adamc@138
|
497 Theorem and_True_conc : forall P Q,
|
adamc@138
|
498 (P --> Q /\ True)
|
adamc@138
|
499 -> (P --> Q).
|
adamc@138
|
500 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
501 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
502
|
adamc@138
|
503 Theorem assoc_prem1 : forall P Q R S,
|
adamc@138
|
504 (P /\ (Q /\ R) --> S)
|
adamc@138
|
505 -> ((P /\ Q) /\ R --> S).
|
adamc@138
|
506 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
507 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
508
|
adamc@138
|
509 Theorem assoc_prem2 : forall P Q R S,
|
adamc@138
|
510 (Q /\ (P /\ R) --> S)
|
adamc@138
|
511 -> ((P /\ Q) /\ R --> S).
|
adamc@138
|
512 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
513 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
514
|
adamc@138
|
515 Theorem comm_prem : forall P Q R,
|
adamc@138
|
516 (P /\ Q --> R)
|
adamc@138
|
517 -> (Q /\ P --> R).
|
adamc@138
|
518 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
519 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
520
|
adamc@138
|
521 Theorem assoc_conc1 : forall P Q R S,
|
adamc@138
|
522 (S --> P /\ (Q /\ R))
|
adamc@138
|
523 -> (S --> (P /\ Q) /\ R).
|
adamc@138
|
524 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
525 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
526
|
adamc@138
|
527 Theorem assoc_conc2 : forall P Q R S,
|
adamc@138
|
528 (S --> Q /\ (P /\ R))
|
adamc@138
|
529 -> (S --> (P /\ Q) /\ R).
|
adamc@138
|
530 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
531 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
532
|
adamc@138
|
533 Theorem comm_conc : forall P Q R,
|
adamc@138
|
534 (R --> P /\ Q)
|
adamc@138
|
535 -> (R --> Q /\ P).
|
adamc@138
|
536 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
537 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
538
|
adam@288
|
539 (** The first order of business in crafting our [matcher] tactic will be auxiliary support for searching through formula trees. The [search_prem] tactic implements running its tactic argument [tac] on every subformula of an [imp] premise. As it traverses a tree, [search_prem] applies some of the above lemmas to rewrite the goal to bring different subformulas to the head of the goal. That is, for every subformula [P] of the implication premise, we want [P] to %``%#"#have a turn,#"#%''% where the premise is rearranged into the form [P /\ Q] for some [Q]. The tactic [tac] should expect to see a goal in this form and focus its attention on the first conjunct of the premise. *)
|
adamc@140
|
540
|
adamc@141
|
541 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@138
|
542 Ltac search_prem tac :=
|
adamc@138
|
543 let rec search P :=
|
adamc@138
|
544 tac
|
adamc@138
|
545 || (apply and_True_prem; tac)
|
adamc@138
|
546 || match P with
|
adamc@138
|
547 | ?P1 /\ ?P2 =>
|
adamc@138
|
548 (apply assoc_prem1; search P1)
|
adamc@138
|
549 || (apply assoc_prem2; search P2)
|
adamc@138
|
550 end
|
adamc@138
|
551 in match goal with
|
adamc@138
|
552 | [ |- ?P /\ _ --> _ ] => search P
|
adamc@138
|
553 | [ |- _ /\ ?P --> _ ] => apply comm_prem; search P
|
adamc@138
|
554 | [ |- _ --> _ ] => progress (tac || (apply and_True_prem; tac))
|
adamc@138
|
555 end.
|
adamc@138
|
556
|
adamc@140
|
557 (** To understand how [search_prem] works, we turn first to the final [match]. If the premise begins with a conjunction, we call the [search] procedure on each of the conjuncts, or only the first conjunct, if that already yields a case where [tac] does not fail. [search P] expects and maintains the invariant that the premise is of the form [P /\ Q] for some [Q]. We pass [P] explicitly as a kind of decreasing induction measure, to avoid looping forever when [tac] always fails. The second [match] case calls a commutativity lemma to realize this invariant, before passing control to [search]. The final [match] case tries applying [tac] directly and then, if that fails, changes the form of the goal by adding an extraneous [True] conjunct and calls [tac] again.
|
adamc@140
|
558
|
adamc@140
|
559 [search] itself tries the same tricks as in the last case of the final [match]. Additionally, if neither works, it checks if [P] is a conjunction. If so, it calls itself recursively on each conjunct, first applying associativity lemmas to maintain the goal-form invariant.
|
adamc@140
|
560
|
adamc@140
|
561 We will also want a dual function [search_conc], which does tree search through an [imp] conclusion. *)
|
adamc@140
|
562
|
adamc@138
|
563 Ltac search_conc tac :=
|
adamc@138
|
564 let rec search P :=
|
adamc@138
|
565 tac
|
adamc@138
|
566 || (apply and_True_conc; tac)
|
adamc@138
|
567 || match P with
|
adamc@138
|
568 | ?P1 /\ ?P2 =>
|
adamc@138
|
569 (apply assoc_conc1; search P1)
|
adamc@138
|
570 || (apply assoc_conc2; search P2)
|
adamc@138
|
571 end
|
adamc@138
|
572 in match goal with
|
adamc@138
|
573 | [ |- _ --> ?P /\ _ ] => search P
|
adamc@138
|
574 | [ |- _ --> _ /\ ?P ] => apply comm_conc; search P
|
adamc@138
|
575 | [ |- _ --> _ ] => progress (tac || (apply and_True_conc; tac))
|
adamc@138
|
576 end.
|
adamc@138
|
577
|
adamc@140
|
578 (** Now we can prove a number of lemmas that are suitable for application by our search tactics. A lemma that is meant to handle a premise should have the form [P /\ Q --> R] for some interesting [P], and a lemma that is meant to handle a conclusion should have the form [P --> Q /\ R] for some interesting [Q]. *)
|
adamc@140
|
579
|
adamc@138
|
580 Theorem False_prem : forall P Q,
|
adamc@138
|
581 False /\ P --> Q.
|
adamc@138
|
582 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
583 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
584
|
adamc@138
|
585 Theorem True_conc : forall P Q : Prop,
|
adamc@138
|
586 (P --> Q)
|
adamc@138
|
587 -> (P --> True /\ Q).
|
adamc@138
|
588 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
589 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
590
|
adamc@138
|
591 Theorem Match : forall P Q R : Prop,
|
adamc@138
|
592 (Q --> R)
|
adamc@138
|
593 -> (P /\ Q --> P /\ R).
|
adamc@138
|
594 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
595 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
596
|
adamc@138
|
597 Theorem ex_prem : forall (T : Type) (P : T -> Prop) (Q R : Prop),
|
adamc@138
|
598 (forall x, P x /\ Q --> R)
|
adamc@138
|
599 -> (ex P /\ Q --> R).
|
adamc@138
|
600 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
601 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
602
|
adamc@138
|
603 Theorem ex_conc : forall (T : Type) (P : T -> Prop) (Q R : Prop) x,
|
adamc@138
|
604 (Q --> P x /\ R)
|
adamc@138
|
605 -> (Q --> ex P /\ R).
|
adamc@138
|
606 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
607 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
608
|
adam@288
|
609 (** We will also want a %``%#"#base case#"#%''% lemma for finishing proofs where cancelation has removed every constituent of the conclusion. *)
|
adamc@140
|
610
|
adamc@138
|
611 Theorem imp_True : forall P,
|
adamc@138
|
612 P --> True.
|
adamc@138
|
613 imp.
|
adamc@138
|
614 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
615
|
adamc@220
|
616 (** Our final [matcher] tactic is now straightforward. First, we [intros] all variables into scope. Then we attempt simple premise simplifications, finishing the proof upon finding [False] and eliminating any existential quantifiers that we find. After that, we search through the conclusion. We remove [True] conjuncts, remove existential quantifiers by introducing unification variables for their bound variables, and search for matching premises to cancel. Finally, when no more progress is made, we see if the goal has become trivial and can be solved by [imp_True]. In each case, we use the tactic [simple apply] in place of [apply] to use a simpler, less expensive unification algorithm. *)
|
adamc@140
|
617
|
adamc@138
|
618 Ltac matcher :=
|
adamc@138
|
619 intros;
|
adam@288
|
620 repeat search_prem ltac:( simple apply False_prem || ( simple apply ex_prem; intro));
|
adam@288
|
621 repeat search_conc ltac:( simple apply True_conc || simple eapply ex_conc
|
adam@288
|
622 || search_prem ltac:( simple apply Match));
|
adamc@204
|
623 try simple apply imp_True.
|
adamc@141
|
624 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@140
|
625
|
adamc@140
|
626 (** Our tactic succeeds at proving a simple example. *)
|
adamc@138
|
627
|
adamc@138
|
628 Theorem t2 : forall P Q : Prop,
|
adamc@138
|
629 Q /\ (P /\ False) /\ P --> P /\ Q.
|
adamc@138
|
630 matcher.
|
adamc@138
|
631 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
632
|
adamc@140
|
633 (** In the generated proof, we find a trace of the workings of the search tactics. *)
|
adamc@140
|
634
|
adamc@140
|
635 Print t2.
|
adamc@220
|
636 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@140
|
637 t2 =
|
adamc@140
|
638 fun P Q : Prop =>
|
adamc@140
|
639 comm_prem (assoc_prem1 (assoc_prem2 (False_prem (P:=P /\ P /\ Q) (P /\ Q))))
|
adamc@140
|
640 : forall P Q : Prop, Q /\ (P /\ False) /\ P --> P /\ Q
|
adamc@220
|
641
|
adamc@220
|
642 ]]
|
adamc@140
|
643
|
adamc@220
|
644 We can also see that [matcher] is well-suited for cases where some human intervention is needed after the automation finishes. *)
|
adamc@140
|
645
|
adamc@138
|
646 Theorem t3 : forall P Q R : Prop,
|
adamc@138
|
647 P /\ Q --> Q /\ R /\ P.
|
adamc@138
|
648 matcher.
|
adamc@140
|
649 (** [[
|
adamc@140
|
650 ============================
|
adamc@140
|
651 True --> R
|
adamc@220
|
652
|
adamc@140
|
653 ]]
|
adamc@140
|
654
|
adamc@140
|
655 [matcher] canceled those conjuncts that it was able to cancel, leaving a simplified subgoal for us, much as [intuition] does. *)
|
adamc@220
|
656
|
adamc@138
|
657 Abort.
|
adamc@138
|
658
|
adamc@140
|
659 (** [matcher] even succeeds at guessing quantifier instantiations. It is the unification that occurs in uses of the [Match] lemma that does the real work here. *)
|
adamc@140
|
660
|
adamc@138
|
661 Theorem t4 : forall (P : nat -> Prop) Q, (exists x, P x /\ Q) --> Q /\ (exists x, P x).
|
adamc@138
|
662 matcher.
|
adamc@138
|
663 Qed.
|
adamc@138
|
664
|
adamc@140
|
665 Print t4.
|
adamc@220
|
666 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@140
|
667 t4 =
|
adamc@140
|
668 fun (P : nat -> Prop) (Q : Prop) =>
|
adamc@140
|
669 and_True_prem
|
adamc@140
|
670 (ex_prem (P:=fun x : nat => P x /\ Q)
|
adamc@140
|
671 (fun x : nat =>
|
adamc@140
|
672 assoc_prem2
|
adamc@140
|
673 (Match (P:=Q)
|
adamc@140
|
674 (and_True_conc
|
adamc@140
|
675 (ex_conc (fun x0 : nat => P x0) x
|
adamc@140
|
676 (Match (P:=P x) (imp_True (P:=True))))))))
|
adamc@140
|
677 : forall (P : nat -> Prop) (Q : Prop),
|
adamc@140
|
678 (exists x : nat, P x /\ Q) --> Q /\ (exists x : nat, P x)
|
adam@302
|
679 ]]
|
adam@302
|
680 *)
|
adamc@234
|
681
|
adamc@234
|
682
|
adamc@234
|
683 (** * Creating Unification Variables *)
|
adamc@234
|
684
|
adamc@234
|
685 (** A final useful ingredient in tactic crafting is the ability to allocate new unification variables explicitly. Tactics like [eauto] introduce unification variable internally to support flexible proof search. While [eauto] and its relatives do %\textit{%#<i>#backward#</i>#%}% reasoning, we often want to do similar %\textit{%#<i>#forward#</i>#%}% reasoning, where unification variables can be useful for similar reasons.
|
adamc@234
|
686
|
adamc@234
|
687 For example, we can write a tactic that instantiates the quantifiers of a universally-quantified hypothesis. The tactic should not need to know what the appropriate instantiantiations are; rather, we want these choices filled with placeholders. We hope that, when we apply the specialized hypothesis later, syntactic unification will determine concrete values.
|
adamc@234
|
688
|
adamc@234
|
689 Before we are ready to write a tactic, we can try out its ingredients one at a time. *)
|
adamc@234
|
690
|
adamc@234
|
691 Theorem t5 : (forall x : nat, S x > x) -> 2 > 1.
|
adamc@234
|
692 intros.
|
adamc@234
|
693
|
adamc@234
|
694 (** [[
|
adamc@234
|
695 H : forall x : nat, S x > x
|
adamc@234
|
696 ============================
|
adamc@234
|
697 2 > 1
|
adamc@234
|
698
|
adamc@234
|
699 ]]
|
adamc@234
|
700
|
adamc@234
|
701 To instantiate [H] generically, we first need to name the value to be used for [x]. *)
|
adamc@234
|
702
|
adamc@234
|
703 evar (y : nat).
|
adamc@234
|
704
|
adamc@234
|
705 (** [[
|
adamc@234
|
706 H : forall x : nat, S x > x
|
adamc@234
|
707 y := ?279 : nat
|
adamc@234
|
708 ============================
|
adamc@234
|
709 2 > 1
|
adamc@234
|
710
|
adamc@234
|
711 ]]
|
adamc@234
|
712
|
adamc@234
|
713 The proof context is extended with a new variable [y], which has been assigned to be equal to a fresh unification variable [?279]. We want to instantiate [H] with [?279]. To get ahold of the new unification variable, rather than just its alias [y], we perform a trivial call-by-value reduction in the expression [y]. In particular, we only request the use of one reduction rule, [delta], which deals with definition unfolding. We pass a flag further stipulating that only the definition of [y] be unfolded. This is a simple trick for getting at the value of a synonym variable. *)
|
adamc@234
|
714
|
adamc@234
|
715 let y' := eval cbv delta [y] in y in
|
adamc@234
|
716 clear y; generalize (H y').
|
adamc@234
|
717
|
adamc@234
|
718 (** [[
|
adamc@234
|
719 H : forall x : nat, S x > x
|
adamc@234
|
720 ============================
|
adamc@234
|
721 S ?279 > ?279 -> 2 > 1
|
adamc@234
|
722
|
adamc@234
|
723 ]]
|
adamc@234
|
724
|
adamc@234
|
725 Our instantiation was successful. We can finish by using the refined formula to replace the original. *)
|
adamc@234
|
726
|
adamc@234
|
727 clear H; intro H.
|
adamc@234
|
728
|
adamc@234
|
729 (** [[
|
adamc@234
|
730 H : S ?281 > ?281
|
adamc@234
|
731 ============================
|
adamc@234
|
732 2 > 1
|
adamc@234
|
733
|
adamc@234
|
734 ]]
|
adamc@234
|
735
|
adamc@234
|
736 We can finish the proof by using [apply]'s unification to figure out the proper value of [?281]. (The original unification variable was replaced by another, as often happens in the internals of the various tactics' implementations.) *)
|
adamc@234
|
737
|
adamc@234
|
738 apply H.
|
adamc@234
|
739 Qed.
|
adamc@234
|
740
|
adamc@234
|
741 (** Now we can write a tactic that encapsulates the pattern we just employed, instantiating all quantifiers of a particular hypothesis. *)
|
adamc@234
|
742
|
adamc@234
|
743 Ltac insterU H :=
|
adamc@234
|
744 repeat match type of H with
|
adamc@234
|
745 | forall x : ?T, _ =>
|
adamc@234
|
746 let x := fresh "x" in
|
adamc@234
|
747 evar (x : T);
|
adamc@234
|
748 let x' := eval cbv delta [x] in x in
|
adamc@234
|
749 clear x; generalize (H x'); clear H; intro H
|
adamc@234
|
750 end.
|
adamc@234
|
751
|
adamc@234
|
752 Theorem t5' : (forall x : nat, S x > x) -> 2 > 1.
|
adamc@234
|
753 intro H; insterU H; apply H.
|
adamc@234
|
754 Qed.
|
adamc@234
|
755
|
adamc@234
|
756 (** This particular example is somewhat silly, since [apply] by itself would have solved the goal originally. Separate forward reasoning is more useful on hypotheses that end in existential quantifications. Before we go through an example, it is useful to define a variant of [insterU] that does not clear the base hypothesis we pass to it. *)
|
adamc@234
|
757
|
adamc@234
|
758 Ltac insterKeep H :=
|
adamc@234
|
759 let H' := fresh "H'" in
|
adamc@234
|
760 generalize H; intro H'; insterU H'.
|
adamc@234
|
761
|
adamc@234
|
762 Section t6.
|
adamc@234
|
763 Variables A B : Type.
|
adamc@234
|
764 Variable P : A -> B -> Prop.
|
adamc@234
|
765 Variable f : A -> A -> A.
|
adamc@234
|
766 Variable g : B -> B -> B.
|
adamc@234
|
767
|
adamc@234
|
768 Hypothesis H1 : forall v, exists u, P v u.
|
adamc@234
|
769 Hypothesis H2 : forall v1 u1 v2 u2,
|
adamc@234
|
770 P v1 u1
|
adamc@234
|
771 -> P v2 u2
|
adamc@234
|
772 -> P (f v1 v2) (g u1 u2).
|
adamc@234
|
773
|
adamc@234
|
774 Theorem t6 : forall v1 v2, exists u1, exists u2, P (f v1 v2) (g u1 u2).
|
adamc@234
|
775 intros.
|
adamc@234
|
776
|
adamc@234
|
777 (** Neither [eauto] nor [firstorder] is clever enough to prove this goal. We can help out by doing some of the work with quantifiers ourselves. *)
|
adamc@234
|
778
|
adamc@234
|
779 do 2 insterKeep H1.
|
adamc@234
|
780
|
adamc@234
|
781 (** Our proof state is extended with two generic instances of [H1].
|
adamc@234
|
782
|
adamc@234
|
783 [[
|
adamc@234
|
784 H' : exists u : B, P ?4289 u
|
adamc@234
|
785 H'0 : exists u : B, P ?4288 u
|
adamc@234
|
786 ============================
|
adamc@234
|
787 exists u1 : B, exists u2 : B, P (f v1 v2) (g u1 u2)
|
adamc@234
|
788
|
adamc@234
|
789 ]]
|
adamc@234
|
790
|
adamc@234
|
791 [eauto] still cannot prove the goal, so we eliminate the two new existential quantifiers. *)
|
adamc@234
|
792
|
adamc@234
|
793 repeat match goal with
|
adamc@234
|
794 | [ H : ex _ |- _ ] => destruct H
|
adamc@234
|
795 end.
|
adamc@234
|
796
|
adamc@234
|
797 (** Now the goal is simple enough to solve by logic programming. *)
|
adamc@234
|
798
|
adamc@234
|
799 eauto.
|
adamc@234
|
800 Qed.
|
adamc@234
|
801 End t6.
|
adamc@234
|
802
|
adamc@234
|
803 (** Our [insterU] tactic does not fare so well with quantified hypotheses that also contain implications. We can see the problem in a slight modification of the last example. We introduce a new unary predicate [Q] and use it to state an additional requirement of our hypothesis [H1]. *)
|
adamc@234
|
804
|
adamc@234
|
805 Section t7.
|
adamc@234
|
806 Variables A B : Type.
|
adamc@234
|
807 Variable Q : A -> Prop.
|
adamc@234
|
808 Variable P : A -> B -> Prop.
|
adamc@234
|
809 Variable f : A -> A -> A.
|
adamc@234
|
810 Variable g : B -> B -> B.
|
adamc@234
|
811
|
adamc@234
|
812 Hypothesis H1 : forall v, Q v -> exists u, P v u.
|
adamc@234
|
813 Hypothesis H2 : forall v1 u1 v2 u2,
|
adamc@234
|
814 P v1 u1
|
adamc@234
|
815 -> P v2 u2
|
adamc@234
|
816 -> P (f v1 v2) (g u1 u2).
|
adamc@234
|
817
|
adam@297
|
818 Theorem t7 : forall v1 v2, Q v1 -> Q v2 -> exists u1, exists u2, P (f v1 v2) (g u1 u2).
|
adamc@234
|
819 intros; do 2 insterKeep H1;
|
adamc@234
|
820 repeat match goal with
|
adamc@234
|
821 | [ H : ex _ |- _ ] => destruct H
|
adamc@234
|
822 end; eauto.
|
adamc@234
|
823
|
adamc@234
|
824 (** This proof script does not hit any errors until the very end, when an error message like this one is displayed.
|
adamc@234
|
825
|
adamc@234
|
826 [[
|
adamc@234
|
827 No more subgoals but non-instantiated existential variables :
|
adamc@234
|
828 Existential 1 =
|
adamc@234
|
829 ?4384 : [A : Type
|
adamc@234
|
830 B : Type
|
adamc@234
|
831 Q : A -> Prop
|
adamc@234
|
832 P : A -> B -> Prop
|
adamc@234
|
833 f : A -> A -> A
|
adamc@234
|
834 g : B -> B -> B
|
adamc@234
|
835 H1 : forall v : A, Q v -> exists u : B, P v u
|
adamc@234
|
836 H2 : forall (v1 : A) (u1 : B) (v2 : A) (u2 : B),
|
adamc@234
|
837 P v1 u1 -> P v2 u2 -> P (f v1 v2) (g u1 u2)
|
adamc@234
|
838 v1 : A
|
adamc@234
|
839 v2 : A
|
adamc@234
|
840 H : Q v1
|
adamc@234
|
841 H0 : Q v2
|
adamc@234
|
842 H' : Q v2 -> exists u : B, P v2 u |- Q v2]
|
adamc@234
|
843
|
adamc@234
|
844 ]]
|
adamc@234
|
845
|
adam@288
|
846 There is another similar line about a different existential variable. Here, %``%#"#existential variable#"#%''% means what we have also called %``%#"#unification variable.#"#%''% In the course of the proof, some unification variable [?4384] was introduced but never unified. Unification variables are just a device to structure proof search; the language of Gallina proof terms does not include them. Thus, we cannot produce a proof term without instantiating the variable.
|
adamc@234
|
847
|
adamc@234
|
848 The error message shows that [?4384] is meant to be a proof of [Q v2] in a particular proof state, whose variables and hypotheses are displayed. It turns out that [?4384] was created by [insterU], as the value of a proof to pass to [H1]. Recall that, in Gallina, implication is just a degenerate case of [forall] quantification, so the [insterU] code to match against [forall] also matched the implication. Since any proof of [Q v2] is as good as any other in this context, there was never any opportunity to use unification to determine exactly which proof is appropriate. We expect similar problems with any implications in arguments to [insterU]. *)
|
adamc@234
|
849
|
adamc@234
|
850 Abort.
|
adamc@234
|
851 End t7.
|
adamc@234
|
852
|
adamc@234
|
853 Reset insterU.
|
adamc@234
|
854
|
adamc@234
|
855 (** We can redefine [insterU] to treat implications differently. In particular, we pattern-match on the type of the type [T] in [forall x : ?T, ...]. If [T] has type [Prop], then [x]'s instantiation should be thought of as a proof. Thus, instead of picking a new unification variable for it, we instead apply a user-supplied tactic [tac]. It is important that we end this special [Prop] case with [|| fail 1], so that, if [tac] fails to prove [T], we abort the instantiation, rather than continuing on to the default quantifier handling. *)
|
adamc@234
|
856
|
adamc@234
|
857 Ltac insterU tac H :=
|
adamc@234
|
858 repeat match type of H with
|
adamc@234
|
859 | forall x : ?T, _ =>
|
adamc@234
|
860 match type of T with
|
adamc@234
|
861 | Prop =>
|
adamc@234
|
862 (let H' := fresh "H'" in
|
adamc@234
|
863 assert (H' : T); [
|
adamc@234
|
864 solve [ tac ]
|
adamc@234
|
865 | generalize (H H'); clear H H'; intro H ])
|
adamc@234
|
866 || fail 1
|
adamc@234
|
867 | _ =>
|
adamc@234
|
868 let x := fresh "x" in
|
adamc@234
|
869 evar (x : T);
|
adamc@234
|
870 let x' := eval cbv delta [x] in x in
|
adamc@234
|
871 clear x; generalize (H x'); clear H; intro H
|
adamc@234
|
872 end
|
adamc@234
|
873 end.
|
adamc@234
|
874
|
adamc@234
|
875 Ltac insterKeep tac H :=
|
adamc@234
|
876 let H' := fresh "H'" in
|
adamc@234
|
877 generalize H; intro H'; insterU tac H'.
|
adamc@234
|
878
|
adamc@234
|
879 Section t7.
|
adamc@234
|
880 Variables A B : Type.
|
adamc@234
|
881 Variable Q : A -> Prop.
|
adamc@234
|
882 Variable P : A -> B -> Prop.
|
adamc@234
|
883 Variable f : A -> A -> A.
|
adamc@234
|
884 Variable g : B -> B -> B.
|
adamc@234
|
885
|
adamc@234
|
886 Hypothesis H1 : forall v, Q v -> exists u, P v u.
|
adamc@234
|
887 Hypothesis H2 : forall v1 u1 v2 u2,
|
adamc@234
|
888 P v1 u1
|
adamc@234
|
889 -> P v2 u2
|
adamc@234
|
890 -> P (f v1 v2) (g u1 u2).
|
adamc@234
|
891
|
adamc@234
|
892 Theorem t6 : forall v1 v2, Q v1 -> Q v2 -> exists u1, exists u2, P (f v1 v2) (g u1 u2).
|
adamc@234
|
893
|
adamc@234
|
894 (** We can prove the goal by calling [insterKeep] with a tactic that tries to find and apply a [Q] hypothesis over a variable about which we do not yet know any [P] facts. We need to begin this tactic code with [idtac; ] to get around a strange limitation in Coq's proof engine, where a first-class tactic argument may not begin with a [match]. *)
|
adamc@234
|
895
|
adamc@234
|
896 intros; do 2 insterKeep ltac:(idtac; match goal with
|
adamc@234
|
897 | [ H : Q ?v |- _ ] =>
|
adamc@234
|
898 match goal with
|
adamc@234
|
899 | [ _ : context[P v _] |- _ ] => fail 1
|
adamc@234
|
900 | _ => apply H
|
adamc@234
|
901 end
|
adamc@234
|
902 end) H1;
|
adamc@234
|
903 repeat match goal with
|
adamc@234
|
904 | [ H : ex _ |- _ ] => destruct H
|
adamc@234
|
905 end; eauto.
|
adamc@234
|
906 Qed.
|
adamc@234
|
907 End t7.
|
adamc@234
|
908
|
adamc@234
|
909 (** It is often useful to instantiate existential variables explicitly. A built-in tactic provides one way of doing so. *)
|
adamc@234
|
910
|
adamc@234
|
911 Theorem t8 : exists p : nat * nat, fst p = 3.
|
adamc@234
|
912 econstructor; instantiate (1 := (3, 2)); reflexivity.
|
adamc@234
|
913 Qed.
|
adamc@234
|
914
|
adamc@234
|
915 (** The [1] above is identifying an existential variable appearing in the current goal, with the last existential appearing assigned number 1, the second last assigned number 2, and so on. The named existential is replaced everywhere by the term to the right of the [:=].
|
adamc@234
|
916
|
adamc@234
|
917 The [instantiate] tactic can be convenient for exploratory proving, but it leads to very brittle proof scripts that are unlikely to adapt to changing theorem statements. It is often more helpful to have a tactic that can be used to assign a value to a term that is known to be an existential. By employing a roundabout implementation technique, we can build a tactic that generalizes this functionality. In particular, our tactic [equate] will assert that two terms are equal. If one of the terms happens to be an existential, then it will be replaced everywhere with the other term. *)
|
adamc@234
|
918
|
adamc@234
|
919 Ltac equate x y :=
|
adamc@234
|
920 let H := fresh "H" in
|
adamc@234
|
921 assert (H : x = y); [ reflexivity | clear H ].
|
adamc@234
|
922
|
adamc@234
|
923 (** [equate] fails if it is not possible to prove [x = y] by [reflexivity]. We perform the proof only for its unification side effects, clearing the fact [x = y] afterward. With [equate], we can build a less brittle version of the prior example. *)
|
adamc@234
|
924
|
adamc@234
|
925 Theorem t9 : exists p : nat * nat, fst p = 3.
|
adamc@234
|
926 econstructor; match goal with
|
adamc@234
|
927 | [ |- fst ?x = 3 ] => equate x (3, 2)
|
adamc@234
|
928 end; reflexivity.
|
adamc@234
|
929 Qed.
|