annotate src/Predicates.v @ 566:1a231194d164

Two new courses
author Adam Chlipala <adam@chlipala.net>
date Fri, 19 Oct 2018 10:27:35 -0400
parents ed829eaa91b2
children
rev   line source
adam@534 1 (* Copyright (c) 2008-2012, 2015, Adam Chlipala
adamc@45 2 *
adamc@45 3 * This work is licensed under a
adamc@45 4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
adamc@45 5 * Unported License.
adamc@45 6 * The license text is available at:
adamc@45 7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
adamc@45 8 *)
adamc@45 9
adamc@45 10 (* begin hide *)
adamc@45 11 Require Import List.
adamc@45 12
adam@534 13 Require Import Cpdt.CpdtTactics.
adamc@45 14
adamc@45 15 Set Implicit Arguments.
adam@534 16 Set Asymmetric Patterns.
adam@322 17
adam@322 18 (* Extra definitions to get coqdoc to choose the right fonts. *)
adam@322 19
adam@323 20 (* begin thide *)
adam@322 21 Inductive unit := tt.
adam@322 22 Inductive Empty_set := .
adam@322 23 Inductive bool := true | false.
adam@322 24 Inductive sum := .
adam@322 25 Inductive prod := .
adam@322 26 Inductive and := conj.
adam@322 27 Inductive or := or_introl | or_intror.
adam@322 28 Inductive ex := ex_intro.
adam@426 29 Inductive eq := eq_refl.
adam@322 30 Reset unit.
adam@323 31 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 32 (* end hide *)
adamc@45 33
adamc@45 34 (** %\chapter{Inductive Predicates}% *)
adamc@45 35
adam@322 36 (** The so-called %\index{Curry-Howard correspondence}``%#"#Curry-Howard correspondence#"#%''~\cite{Curry,Howard}% states a formal connection between functional programs and mathematical proofs. In the last chapter, we snuck in a first introduction to this subject in Coq. Witness the close similarity between the types [unit] and [True] from the standard library: *)
adamc@45 37
adamc@45 38 Print unit.
adam@440 39 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adamc@209 40 Inductive unit : Set := tt : unit
adam@302 41 ]]
adam@302 42 *)
adamc@45 43
adamc@45 44 Print True.
adam@440 45 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adamc@209 46 Inductive True : Prop := I : True
adam@322 47 ]]
adamc@45 48
adam@442 49 Recall that [unit] is the type with only one value, and [True] is the proposition that always holds. Despite this superficial difference between the two concepts, in both cases we can use the same inductive definition mechanism. The connection goes further than this. We see that we arrive at the definition of [True] by replacing [unit] by [True], [tt] by [I], and [Set] by [Prop]. The first two of these differences are superficial changes of names, while the third difference is the crucial one for separating programs from proofs. A term [T] of type [Set] is a type of programs, and a term of type [T] is a program. A term [T] of type [Prop] is a logical proposition, and its proofs are of type [T]. Chapter 12 goes into more detail about the theoretical differences between [Prop] and [Set]. For now, we will simply follow common intuitions about what a proof is.
adamc@45 50
adam@475 51 The type [unit] has one value, [tt]. The type [True] has one proof, [I]. Why distinguish between these two types? Many people who have read about Curry-Howard in an abstract context but who have not put it to use in proof engineering answer that the two types in fact _should not_ be distinguished. There is a certain aesthetic appeal to this point of view, but I want to argue that it is best to treat Curry-Howard very loosely in practical proving. There are Coq-specific reasons for preferring the distinction, involving efficient compilation and avoidance of paradoxes in the presence of classical math, but I will argue that there is a more general principle that should lead us to avoid conflating programming and proving.
adamc@45 52
adam@401 53 The essence of the argument is roughly this: to an engineer, not all functions of type [A -> B] are created equal, but all proofs of a proposition [P -> Q] are. This idea is known as%\index{proof irrelevance}% _proof irrelevance_, and its formalizations in logics prevent us from distinguishing between alternate proofs of the same proposition. Proof irrelevance is compatible with, but not derivable in, Gallina. Apart from this theoretical concern, I will argue that it is most effective to do engineering with Coq by employing different techniques for programs versus proofs. Most of this book is organized around that distinction, describing how to program, by applying standard functional programming techniques in the presence of dependent types; and how to prove, by writing custom Ltac decision procedures.
adamc@45 54
adam@421 55 With that perspective in mind, this chapter is sort of a mirror image of the last chapter, introducing how to define predicates with inductive definitions. We will point out similarities in places, but much of the effective Coq user's bag of tricks is disjoint for predicates versus "datatypes." This chapter is also a covert introduction to dependent types, which are the foundation on which interesting inductive predicates are built, though we will rely on tactics to build dependently typed proof terms for us for now. A future chapter introduces more manual application of dependent types. *)
adamc@45 56
adamc@45 57
adamc@48 58 (** * Propositional Logic *)
adamc@45 59
adam@471 60 (** Let us begin with a brief tour through the definitions of the connectives for propositional logic. We will work within a Coq section that provides us with a set of propositional variables. In Coq parlance, these are just variables of type [Prop]. *)
adamc@45 61
adamc@45 62 Section Propositional.
adamc@46 63 Variables P Q R : Prop.
adamc@45 64
adamc@45 65 (** In Coq, the most basic propositional connective is implication, written [->], which we have already used in almost every proof. Rather than being defined inductively, implication is built into Coq as the function type constructor.
adamc@45 66
adamc@45 67 We have also already seen the definition of [True]. For a demonstration of a lower-level way of establishing proofs of inductive predicates, we turn to this trivial theorem. *)
adamc@45 68
adamc@45 69 Theorem obvious : True.
adamc@55 70 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 71 apply I.
adamc@55 72 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 73 Qed.
adamc@45 74
adam@401 75 (** We may always use the [apply] tactic to take a proof step based on applying a particular constructor of the inductive predicate that we are trying to establish. Sometimes there is only one constructor that could possibly apply, in which case a shortcut is available:%\index{tactics!constructor}% *)
adamc@45 76
adamc@55 77 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 78 Theorem obvious' : True.
adamc@45 79 constructor.
adamc@45 80 Qed.
adamc@45 81
adamc@55 82 (* end thide *)
adamc@55 83
adamc@45 84 (** There is also a predicate [False], which is the Curry-Howard mirror image of [Empty_set] from the last chapter. *)
adamc@45 85
adamc@45 86 Print False.
adam@440 87 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adamc@209 88 Inductive False : Prop :=
adamc@209 89 ]]
adamc@45 90
adam@442 91 We can conclude anything from [False], doing case analysis on a proof of [False] in the same way we might do case analysis on, say, a natural number. Since there are no cases to consider, any such case analysis succeeds immediately in proving the goal. *)
adamc@45 92
adamc@45 93 Theorem False_imp : False -> 2 + 2 = 5.
adamc@55 94 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 95 destruct 1.
adamc@55 96 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 97 Qed.
adamc@45 98
adam@449 99 (** In a consistent context, we can never build a proof of [False]. In inconsistent contexts that appear in the courses of proofs, it is usually easiest to proceed by demonstrating the inconsistency with an explicit proof of [False]. *)
adamc@45 100
adamc@45 101 Theorem arith_neq : 2 + 2 = 5 -> 9 + 9 = 835.
adamc@55 102 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 103 intro.
adamc@45 104
adam@471 105 (** At this point, we have an inconsistent hypothesis [2 + 2 = 5], so the specific conclusion is not important. We use the %\index{tactics!elimtype}%[elimtype] tactic. For a full description of it, see the Coq manual. For our purposes, we only need the variant [elimtype False], which lets us replace any conclusion formula with [False], because any fact follows from an inconsistent context. *)
adamc@45 106
adamc@45 107 elimtype False.
adamc@45 108 (** [[
adamc@45 109 H : 2 + 2 = 5
adamc@45 110 ============================
adamc@45 111 False
adamc@209 112
adamc@209 113 ]]
adamc@45 114
adamc@209 115 For now, we will leave the details of this proof about arithmetic to [crush]. *)
adamc@45 116
adamc@45 117 crush.
adamc@55 118 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 119 Qed.
adamc@45 120
adamc@45 121 (** A related notion to [False] is logical negation. *)
adamc@45 122
adam@421 123 (* begin hide *)
adam@421 124 Definition foo := not.
adam@421 125 (* end hide *)
adam@421 126
adamc@45 127 Print not.
adamc@209 128 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@209 129 not = fun A : Prop => A -> False
adamc@209 130 : Prop -> Prop
adamc@209 131 ]]
adamc@45 132
adam@488 133 We see that [not] is just shorthand for implication of [False]. We can use that fact explicitly in proofs. The syntax [~ P] %(written with a tilde in ASCII)% expands to [not P]. *)
adamc@45 134
adamc@45 135 Theorem arith_neq' : ~ (2 + 2 = 5).
adamc@55 136 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 137 unfold not.
adamc@45 138 (** [[
adamc@45 139 ============================
adamc@45 140 2 + 2 = 5 -> False
adam@302 141 ]]
adam@302 142 *)
adamc@45 143
adamc@45 144 crush.
adamc@55 145 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 146 Qed.
adamc@45 147
adamc@45 148 (** We also have conjunction, which we introduced in the last chapter. *)
adamc@45 149
adamc@45 150 Print and.
adam@440 151 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adam@322 152 Inductive and (A : Prop) (B : Prop) : Prop := conj : A -> B -> A /\ B
adamc@209 153 ]]
adamc@209 154
adam@442 155 The interested reader can check that [and] has a Curry-Howard equivalent called %\index{Gallina terms!prod}%[prod], the type of pairs. However, it is generally most convenient to reason about conjunction using tactics. An explicit proof of commutativity of [and] illustrates the usual suspects for such tasks. The operator [/\] is an infix shorthand for [and]. *)
adamc@45 156
adamc@45 157 Theorem and_comm : P /\ Q -> Q /\ P.
adamc@209 158
adamc@55 159 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 160 (** We start by case analysis on the proof of [P /\ Q]. *)
adamc@45 161
adamc@45 162 destruct 1.
adamc@45 163 (** [[
adamc@45 164 H : P
adamc@45 165 H0 : Q
adamc@45 166 ============================
adamc@45 167 Q /\ P
adamc@209 168
adamc@209 169 ]]
adamc@45 170
adam@322 171 Every proof of a conjunction provides proofs for both conjuncts, so we get a single subgoal reflecting that. We can proceed by splitting this subgoal into a case for each conjunct of [Q /\ P].%\index{tactics!split}% *)
adamc@45 172
adamc@45 173 split.
adam@440 174 (** [[
adam@440 175 2 subgoals
adamc@45 176
adamc@45 177 H : P
adamc@45 178 H0 : Q
adamc@45 179 ============================
adamc@45 180 Q
adam@439 181
adam@439 182 subgoal 2 is
adam@439 183
adam@322 184 P
adamc@209 185
adamc@209 186 ]]
adamc@45 187
adam@322 188 In each case, the conclusion is among our hypotheses, so the %\index{tactics!assumption}%[assumption] tactic finishes the process. *)
adamc@45 189
adamc@45 190 assumption.
adamc@45 191 assumption.
adamc@55 192 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 193 Qed.
adamc@45 194
adam@322 195 (** Coq disjunction is called %\index{Gallina terms!or}%[or] and abbreviated with the infix operator [\/]. *)
adamc@45 196
adamc@45 197 Print or.
adam@440 198 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adamc@209 199 Inductive or (A : Prop) (B : Prop) : Prop :=
adamc@209 200 or_introl : A -> A \/ B | or_intror : B -> A \/ B
adamc@209 201 ]]
adamc@45 202
adam@449 203 We see that there are two ways to prove a disjunction: prove the first disjunct or prove the second. The Curry-Howard analogue of this is the Coq %\index{Gallina terms!sum}%[sum] type. We can demonstrate the main tactics here with another proof of commutativity. *)
adamc@45 204
adamc@45 205 Theorem or_comm : P \/ Q -> Q \/ P.
adamc@55 206
adamc@55 207 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 208 (** As in the proof for [and], we begin with case analysis, though this time we are met by two cases instead of one. *)
adamc@209 209
adamc@45 210 destruct 1.
adam@439 211 (** [[
adam@439 212 2 subgoals
adamc@45 213
adamc@45 214 H : P
adamc@45 215 ============================
adamc@45 216 Q \/ P
adam@439 217
adam@439 218 subgoal 2 is
adam@439 219
adamc@45 220 Q \/ P
adamc@209 221
adamc@209 222 ]]
adamc@45 223
adam@401 224 We can see that, in the first subgoal, we want to prove the disjunction by proving its second disjunct. The %\index{tactics!right}%[right] tactic telegraphs this intent. *)
adam@322 225
adamc@45 226 right; assumption.
adamc@45 227
adam@322 228 (** The second subgoal has a symmetric proof.%\index{tactics!left}%
adamc@45 229
adamc@45 230 [[
adamc@45 231 1 subgoal
adamc@45 232
adamc@45 233 H : Q
adamc@45 234 ============================
adamc@45 235 Q \/ P
adam@302 236 ]]
adam@302 237 *)
adamc@45 238
adamc@45 239 left; assumption.
adam@322 240
adamc@55 241 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 242 Qed.
adamc@45 243
adamc@46 244
adamc@46 245 (* begin hide *)
adamc@46 246 (* In-class exercises *)
adamc@46 247
adamc@46 248 Theorem contra : P -> ~P -> R.
adamc@52 249 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 250 unfold not.
adamc@52 251 intros.
adamc@52 252 elimtype False.
adamc@52 253 apply H0.
adamc@52 254 assumption.
adamc@52 255 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 256 Admitted.
adamc@46 257
adamc@46 258 Theorem and_assoc : (P /\ Q) /\ R -> P /\ (Q /\ R).
adamc@52 259 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 260 intros.
adamc@52 261 destruct H.
adamc@52 262 destruct H.
adamc@52 263 split.
adamc@52 264 assumption.
adamc@52 265 split.
adamc@52 266 assumption.
adamc@52 267 assumption.
adamc@52 268 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 269 Admitted.
adamc@46 270
adamc@46 271 Theorem or_assoc : (P \/ Q) \/ R -> P \/ (Q \/ R).
adamc@52 272 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 273 intros.
adamc@52 274 destruct H.
adamc@52 275 destruct H.
adamc@52 276 left.
adamc@52 277 assumption.
adamc@52 278 right.
adamc@52 279 left.
adamc@52 280 assumption.
adamc@52 281 right.
adamc@52 282 right.
adamc@52 283 assumption.
adamc@52 284 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 285 Admitted.
adamc@46 286
adamc@46 287 (* end hide *)
adamc@46 288
adamc@46 289
adam@421 290 (** It would be a shame to have to plod manually through all proofs about propositional logic. Luckily, there is no need. One of the most basic Coq automation tactics is %\index{tactics!tauto}%[tauto], which is a complete decision procedure for constructive propositional logic. (More on what "constructive" means in the next section.) We can use [tauto] to dispatch all of the purely propositional theorems we have proved so far. *)
adamc@46 291
adamc@46 292 Theorem or_comm' : P \/ Q -> Q \/ P.
adamc@55 293 (* begin thide *)
adamc@46 294 tauto.
adamc@55 295 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 296 Qed.
adamc@46 297
adam@471 298 (** Sometimes propositional reasoning forms important plumbing for the proof of a theorem, but we still need to apply some other smarts about, say, arithmetic. The tactic %\index{tactics!intuition}%[intuition] is a generalization of [tauto] that proves everything it can using propositional reasoning. When some further facts must be established to finish the proof, [intuition] uses propositional laws to simplify them as far as possible. Consider this example, which uses the list concatenation operator %\coqdocnotation{%#<tt>#++#</tt>#%}% from the standard library. *)
adamc@46 299
adamc@46 300 Theorem arith_comm : forall ls1 ls2 : list nat,
adamc@46 301 length ls1 = length ls2 \/ length ls1 + length ls2 = 6
adamc@46 302 -> length (ls1 ++ ls2) = 6 \/ length ls1 = length ls2.
adamc@55 303 (* begin thide *)
adamc@46 304 intuition.
adamc@46 305
adamc@46 306 (** A lot of the proof structure has been generated for us by [intuition], but the final proof depends on a fact about lists. The remaining subgoal hints at what cleverness we need to inject. *)
adamc@46 307
adamc@46 308 (** [[
adamc@46 309 ls1 : list nat
adamc@46 310 ls2 : list nat
adamc@46 311 H0 : length ls1 + length ls2 = 6
adamc@46 312 ============================
adamc@46 313 length (ls1 ++ ls2) = 6 \/ length ls1 = length ls2
adamc@209 314
adamc@209 315 ]]
adamc@46 316
adamc@209 317 We can see that we need a theorem about lengths of concatenated lists, which we proved last chapter and is also in the standard library. *)
adamc@46 318
adamc@46 319 rewrite app_length.
adamc@46 320 (** [[
adamc@46 321 ls1 : list nat
adamc@46 322 ls2 : list nat
adamc@46 323 H0 : length ls1 + length ls2 = 6
adamc@46 324 ============================
adamc@46 325 length ls1 + length ls2 = 6 \/ length ls1 = length ls2
adamc@209 326
adamc@209 327 ]]
adamc@46 328
adamc@209 329 Now the subgoal follows by purely propositional reasoning. That is, we could replace [length ls1 + length ls2 = 6] with [P] and [length ls1 = length ls2] with [Q] and arrive at a tautology of propositional logic. *)
adamc@46 330
adamc@46 331 tauto.
adamc@55 332 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 333 Qed.
adamc@46 334
adam@322 335 (** The [intuition] tactic is one of the main bits of glue in the implementation of [crush], so, with a little help, we can get a short automated proof of the theorem. *)
adamc@46 336
adamc@55 337 (* begin thide *)
adamc@46 338 Theorem arith_comm' : forall ls1 ls2 : list nat,
adamc@46 339 length ls1 = length ls2 \/ length ls1 + length ls2 = 6
adamc@46 340 -> length (ls1 ++ ls2) = 6 \/ length ls1 = length ls2.
adam@375 341 Hint Rewrite app_length.
adamc@46 342
adamc@46 343 crush.
adamc@46 344 Qed.
adamc@55 345 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 346
adamc@45 347 End Propositional.
adamc@45 348
adam@322 349 (** Ending the section here has the same effect as always. Each of our propositional theorems becomes universally quantified over the propositional variables that we used. *)
adam@322 350
adamc@46 351
adamc@47 352 (** * What Does It Mean to Be Constructive? *)
adamc@46 353
adam@471 354 (** One potential point of confusion in the presentation so far is the distinction between [bool] and [Prop]. The datatype [bool] is built from two values [true] and [false], while [Prop] is a more primitive type that includes among its members [True] and [False]. Why not collapse these two concepts into one, and why must there be more than two states of mathematical truth, [True] and [False]?
adamc@46 355
adam@421 356 The answer comes from the fact that Coq implements%\index{constructive logic}% _constructive_ or%\index{intuitionistic logic|see{constructive logic}}% _intuitionistic_ logic, in contrast to the%\index{classical logic}% _classical_ logic that you may be more familiar with. In constructive logic, classical tautologies like [~ ~ P -> P] and [P \/ ~ P] do not always hold. In general, we can only prove these tautologies when [P] is%\index{decidability}% _decidable_, in the sense of %\index{computability|see{decidability}}%computability theory. The Curry-Howard encoding that Coq uses for [or] allows us to extract either a proof of [P] or a proof of [~ P] from any proof of [P \/ ~ P]. Since our proofs are just functional programs which we can run, a general %\index{law of the excluded middle}%law of the excluded middle would give us a decision procedure for the halting problem, where the instantiations of [P] would be formulas like "this particular Turing machine halts."
adamc@47 357
adam@471 358 A similar paradoxical situation would result if every proposition evaluated to either [True] or [False]. Evaluation in Coq is decidable, so we would be limiting ourselves to decidable propositions only.
adam@471 359
adam@421 360 Hence the distinction between [bool] and [Prop]. Programs of type [bool] are computational by construction; we can always run them to determine their results. Many [Prop]s are undecidable, and so we can write more expressive formulas with [Prop]s than with [bool]s, but the inevitable consequence is that we cannot simply "run a [Prop] to determine its truth."
adamc@47 361
adam@401 362 Constructive logic lets us define all of the logical connectives in an aesthetically appealing way, with orthogonal inductive definitions. That is, each connective is defined independently using a simple, shared mechanism. Constructivity also enables a trick called%\index{program extraction}% _program extraction_, where we write programs by phrasing them as theorems to be proved. Since our proofs are just functional programs, we can extract executable programs from our final proofs, which we could not do as naturally with classical proofs.
adamc@47 363
adamc@47 364 We will see more about Coq's program extraction facility in a later chapter. However, I think it is worth interjecting another warning at this point, following up on the prior warning about taking the Curry-Howard correspondence too literally. It is possible to write programs by theorem-proving methods in Coq, but hardly anyone does it. It is almost always most useful to maintain the distinction between programs and proofs. If you write a program by proving a theorem, you are likely to run into algorithmic inefficiencies that you introduced in your proof to make it easier to prove. It is a shame to have to worry about such situations while proving tricky theorems, and it is a happy state of affairs that you almost certainly will not need to, with the ideal of extracting programs from proofs being confined mostly to theoretical studies. *)
adamc@48 365
adamc@48 366
adamc@48 367 (** * First-Order Logic *)
adamc@48 368
adam@421 369 (** The %\index{Gallina terms!forall}%[forall] connective of first-order logic, which we have seen in many examples so far, is built into Coq. Getting ahead of ourselves a bit, we can see it as the dependent function type constructor. In fact, implication and universal quantification are just different syntactic shorthands for the same Coq mechanism. A formula [P -> Q] is equivalent to [forall x : P, Q], where [x] does not appear in [Q]. That is, the "real" type of the implication says "for every proof of [P], there exists a proof of [Q]."
adamc@48 370
adam@322 371 %\index{existential quantification}\index{Gallina terms!exists}\index{Gallina terms!ex}%Existential quantification is defined in the standard library. *)
adamc@48 372
adam@322 373 Print ex.
adam@440 374 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adamc@209 375 Inductive ex (A : Type) (P : A -> Prop) : Prop :=
adamc@209 376 ex_intro : forall x : A, P x -> ex P
adamc@209 377 ]]
adamc@48 378
adam@469 379 (Note that here, as always, each [forall] quantifier has the largest possible scope, so that the type of [ex_intro] could also be written [forall x : A, (P x -> ex P)].)
adam@469 380
adam@471 381 The family [ex] is parameterized by the type [A] that we quantify over, and by a predicate [P] over [A]s. We prove an existential by exhibiting some [x] of type [A], along with a proof of [P x]. As usual, there are tactics that save us from worrying about the low-level details most of the time.
adam@471 382
adam@471 383 Here is an example of a theorem statement with existential quantification. We use the equality operator [=], which, depending on the settings in which they learned logic, different people will say either is or is not part of first-order logic. For our purposes, it is. *)
adamc@48 384
adamc@48 385 Theorem exist1 : exists x : nat, x + 1 = 2.
adamc@55 386 (* begin thide *)
adamc@67 387 (** remove printing exists *)
adam@470 388 (** We can start this proof with a tactic %\index{tactics!exists}%[exists], which should not be confused with the formula constructor shorthand of the same name. %In the version of this document that you are reading, the reverse ``E'' appears instead of the text ``exists'' in formulas.% *)
adamc@209 389
adamc@48 390 exists 1.
adamc@48 391
adamc@209 392 (** The conclusion is replaced with a version using the existential witness that we announced.
adamc@48 393
adamc@209 394 [[
adamc@48 395 ============================
adamc@48 396 1 + 1 = 2
adam@302 397 ]]
adam@302 398 *)
adamc@48 399
adamc@48 400 reflexivity.
adamc@55 401 (* end thide *)
adamc@48 402 Qed.
adamc@48 403
adamc@48 404 (** printing exists $\exists$ *)
adamc@48 405
adamc@48 406 (** We can also use tactics to reason about existential hypotheses. *)
adamc@48 407
adamc@48 408 Theorem exist2 : forall n m : nat, (exists x : nat, n + x = m) -> n <= m.
adamc@55 409 (* begin thide *)
adamc@48 410 (** We start by case analysis on the proof of the existential fact. *)
adamc@209 411
adamc@48 412 destruct 1.
adamc@48 413 (** [[
adamc@48 414 n : nat
adamc@48 415 m : nat
adamc@48 416 x : nat
adamc@48 417 H : n + x = m
adamc@48 418 ============================
adamc@48 419 n <= m
adamc@209 420
adamc@209 421 ]]
adamc@48 422
adamc@209 423 The goal has been replaced by a form where there is a new free variable [x], and where we have a new hypothesis that the body of the existential holds with [x] substituted for the old bound variable. From here, the proof is just about arithmetic and is easy to automate. *)
adamc@48 424
adamc@48 425 crush.
adamc@55 426 (* end thide *)
adamc@48 427 Qed.
adamc@48 428
adamc@48 429
adamc@48 430 (* begin hide *)
adamc@48 431 (* In-class exercises *)
adamc@48 432
adamc@48 433 Theorem forall_exists_commute : forall (A B : Type) (P : A -> B -> Prop),
adamc@48 434 (exists x : A, forall y : B, P x y) -> (forall y : B, exists x : A, P x y).
adamc@52 435 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 436 intros.
adamc@52 437 destruct H.
adamc@52 438 exists x.
adamc@52 439 apply H.
adamc@52 440 (* end thide *)
adamc@48 441 Admitted.
adamc@48 442
adamc@48 443 (* end hide *)
adamc@48 444
adamc@48 445
adam@322 446 (** The tactic [intuition] has a first-order cousin called %\index{tactics!firstorder}%[firstorder], which proves many formulas when only first-order reasoning is needed, and it tries to perform first-order simplifications in any case. First-order reasoning is much harder than propositional reasoning, so [firstorder] is much more likely than [intuition] to get stuck in a way that makes it run for long enough to be useless. *)
adamc@49 447
adamc@49 448
adamc@49 449 (** * Predicates with Implicit Equality *)
adamc@49 450
adamc@49 451 (** We start our exploration of a more complicated class of predicates with a simple example: an alternative way of characterizing when a natural number is zero. *)
adamc@49 452
adamc@49 453 Inductive isZero : nat -> Prop :=
adamc@49 454 | IsZero : isZero 0.
adamc@49 455
adamc@49 456 Theorem isZero_zero : isZero 0.
adamc@55 457 (* begin thide *)
adamc@49 458 constructor.
adamc@55 459 (* end thide *)
adamc@49 460 Qed.
adamc@49 461
adam@449 462 (** We can call [isZero] a%\index{judgment}% _judgment_, in the sense often used in the semantics of programming languages. Judgments are typically defined in the style of%\index{natural deduction}% _natural deduction_, where we write a number of%\index{inference rules}% _inference rules_ with premises appearing above a solid line and a conclusion appearing below the line. In this example, the sole constructor [IsZero] of [isZero] can be thought of as the single inference rule for deducing [isZero], with nothing above the line and [isZero 0] below it. The proof of [isZero_zero] demonstrates how we can apply an inference rule. (Readers not familiar with formal semantics should not worry about not following this paragraph!)
adamc@49 463
adam@494 464 The definition of [isZero] differs in an important way from all of the other inductive definitions that we have seen in this and the previous chapter. Instead of writing just [Set] or [Prop] after the colon, here we write [nat -> Prop]. We saw examples of parameterized types like [list], but there the parameters appeared with names _before_ the colon. Every constructor of a parameterized inductive type must have a range type that uses the same parameter, whereas the form we use here enables us to choose different arguments to the type for different constructors.
adamc@49 465
adam@449 466 For instance, our definition [isZero] makes the predicate provable only when the argument is [0]. We can see that the concept of equality is somehow implicit in the inductive definition mechanism. The way this is accomplished is similar to the way that logic variables are used in %\index{Prolog}%Prolog (but worry not if not familiar with Prolog), and it is a very powerful mechanism that forms a foundation for formalizing all of mathematics. In fact, though it is natural to think of inductive types as folding in the functionality of equality, in Coq, the true situation is reversed, with equality defined as just another inductive type!%\index{Gallina terms!eq}\index{Gallina terms!refl\_equal}% *)
adamc@49 467
adamc@49 468 Print eq.
adam@440 469 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adam@426 470 Inductive eq (A : Type) (x : A) : A -> Prop := eq_refl : x = x
adamc@209 471 ]]
adamc@49 472
adam@442 473 Behind the scenes, uses of infix [=] are expanded to instances of [eq]. We see that [eq] has both a parameter [x] that is fixed and an extra unnamed argument of the same type. The type of [eq] allows us to state any equalities, even those that are provably false. However, examining the type of equality's sole constructor [eq_refl], we see that we can only _prove_ equality when its two arguments are syntactically equal. This definition turns out to capture all of the basic properties of equality, and the equality-manipulating tactics that we have seen so far, like [reflexivity] and [rewrite], are implemented treating [eq] as just another inductive type with a well-chosen definition. Another way of stating that definition is: equality is defined as the least reflexive relation.
adamc@49 474
adam@322 475 Returning to the example of [isZero], we can see how to work with hypotheses that use this predicate. *)
adamc@49 476
adamc@49 477 Theorem isZero_plus : forall n m : nat, isZero m -> n + m = n.
adamc@55 478 (* begin thide *)
adamc@49 479 (** We want to proceed by cases on the proof of the assumption about [isZero]. *)
adamc@209 480
adamc@49 481 destruct 1.
adamc@49 482 (** [[
adamc@49 483 n : nat
adamc@49 484 ============================
adamc@49 485 n + 0 = n
adamc@209 486
adamc@209 487 ]]
adamc@49 488
adamc@209 489 Since [isZero] has only one constructor, we are presented with only one subgoal. The argument [m] to [isZero] is replaced with that type's argument from the single constructor [IsZero]. From this point, the proof is trivial. *)
adamc@49 490
adamc@49 491 crush.
adamc@55 492 (* end thide *)
adamc@49 493 Qed.
adamc@49 494
adamc@49 495 (** Another example seems at first like it should admit an analogous proof, but in fact provides a demonstration of one of the most basic gotchas of Coq proving. *)
adamc@49 496
adamc@49 497 Theorem isZero_contra : isZero 1 -> False.
adamc@55 498 (* begin thide *)
adamc@49 499 (** Let us try a proof by cases on the assumption, as in the last proof. *)
adamc@209 500
adamc@49 501 destruct 1.
adamc@49 502 (** [[
adamc@49 503 ============================
adamc@49 504 False
adamc@209 505
adamc@209 506 ]]
adamc@49 507
adamc@209 508 It seems that case analysis has not helped us much at all! Our sole hypothesis disappears, leaving us, if anything, worse off than we were before. What went wrong? We have met an important restriction in tactics like [destruct] and [induction] when applied to types with arguments. If the arguments are not already free variables, they will be replaced by new free variables internally before doing the case analysis or induction. Since the argument [1] to [isZero] is replaced by a fresh variable, we lose the crucial fact that it is not equal to [0].
adamc@49 509
adam@449 510 Why does Coq use this restriction? We will discuss the issue in detail in a future chapter, when we see the dependently typed programming techniques that would allow us to write this proof term manually. For now, we just say that the algorithmic problem of "logically complete case analysis" is undecidable when phrased in Coq's logic. A few tactics and design patterns that we will present in this chapter suffice in almost all cases. For the current example, what we want is a tactic called %\index{tactics!inversion}%[inversion], which corresponds to the concept of inversion that is frequently used with natural deduction proof systems. (Again, worry not if the semantics-oriented terminology from this last sentence is unfamiliar.) *)
adamc@49 511
adamc@49 512 Undo.
adamc@49 513 inversion 1.
adamc@55 514 (* end thide *)
adamc@49 515 Qed.
adamc@49 516
adamc@49 517 (** What does [inversion] do? Think of it as a version of [destruct] that does its best to take advantage of the structure of arguments to inductive types. In this case, [inversion] completed the proof immediately, because it was able to detect that we were using [isZero] with an impossible argument.
adamc@49 518
adamc@49 519 Sometimes using [destruct] when you should have used [inversion] can lead to confusing results. To illustrate, consider an alternate proof attempt for the last theorem. *)
adamc@49 520
adamc@49 521 Theorem isZero_contra' : isZero 1 -> 2 + 2 = 5.
adamc@49 522 destruct 1.
adamc@49 523 (** [[
adamc@49 524 ============================
adamc@49 525 1 + 1 = 4
adamc@209 526
adamc@209 527 ]]
adamc@49 528
adam@469 529 What on earth happened here? Internally, [destruct] replaced [1] with a fresh variable, and, trying to be helpful, it also replaced the occurrence of [1] within the unary representation of each number in the goal. Then, within the [O] case of the proof, we replace the fresh variable with [O]. This has the net effect of decrementing each of these numbers. *)
adamc@209 530
adamc@49 531 Abort.
adamc@49 532
adam@280 533 (** To see more clearly what is happening, we can consider the type of [isZero]'s induction principle. *)
adam@280 534
adam@280 535 Check isZero_ind.
adam@280 536 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adam@280 537 isZero_ind
adam@280 538 : forall P : nat -> Prop, P 0 -> forall n : nat, isZero n -> P n
adam@280 539 ]]
adam@280 540
adam@442 541 In our last proof script, [destruct] chose to instantiate [P] as [fun n => S n + S n = S (S (S (S n)))]. You can verify for yourself that this specialization of the principle applies to the goal and that the hypothesis [P 0] then matches the subgoal we saw generated. If you are doing a proof and encounter a strange transmutation like this, there is a good chance that you should go back and replace a use of [destruct] with [inversion]. *)
adam@280 542
adamc@49 543
adamc@49 544 (* begin hide *)
adamc@49 545 (* In-class exercises *)
adamc@49 546
adamc@49 547 (* EX: Define an inductive type capturing when a list has exactly two elements. Prove that your predicate does not hold of the empty list, and prove that, whenever it holds of a list, the length of that list is two. *)
adamc@49 548
adamc@52 549 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 550 Section twoEls.
adamc@52 551 Variable A : Type.
adamc@52 552
adamc@52 553 Inductive twoEls : list A -> Prop :=
adamc@52 554 | TwoEls : forall x y, twoEls (x :: y :: nil).
adamc@52 555
adamc@52 556 Theorem twoEls_nil : twoEls nil -> False.
adamc@52 557 inversion 1.
adamc@52 558 Qed.
adamc@52 559
adamc@52 560 Theorem twoEls_two : forall ls, twoEls ls -> length ls = 2.
adamc@52 561 inversion 1.
adamc@52 562 reflexivity.
adamc@52 563 Qed.
adamc@52 564 End twoEls.
adamc@52 565 (* end thide *)
adamc@52 566
adamc@49 567 (* end hide *)
adamc@49 568
adamc@50 569
adamc@50 570 (** * Recursive Predicates *)
adamc@50 571
adamc@50 572 (** We have already seen all of the ingredients we need to build interesting recursive predicates, like this predicate capturing even-ness. *)
adamc@50 573
adamc@50 574 Inductive even : nat -> Prop :=
adamc@50 575 | EvenO : even O
adamc@50 576 | EvenSS : forall n, even n -> even (S (S n)).
adamc@50 577
adam@401 578 (** Think of [even] as another judgment defined by natural deduction rules. The rule [EvenO] has nothing above the line and [even O] below the line, and [EvenSS] is a rule with [even n] above the line and [even (S (S n))] below.
adamc@50 579
adamc@50 580 The proof techniques of the last section are easily adapted. *)
adamc@50 581
adamc@50 582 Theorem even_0 : even 0.
adamc@55 583 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 584 constructor.
adamc@55 585 (* end thide *)
adamc@50 586 Qed.
adamc@50 587
adamc@50 588 Theorem even_4 : even 4.
adamc@55 589 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 590 constructor; constructor; constructor.
adamc@55 591 (* end thide *)
adamc@50 592 Qed.
adamc@50 593
adam@375 594 (** It is not hard to see that sequences of constructor applications like the above can get tedious. We can avoid them using Coq's hint facility, with a new [Hint] variant that asks to consider all constructors of an inductive type during proof search. The tactic %\index{tactics!auto}%[auto] performs exhaustive proof search up to a fixed depth, considering only the proof steps we have registered as hints. *)
adamc@50 595
adamc@55 596 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 597 Hint Constructors even.
adamc@50 598
adamc@50 599 Theorem even_4' : even 4.
adamc@50 600 auto.
adamc@50 601 Qed.
adamc@50 602
adamc@55 603 (* end thide *)
adamc@55 604
adam@322 605 (** We may also use [inversion] with [even]. *)
adam@322 606
adamc@50 607 Theorem even_1_contra : even 1 -> False.
adamc@55 608 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 609 inversion 1.
adamc@55 610 (* end thide *)
adamc@50 611 Qed.
adamc@50 612
adamc@50 613 Theorem even_3_contra : even 3 -> False.
adamc@55 614 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 615 inversion 1.
adamc@50 616 (** [[
adamc@50 617 H : even 3
adamc@50 618 n : nat
adamc@50 619 H1 : even 1
adamc@50 620 H0 : n = 1
adamc@50 621 ============================
adamc@50 622 False
adamc@209 623
adamc@209 624 ]]
adamc@50 625
adam@322 626 The [inversion] tactic can be a little overzealous at times, as we can see here with the introduction of the unused variable [n] and an equality hypothesis about it. For more complicated predicates, though, adding such assumptions is critical to dealing with the undecidability of general inversion. More complex inductive definitions and theorems can cause [inversion] to generate equalities where neither side is a variable. *)
adamc@50 627
adamc@50 628 inversion H1.
adamc@55 629 (* end thide *)
adamc@50 630 Qed.
adamc@50 631
adamc@50 632 (** We can also do inductive proofs about [even]. *)
adamc@50 633
adamc@50 634 Theorem even_plus : forall n m, even n -> even m -> even (n + m).
adamc@55 635 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 636 (** It seems a reasonable first choice to proceed by induction on [n]. *)
adamc@209 637
adamc@50 638 induction n; crush.
adamc@50 639 (** [[
adamc@50 640 n : nat
adamc@50 641 IHn : forall m : nat, even n -> even m -> even (n + m)
adamc@50 642 m : nat
adamc@50 643 H : even (S n)
adamc@50 644 H0 : even m
adamc@50 645 ============================
adamc@50 646 even (S (n + m))
adamc@209 647
adamc@209 648 ]]
adamc@50 649
adamc@209 650 We will need to use the hypotheses [H] and [H0] somehow. The most natural choice is to invert [H]. *)
adamc@50 651
adamc@50 652 inversion H.
adamc@50 653 (** [[
adamc@50 654 n : nat
adamc@50 655 IHn : forall m : nat, even n -> even m -> even (n + m)
adamc@50 656 m : nat
adamc@50 657 H : even (S n)
adamc@50 658 H0 : even m
adamc@50 659 n0 : nat
adamc@50 660 H2 : even n0
adamc@50 661 H1 : S n0 = n
adamc@50 662 ============================
adamc@50 663 even (S (S n0 + m))
adamc@209 664
adamc@209 665 ]]
adamc@50 666
adamc@209 667 Simplifying the conclusion brings us to a point where we can apply a constructor. *)
adamc@209 668
adamc@50 669 simpl.
adamc@50 670 (** [[
adamc@50 671 ============================
adamc@50 672 even (S (S (n0 + m)))
adam@302 673 ]]
adam@302 674 *)
adamc@50 675
adamc@50 676 constructor.
adam@322 677
adam@401 678 (** [[
adamc@50 679 ============================
adamc@50 680 even (n0 + m)
adamc@209 681
adamc@209 682 ]]
adamc@50 683
adamc@209 684 At this point, we would like to apply the inductive hypothesis, which is:
adamc@209 685
adamc@209 686 [[
adamc@50 687 IHn : forall m : nat, even n -> even m -> even (n + m)
adam@440 688
adamc@209 689 ]]
adamc@50 690
adam@421 691 Unfortunately, the goal mentions [n0] where it would need to mention [n] to match [IHn]. We could keep looking for a way to finish this proof from here, but it turns out that we can make our lives much easier by changing our basic strategy. Instead of inducting on the structure of [n], we should induct _on the structure of one of the [even] proofs_. This technique is commonly called%\index{rule induction}% _rule induction_ in programming language semantics. In the setting of Coq, we have already seen how predicates are defined using the same inductive type mechanism as datatypes, so the fundamental unity of rule induction with "normal" induction is apparent.
adamc@50 692
adam@322 693 Recall that tactics like [induction] and [destruct] may be passed numbers to refer to unnamed lefthand sides of implications in the conclusion, where the argument [n] refers to the [n]th such hypothesis. *)
adam@322 694
adamc@50 695 Restart.
adamc@50 696
adamc@50 697 induction 1.
adamc@50 698 (** [[
adamc@50 699 m : nat
adamc@50 700 ============================
adamc@50 701 even m -> even (0 + m)
adam@322 702 ]]
adamc@50 703
adam@322 704 %\noindent \coqdockw{subgoal} 2 \coqdockw{is}:%#<tt>subgoal 2 is</tt>#
adam@322 705 [[
adamc@50 706 even m -> even (S (S n) + m)
adamc@209 707
adamc@209 708 ]]
adamc@50 709
adamc@209 710 The first case is easily discharged by [crush], based on the hint we added earlier to try the constructors of [even]. *)
adamc@50 711
adamc@50 712 crush.
adamc@50 713
adamc@50 714 (** Now we focus on the second case: *)
adamc@209 715
adamc@50 716 intro.
adamc@50 717 (** [[
adamc@50 718 m : nat
adamc@50 719 n : nat
adamc@50 720 H : even n
adamc@50 721 IHeven : even m -> even (n + m)
adamc@50 722 H0 : even m
adamc@50 723 ============================
adamc@50 724 even (S (S n) + m)
adamc@209 725
adamc@209 726 ]]
adamc@50 727
adamc@209 728 We simplify and apply a constructor, as in our last proof attempt. *)
adamc@50 729
adamc@50 730 simpl; constructor.
adam@322 731
adam@401 732 (** [[
adamc@50 733 ============================
adamc@50 734 even (n + m)
adamc@209 735
adamc@209 736 ]]
adamc@50 737
adamc@209 738 Now we have an exact match with our inductive hypothesis, and the remainder of the proof is trivial. *)
adamc@50 739
adamc@50 740 apply IHeven; assumption.
adamc@50 741
adamc@50 742 (** In fact, [crush] can handle all of the details of the proof once we declare the induction strategy. *)
adamc@50 743
adamc@50 744 Restart.
adam@322 745
adamc@50 746 induction 1; crush.
adamc@55 747 (* end thide *)
adamc@50 748 Qed.
adamc@50 749
adamc@50 750 (** Induction on recursive predicates has similar pitfalls to those we encountered with inversion in the last section. *)
adamc@50 751
adamc@50 752 Theorem even_contra : forall n, even (S (n + n)) -> False.
adamc@55 753 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 754 induction 1.
adamc@50 755 (** [[
adamc@50 756 n : nat
adamc@50 757 ============================
adamc@50 758 False
adam@322 759 ]]
adamc@50 760
adam@322 761 %\noindent \coqdockw{subgoal} 2 \coqdockw{is}:%#<tt>subgoal 2 is</tt>#
adam@322 762 [[
adamc@50 763 False
adamc@209 764
adamc@209 765 ]]
adamc@50 766
adam@280 767 We are already sunk trying to prove the first subgoal, since the argument to [even] was replaced by a fresh variable internally. This time, we find it easier to prove this theorem by way of a lemma. Instead of trusting [induction] to replace expressions with fresh variables, we do it ourselves, explicitly adding the appropriate equalities as new assumptions. *)
adamc@209 768
adamc@50 769 Abort.
adamc@50 770
adamc@50 771 Lemma even_contra' : forall n', even n' -> forall n, n' = S (n + n) -> False.
adamc@50 772 induction 1; crush.
adamc@50 773
adamc@54 774 (** At this point, it is useful to consider all cases of [n] and [n0] being zero or nonzero. Only one of these cases has any trickiness to it. *)
adamc@209 775
adamc@50 776 destruct n; destruct n0; crush.
adamc@50 777
adamc@50 778 (** [[
adamc@50 779 n : nat
adamc@50 780 H : even (S n)
adamc@50 781 IHeven : forall n0 : nat, S n = S (n0 + n0) -> False
adamc@50 782 n0 : nat
adamc@50 783 H0 : S n = n0 + S n0
adamc@50 784 ============================
adamc@50 785 False
adamc@209 786
adamc@209 787 ]]
adamc@50 788
adam@280 789 At this point it is useful to use a theorem from the standard library, which we also proved with a different name in the last chapter. We can search for a theorem that allows us to rewrite terms of the form [x + S y]. *)
adamc@209 790
adam@280 791 SearchRewrite (_ + S _).
adam@440 792 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adam@280 793 plus_n_Sm : forall n m : nat, S (n + m) = n + S m
adam@302 794 ]]
adam@302 795 *)
adamc@50 796
adamc@50 797 rewrite <- plus_n_Sm in H0.
adamc@50 798
adam@322 799 (** The induction hypothesis lets us complete the proof, if we use a variant of [apply] that has a %\index{tactics!with}%[with] clause to give instantiations of quantified variables. *)
adamc@209 800
adamc@50 801 apply IHeven with n0; assumption.
adamc@50 802
adam@322 803 (** As usual, we can rewrite the proof to avoid referencing any locally generated names, which makes our proof script more readable and more robust to changes in the theorem statement. We use the notation [<-] to request a hint that does right-to-left rewriting, just like we can with the [rewrite] tactic. *)
adamc@209 804
adamc@209 805 Restart.
adam@322 806
adam@375 807 Hint Rewrite <- plus_n_Sm.
adamc@50 808
adamc@50 809 induction 1; crush;
adamc@50 810 match goal with
adamc@50 811 | [ H : S ?N = ?N0 + ?N0 |- _ ] => destruct N; destruct N0
adam@500 812 end; crush.
adamc@50 813 Qed.
adamc@50 814
adam@500 815 (** We write the proof in a way that avoids the use of local variable or hypothesis names, using the %\index{tactics!match}%[match] tactic form to do pattern-matching on the goal. We use unification variables prefixed by question marks in the pattern, and we take advantage of the possibility to mention a unification variable twice in one pattern, to enforce equality between occurrences. The hint to rewrite with [plus_n_Sm] in a particular direction saves us from having to figure out the right place to apply that theorem.
adamc@50 816
adam@500 817 The original theorem now follows trivially from our lemma, using a new tactic %\index{tactics!eauto}%[eauto], a fancier version of [auto] whose explanation we postpone to Chapter 13. *)
adamc@50 818
adamc@50 819 Theorem even_contra : forall n, even (S (n + n)) -> False.
adamc@52 820 intros; eapply even_contra'; eauto.
adamc@50 821 Qed.
adamc@52 822
adam@398 823 (** We use a variant %\index{tactics!apply}%[eapply] of [apply] which has the same relationship to [apply] as [eauto] has to [auto]. An invocation of [apply] only succeeds if all arguments to the rule being used can be determined from the form of the goal, whereas [eapply] will introduce unification variables for undetermined arguments. In this case, [eauto] is able to determine the right values for those unification variables, using (unsurprisingly) a variant of the classic algorithm for _unification_ %\cite{unification}%.
adamc@52 824
adamc@52 825 By considering an alternate attempt at proving the lemma, we can see another common pitfall of inductive proofs in Coq. Imagine that we had tried to prove [even_contra'] with all of the [forall] quantifiers moved to the front of the lemma statement. *)
adamc@52 826
adamc@52 827 Lemma even_contra'' : forall n' n, even n' -> n' = S (n + n) -> False.
adamc@52 828 induction 1; crush;
adamc@52 829 match goal with
adamc@52 830 | [ H : S ?N = ?N0 + ?N0 |- _ ] => destruct N; destruct N0
adam@500 831 end; crush.
adamc@52 832
adamc@209 833 (** One subgoal remains:
adamc@52 834
adamc@209 835 [[
adamc@52 836 n : nat
adamc@52 837 H : even (S (n + n))
adamc@52 838 IHeven : S (n + n) = S (S (S (n + n))) -> False
adamc@52 839 ============================
adamc@52 840 False
adamc@209 841
adamc@209 842 ]]
adamc@52 843
adam@398 844 We are out of luck here. The inductive hypothesis is trivially true, since its assumption is false. In the version of this proof that succeeded, [IHeven] had an explicit quantification over [n]. This is because the quantification of [n] _appeared after the thing we are inducting on_ in the theorem statement. In general, quantified variables and hypotheses that appear before the induction object in the theorem statement stay fixed throughout the inductive proof. Variables and hypotheses that are quantified after the induction object may be varied explicitly in uses of inductive hypotheses. *)
adamc@52 845
adam@322 846 Abort.
adam@322 847
adam@322 848 (** Why should Coq implement [induction] this way? One answer is that it avoids burdening this basic tactic with additional heuristic smarts, but that is not the whole picture. Imagine that [induction] analyzed dependencies among variables and reordered quantifiers to preserve as much freedom as possible in later uses of inductive hypotheses. This could make the inductive hypotheses more complex, which could in turn cause particular automation machinery to fail when it would have succeeded before. In general, we want to avoid quantifiers in our proofs whenever we can, and that goal is furthered by the refactoring that the [induction] tactic forces us to do. *)
adamc@55 849 (* end thide *)
adamc@209 850
adam@322 851
adamc@51 852
adamc@52 853
adamc@52 854 (* begin hide *)
adamc@52 855 (* In-class exercises *)
adamc@52 856
adam@448 857 (* EX: Define a type [prop] of simple Boolean formulas made up only of truth, falsehood, binary conjunction, and binary disjunction. Define an inductive predicate [holds] that captures when [prop]s are valid, and define a predicate [falseFree] that captures when a [prop] does not contain the "false" formula. Prove that every false-free [prop] is valid. *)
adamc@52 858
adamc@52 859 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 860 Inductive prop : Set :=
adamc@52 861 | Tru : prop
adamc@52 862 | Fals : prop
adamc@52 863 | And : prop -> prop -> prop
adamc@52 864 | Or : prop -> prop -> prop.
adamc@52 865
adamc@52 866 Inductive holds : prop -> Prop :=
adamc@52 867 | HTru : holds Tru
adamc@52 868 | HAnd : forall p1 p2, holds p1 -> holds p2 -> holds (And p1 p2)
adamc@52 869 | HOr1 : forall p1 p2, holds p1 -> holds (Or p1 p2)
adamc@52 870 | HOr2 : forall p1 p2, holds p2 -> holds (Or p1 p2).
adamc@52 871
adamc@52 872 Inductive falseFree : prop -> Prop :=
adamc@52 873 | FFTru : falseFree Tru
adamc@52 874 | FFAnd : forall p1 p2, falseFree p1 -> falseFree p2 -> falseFree (And p1 p2)
adamc@52 875 | FFNot : forall p1 p2, falseFree p1 -> falseFree p2 -> falseFree (Or p1 p2).
adamc@52 876
adamc@52 877 Hint Constructors holds.
adamc@52 878
adamc@52 879 Theorem falseFree_holds : forall p, falseFree p -> holds p.
adamc@52 880 induction 1; crush.
adamc@52 881 Qed.
adamc@52 882 (* end thide *)
adamc@52 883
adamc@52 884
adamc@52 885 (* EX: Define an inductive type [prop'] that is the same as [prop] but omits the possibility for falsehood. Define a proposition [holds'] for [prop'] that is analogous to [holds]. Define a function [propify] for translating [prop']s to [prop]s. Prove that, for any [prop'] [p], if [propify p] is valid, then so is [p]. *)
adamc@52 886
adamc@52 887 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 888 Inductive prop' : Set :=
adamc@52 889 | Tru' : prop'
adamc@52 890 | And' : prop' -> prop' -> prop'
adamc@52 891 | Or' : prop' -> prop' -> prop'.
adamc@52 892
adamc@52 893 Inductive holds' : prop' -> Prop :=
adamc@52 894 | HTru' : holds' Tru'
adamc@52 895 | HAnd' : forall p1 p2, holds' p1 -> holds' p2 -> holds' (And' p1 p2)
adamc@52 896 | HOr1' : forall p1 p2, holds' p1 -> holds' (Or' p1 p2)
adamc@52 897 | HOr2' : forall p1 p2, holds' p2 -> holds' (Or' p1 p2).
adamc@52 898
adamc@52 899 Fixpoint propify (p : prop') : prop :=
adamc@52 900 match p with
adamc@52 901 | Tru' => Tru
adamc@52 902 | And' p1 p2 => And (propify p1) (propify p2)
adamc@52 903 | Or' p1 p2 => Or (propify p1) (propify p2)
adamc@52 904 end.
adamc@52 905
adamc@52 906 Hint Constructors holds'.
adamc@52 907
adamc@52 908 Lemma propify_holds' : forall p', holds p' -> forall p, p' = propify p -> holds' p.
adamc@52 909 induction 1; crush; destruct p; crush.
adamc@52 910 Qed.
adamc@52 911
adamc@52 912 Theorem propify_holds : forall p, holds (propify p) -> holds' p.
adamc@52 913 intros; eapply propify_holds'; eauto.
adamc@52 914 Qed.
adamc@52 915 (* end thide *)
adamc@52 916
adamc@52 917 (* end hide *)