adam@379
|
1 (* Copyright (c) 2008-2012, Adam Chlipala
|
adamc@142
|
2 *
|
adamc@142
|
3 * This work is licensed under a
|
adamc@142
|
4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
|
adamc@142
|
5 * Unported License.
|
adamc@142
|
6 * The license text is available at:
|
adamc@142
|
7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
|
adamc@142
|
8 *)
|
adamc@142
|
9
|
adamc@142
|
10 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@142
|
11 Require Import List.
|
adamc@142
|
12
|
adam@314
|
13 Require Import CpdtTactics MoreSpecif.
|
adamc@142
|
14
|
adamc@142
|
15 Set Implicit Arguments.
|
adamc@142
|
16 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@142
|
17
|
adamc@142
|
18
|
adamc@142
|
19 (** %\chapter{Proof by Reflection}% *)
|
adamc@142
|
20
|
adam@412
|
21 (** The last chapter highlighted a very heuristic approach to proving. In this chapter, we will study an alternative technique,%\index{proof by reflection}% _proof by reflection_ %\cite{reflection}%. We will write, in Gallina, decision procedures with proofs of correctness, and we will appeal to these procedures in writing very short proofs. Such a proof is checked by running the decision procedure. The term _reflection_ applies because we will need to translate Gallina propositions into values of inductive types representing syntax, so that Gallina programs may analyze them, and translating such a term back to the original form is called _reflecting_ it. *)
|
adamc@142
|
22
|
adamc@142
|
23
|
adamc@142
|
24 (** * Proving Evenness *)
|
adamc@142
|
25
|
adamc@142
|
26 (** Proving that particular natural number constants are even is certainly something we would rather have happen automatically. The Ltac-programming techniques that we learned in the last chapter make it easy to implement such a procedure. *)
|
adamc@142
|
27
|
adamc@142
|
28 Inductive isEven : nat -> Prop :=
|
adamc@144
|
29 | Even_O : isEven O
|
adamc@144
|
30 | Even_SS : forall n, isEven n -> isEven (S (S n)).
|
adamc@142
|
31
|
adamc@148
|
32 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@142
|
33 Ltac prove_even := repeat constructor.
|
adamc@148
|
34 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@142
|
35
|
adamc@142
|
36 Theorem even_256 : isEven 256.
|
adamc@142
|
37 prove_even.
|
adamc@142
|
38 Qed.
|
adamc@142
|
39
|
adamc@142
|
40 Print even_256.
|
adamc@221
|
41 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@142
|
42 even_256 =
|
adamc@142
|
43 Even_SS
|
adamc@142
|
44 (Even_SS
|
adamc@142
|
45 (Even_SS
|
adamc@142
|
46 (Even_SS
|
adamc@142
|
47 ]]
|
adamc@142
|
48
|
adam@360
|
49 %\noindent%...and so on. This procedure always works (at least on machines with infinite resources), but it has a serious drawback, which we see when we print the proof it generates that 256 is even. The final proof term has length super-linear in the input value. Coq's implicit arguments mechanism is hiding the values given for parameter [n] of [Even_SS], which is why the proof term only appears linear here. Also, proof terms are represented internally as syntax trees, with opportunity for sharing of node representations, but in this chapter we will measure proof term size as simple textual length or as the number of nodes in the term's syntax tree, two measures that are approximately equivalent. Sometimes apparently large proof terms have enough internal sharing that they take up less memory than we expect, but one avoids having to reason about such sharing by ensuring that the size of a sharing-free version of a term is low enough.
|
adam@360
|
50
|
adam@360
|
51 Superlinear evenness proof terms seem like a shame, since we could write a trivial and trustworthy program to verify evenness of constants. The proof checker could simply call our program where needed.
|
adamc@142
|
52
|
adamc@142
|
53 It is also unfortunate not to have static typing guarantees that our tactic always behaves appropriately. Other invocations of similar tactics might fail with dynamic type errors, and we would not know about the bugs behind these errors until we happened to attempt to prove complex enough goals.
|
adamc@142
|
54
|
adamc@142
|
55 The techniques of proof by reflection address both complaints. We will be able to write proofs like this with constant size overhead beyond the size of the input, and we will do it with verified decision procedures written in Gallina.
|
adamc@142
|
56
|
adamc@221
|
57 For this example, we begin by using a type from the [MoreSpecif] module (included in the book source) to write a certified evenness checker. *)
|
adamc@142
|
58
|
adam@432
|
59 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@437
|
60 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@432
|
61 Definition paartial := partial.
|
adam@437
|
62 (* end thide *)
|
adam@432
|
63 (* end hide *)
|
adam@432
|
64
|
adamc@142
|
65 Print partial.
|
adamc@221
|
66 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@221
|
67 Inductive partial (P : Prop) : Set := Proved : P -> [P] | Uncertain : [P]
|
adamc@221
|
68 ]]
|
adamc@142
|
69
|
adamc@221
|
70 A [partial P] value is an optional proof of [P]. The notation [[P]] stands for [partial P]. *)
|
adamc@142
|
71
|
adamc@221
|
72 Local Open Scope partial_scope.
|
adamc@142
|
73
|
adamc@142
|
74 (** We bring into scope some notations for the [partial] type. These overlap with some of the notations we have seen previously for specification types, so they were placed in a separate scope that needs separate opening. *)
|
adamc@142
|
75
|
adamc@148
|
76 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@297
|
77 Definition check_even : forall n : nat, [isEven n].
|
adamc@142
|
78 Hint Constructors isEven.
|
adamc@142
|
79
|
adamc@142
|
80 refine (fix F (n : nat) : [isEven n] :=
|
adamc@221
|
81 match n with
|
adamc@142
|
82 | 0 => Yes
|
adamc@142
|
83 | 1 => No
|
adamc@142
|
84 | S (S n') => Reduce (F n')
|
adamc@142
|
85 end); auto.
|
adamc@142
|
86 Defined.
|
adamc@142
|
87
|
adam@461
|
88 (** The function [check_even] may be viewed as a _verified decision procedure_, because its type guarantees that it never returns %\coqdocnotation{%#<tt>#Yes#</tt>#%}% for inputs that are not even.
|
adam@360
|
89
|
adam@360
|
90 Now we can use dependent pattern-matching to write a function that performs a surprising feat. When given a [partial P], this function [partialOut] returns a proof of [P] if the [partial] value contains a proof, and it returns a (useless) proof of [True] otherwise. From the standpoint of ML and Haskell programming, it seems impossible to write such a type, but it is trivial with a [return] annotation. *)
|
adamc@142
|
91
|
adamc@142
|
92 Definition partialOut (P : Prop) (x : [P]) :=
|
adamc@142
|
93 match x return (match x with
|
adamc@142
|
94 | Proved _ => P
|
adamc@142
|
95 | Uncertain => True
|
adamc@142
|
96 end) with
|
adamc@142
|
97 | Proved pf => pf
|
adamc@142
|
98 | Uncertain => I
|
adamc@142
|
99 end.
|
adamc@142
|
100
|
adam@289
|
101 (** It may seem strange to define a function like this. However, it turns out to be very useful in writing a reflective version of our earlier [prove_even] tactic: *)
|
adamc@142
|
102
|
adamc@142
|
103 Ltac prove_even_reflective :=
|
adamc@142
|
104 match goal with
|
adamc@142
|
105 | [ |- isEven ?N] => exact (partialOut (check_even N))
|
adamc@142
|
106 end.
|
adamc@148
|
107 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@142
|
108
|
adam@432
|
109 (** We identify which natural number we are considering, and we "prove" its evenness by pulling the proof out of the appropriate [check_even] call. Recall that the %\index{tactics!exact}%[exact] tactic proves a proposition [P] when given a proof term of precisely type [P]. *)
|
adamc@142
|
110
|
adamc@142
|
111 Theorem even_256' : isEven 256.
|
adamc@142
|
112 prove_even_reflective.
|
adamc@142
|
113 Qed.
|
adamc@142
|
114
|
adamc@142
|
115 Print even_256'.
|
adamc@221
|
116 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@142
|
117 even_256' = partialOut (check_even 256)
|
adamc@142
|
118 : isEven 256
|
adamc@142
|
119 ]]
|
adamc@142
|
120
|
adam@289
|
121 We can see a constant wrapper around the object of the proof. For any even number, this form of proof will suffice. The size of the proof term is now linear in the number being checked, containing two repetitions of the unary form of that number, one of which is hidden above within the implicit argument to [partialOut].
|
adam@289
|
122
|
adam@289
|
123 What happens if we try the tactic with an odd number? *)
|
adamc@142
|
124
|
adamc@142
|
125 Theorem even_255 : isEven 255.
|
adam@360
|
126 (** %\vspace{-.275in}%[[
|
adamc@142
|
127 prove_even_reflective.
|
adam@360
|
128 ]]
|
adamc@142
|
129
|
adam@360
|
130 <<
|
adamc@142
|
131 User error: No matching clauses for match goal
|
adam@360
|
132 >>
|
adamc@142
|
133
|
adamc@142
|
134 Thankfully, the tactic fails. To see more precisely what goes wrong, we can run manually the body of the [match].
|
adamc@142
|
135
|
adam@360
|
136 %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adamc@142
|
137 exact (partialOut (check_even 255)).
|
adam@360
|
138 ]]
|
adamc@142
|
139
|
adam@360
|
140 <<
|
adamc@142
|
141 Error: The term "partialOut (check_even 255)" has type
|
adamc@142
|
142 "match check_even 255 with
|
adamc@142
|
143 | Yes => isEven 255
|
adamc@142
|
144 | No => True
|
adamc@142
|
145 end" while it is expected to have type "isEven 255"
|
adam@360
|
146 >>
|
adamc@142
|
147
|
adam@461
|
148 As usual, the type checker performs no reductions to simplify error messages. If we reduced the first term ourselves, we would see that [check_even 255] reduces to a %\coqdocnotation{%#<tt>#No#</tt>#%}%, so that the first term is equivalent to [True], which certainly does not unify with [isEven 255]. *)
|
adamc@221
|
149
|
adamc@142
|
150 Abort.
|
adamc@143
|
151
|
adam@362
|
152 (** Our tactic [prove_even_reflective] is reflective because it performs a proof search process (a trivial one, in this case) wholly within Gallina, where the only use of Ltac is to translate a goal into an appropriate use of [check_even]. *)
|
adamc@143
|
153
|
adam@360
|
154
|
adam@360
|
155 (** * Reifying the Syntax of a Trivial Tautology Language *)
|
adamc@143
|
156
|
adamc@143
|
157 (** We might also like to have reflective proofs of trivial tautologies like this one: *)
|
adamc@143
|
158
|
adamc@143
|
159 Theorem true_galore : (True /\ True) -> (True \/ (True /\ (True -> True))).
|
adamc@143
|
160 tauto.
|
adamc@143
|
161 Qed.
|
adamc@143
|
162
|
adam@432
|
163 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@437
|
164 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@432
|
165 Definition tg := (and_ind, or_introl).
|
adam@437
|
166 (* end thide *)
|
adam@432
|
167 (* end hide *)
|
adam@432
|
168
|
adamc@143
|
169 Print true_galore.
|
adamc@221
|
170 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@143
|
171 true_galore =
|
adamc@143
|
172 fun H : True /\ True =>
|
adamc@143
|
173 and_ind (fun _ _ : True => or_introl (True /\ (True -> True)) I) H
|
adamc@143
|
174 : True /\ True -> True \/ True /\ (True -> True)
|
adamc@143
|
175 ]]
|
adamc@143
|
176
|
adamc@143
|
177 As we might expect, the proof that [tauto] builds contains explicit applications of natural deduction rules. For large formulas, this can add a linear amount of proof size overhead, beyond the size of the input.
|
adamc@143
|
178
|
adam@432
|
179 To write a reflective procedure for this class of goals, we will need to get into the actual "reflection" part of "proof by reflection." It is impossible to case-analyze a [Prop] in any way in Gallina. We must%\index{reification}% _reify_ [Prop] into some type that we _can_ analyze. This inductive type is a good candidate: *)
|
adamc@143
|
180
|
adamc@148
|
181 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@143
|
182 Inductive taut : Set :=
|
adamc@143
|
183 | TautTrue : taut
|
adamc@143
|
184 | TautAnd : taut -> taut -> taut
|
adamc@143
|
185 | TautOr : taut -> taut -> taut
|
adamc@143
|
186 | TautImp : taut -> taut -> taut.
|
adamc@143
|
187
|
adam@432
|
188 (** We write a recursive function to _reflect_ this syntax back to [Prop]. Such functions are also called%\index{interpretation function}% _interpretation functions_, and we have used them in previous examples to give semantics to small programming languages. *)
|
adamc@143
|
189
|
adamc@143
|
190 Fixpoint tautDenote (t : taut) : Prop :=
|
adamc@143
|
191 match t with
|
adamc@143
|
192 | TautTrue => True
|
adamc@143
|
193 | TautAnd t1 t2 => tautDenote t1 /\ tautDenote t2
|
adamc@143
|
194 | TautOr t1 t2 => tautDenote t1 \/ tautDenote t2
|
adamc@143
|
195 | TautImp t1 t2 => tautDenote t1 -> tautDenote t2
|
adamc@143
|
196 end.
|
adamc@143
|
197
|
adamc@143
|
198 (** It is easy to prove that every formula in the range of [tautDenote] is true. *)
|
adamc@143
|
199
|
adamc@143
|
200 Theorem tautTrue : forall t, tautDenote t.
|
adamc@143
|
201 induction t; crush.
|
adamc@143
|
202 Qed.
|
adamc@143
|
203
|
adam@360
|
204 (** To use [tautTrue] to prove particular formulas, we need to implement the syntax reification process. A recursive Ltac function does the job. *)
|
adamc@143
|
205
|
adam@360
|
206 Ltac tautReify P :=
|
adamc@143
|
207 match P with
|
adamc@143
|
208 | True => TautTrue
|
adamc@143
|
209 | ?P1 /\ ?P2 =>
|
adam@360
|
210 let t1 := tautReify P1 in
|
adam@360
|
211 let t2 := tautReify P2 in
|
adamc@143
|
212 constr:(TautAnd t1 t2)
|
adamc@143
|
213 | ?P1 \/ ?P2 =>
|
adam@360
|
214 let t1 := tautReify P1 in
|
adam@360
|
215 let t2 := tautReify P2 in
|
adamc@143
|
216 constr:(TautOr t1 t2)
|
adamc@143
|
217 | ?P1 -> ?P2 =>
|
adam@360
|
218 let t1 := tautReify P1 in
|
adam@360
|
219 let t2 := tautReify P2 in
|
adamc@143
|
220 constr:(TautImp t1 t2)
|
adamc@143
|
221 end.
|
adamc@143
|
222
|
adam@461
|
223 (** With [tautReify] available, it is easy to finish our reflective tactic. We look at the goal formula, reify it, and apply [tautTrue] to the reified formula. *)
|
adamc@143
|
224
|
adamc@143
|
225 Ltac obvious :=
|
adamc@143
|
226 match goal with
|
adamc@143
|
227 | [ |- ?P ] =>
|
adam@360
|
228 let t := tautReify P in
|
adamc@143
|
229 exact (tautTrue t)
|
adamc@143
|
230 end.
|
adamc@143
|
231
|
adamc@143
|
232 (** We can verify that [obvious] solves our original example, with a proof term that does not mention details of the proof. *)
|
adamc@148
|
233 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@143
|
234
|
adamc@143
|
235 Theorem true_galore' : (True /\ True) -> (True \/ (True /\ (True -> True))).
|
adamc@143
|
236 obvious.
|
adamc@143
|
237 Qed.
|
adamc@143
|
238
|
adamc@143
|
239 Print true_galore'.
|
adamc@221
|
240 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@143
|
241 true_galore' =
|
adamc@143
|
242 tautTrue
|
adamc@143
|
243 (TautImp (TautAnd TautTrue TautTrue)
|
adamc@143
|
244 (TautOr TautTrue (TautAnd TautTrue (TautImp TautTrue TautTrue))))
|
adamc@143
|
245 : True /\ True -> True \/ True /\ (True -> True)
|
adamc@143
|
246 ]]
|
adamc@143
|
247
|
adam@432
|
248 It is worth considering how the reflective tactic improves on a pure-Ltac implementation. The formula reification process is just as ad-hoc as before, so we gain little there. In general, proofs will be more complicated than formula translation, and the "generic proof rule" that we apply here _is_ on much better formal footing than a recursive Ltac function. The dependent type of the proof guarantees that it "works" on any input formula. This is all in addition to the proof-size improvement that we have already seen.
|
adam@360
|
249
|
adam@360
|
250 It may also be worth pointing out that our previous example of evenness testing used a function [partialOut] for sound handling of input goals that the verified decision procedure fails to prove. Here, we prove that our procedure [tautTrue] (recall that an inductive proof may be viewed as a recursive procedure) is able to prove any goal representable in [taut], so no extra step is necessary. *)
|
adamc@144
|
251
|
adamc@144
|
252
|
adamc@145
|
253 (** * A Monoid Expression Simplifier *)
|
adamc@145
|
254
|
adam@432
|
255 (** Proof by reflection does not require encoding of all of the syntax in a goal. We can insert "variables" in our syntax types to allow injection of arbitrary pieces, even if we cannot apply specialized reasoning to them. In this section, we explore that possibility by writing a tactic for normalizing monoid equations. *)
|
adamc@146
|
256
|
adamc@145
|
257 Section monoid.
|
adamc@145
|
258 Variable A : Set.
|
adamc@145
|
259 Variable e : A.
|
adamc@145
|
260 Variable f : A -> A -> A.
|
adamc@145
|
261
|
adamc@145
|
262 Infix "+" := f.
|
adamc@145
|
263
|
adamc@145
|
264 Hypothesis assoc : forall a b c, (a + b) + c = a + (b + c).
|
adamc@145
|
265 Hypothesis identl : forall a, e + a = a.
|
adamc@145
|
266 Hypothesis identr : forall a, a + e = a.
|
adamc@145
|
267
|
adamc@146
|
268 (** We add variables and hypotheses characterizing an arbitrary instance of the algebraic structure of monoids. We have an associative binary operator and an identity element for it.
|
adamc@146
|
269
|
adam@432
|
270 It is easy to define an expression tree type for monoid expressions. A [Var] constructor is a "catch-all" case for subexpressions that we cannot model. These subexpressions could be actual Gallina variables, or they could just use functions that our tactic is unable to understand. *)
|
adamc@146
|
271
|
adamc@148
|
272 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@145
|
273 Inductive mexp : Set :=
|
adamc@145
|
274 | Ident : mexp
|
adamc@145
|
275 | Var : A -> mexp
|
adamc@145
|
276 | Op : mexp -> mexp -> mexp.
|
adamc@145
|
277
|
adam@360
|
278 (** Next, we write an interpretation function. *)
|
adamc@146
|
279
|
adamc@145
|
280 Fixpoint mdenote (me : mexp) : A :=
|
adamc@145
|
281 match me with
|
adamc@145
|
282 | Ident => e
|
adamc@145
|
283 | Var v => v
|
adamc@145
|
284 | Op me1 me2 => mdenote me1 + mdenote me2
|
adamc@145
|
285 end.
|
adamc@145
|
286
|
adamc@146
|
287 (** We will normalize expressions by flattening them into lists, via associativity, so it is helpful to have a denotation function for lists of monoid values. *)
|
adamc@146
|
288
|
adamc@145
|
289 Fixpoint mldenote (ls : list A) : A :=
|
adamc@145
|
290 match ls with
|
adamc@145
|
291 | nil => e
|
adamc@145
|
292 | x :: ls' => x + mldenote ls'
|
adamc@145
|
293 end.
|
adamc@145
|
294
|
adamc@146
|
295 (** The flattening function itself is easy to implement. *)
|
adamc@146
|
296
|
adamc@145
|
297 Fixpoint flatten (me : mexp) : list A :=
|
adamc@145
|
298 match me with
|
adamc@145
|
299 | Ident => nil
|
adamc@145
|
300 | Var x => x :: nil
|
adamc@145
|
301 | Op me1 me2 => flatten me1 ++ flatten me2
|
adamc@145
|
302 end.
|
adamc@145
|
303
|
adam@461
|
304 (** This function has a straightforward correctness proof in terms of our [denote] functions. *)
|
adamc@146
|
305
|
adamc@146
|
306 Lemma flatten_correct' : forall ml2 ml1,
|
adamc@146
|
307 mldenote ml1 + mldenote ml2 = mldenote (ml1 ++ ml2).
|
adamc@145
|
308 induction ml1; crush.
|
adamc@145
|
309 Qed.
|
adamc@145
|
310
|
adamc@145
|
311 Theorem flatten_correct : forall me, mdenote me = mldenote (flatten me).
|
adamc@145
|
312 Hint Resolve flatten_correct'.
|
adamc@145
|
313
|
adamc@145
|
314 induction me; crush.
|
adamc@145
|
315 Qed.
|
adamc@145
|
316
|
adamc@146
|
317 (** Now it is easy to prove a theorem that will be the main tool behind our simplification tactic. *)
|
adamc@146
|
318
|
adamc@146
|
319 Theorem monoid_reflect : forall me1 me2,
|
adamc@146
|
320 mldenote (flatten me1) = mldenote (flatten me2)
|
adamc@146
|
321 -> mdenote me1 = mdenote me2.
|
adamc@145
|
322 intros; repeat rewrite flatten_correct; assumption.
|
adamc@145
|
323 Qed.
|
adamc@145
|
324
|
adam@360
|
325 (** We implement reification into the [mexp] type. *)
|
adamc@146
|
326
|
adam@360
|
327 Ltac reify me :=
|
adamc@146
|
328 match me with
|
adamc@145
|
329 | e => Ident
|
adamc@146
|
330 | ?me1 + ?me2 =>
|
adam@360
|
331 let r1 := reify me1 in
|
adam@360
|
332 let r2 := reify me2 in
|
adamc@145
|
333 constr:(Op r1 r2)
|
adamc@146
|
334 | _ => constr:(Var me)
|
adamc@145
|
335 end.
|
adamc@145
|
336
|
adam@360
|
337 (** The final [monoid] tactic works on goals that equate two monoid terms. We reify each and change the goal to refer to the reified versions, finishing off by applying [monoid_reflect] and simplifying uses of [mldenote]. Recall that the %\index{tactics!change}%[change] tactic replaces a conclusion formula with another that is definitionally equal to it. *)
|
adamc@146
|
338
|
adamc@145
|
339 Ltac monoid :=
|
adamc@145
|
340 match goal with
|
adamc@146
|
341 | [ |- ?me1 = ?me2 ] =>
|
adam@360
|
342 let r1 := reify me1 in
|
adam@360
|
343 let r2 := reify me2 in
|
adamc@145
|
344 change (mdenote r1 = mdenote r2);
|
adam@360
|
345 apply monoid_reflect; simpl
|
adamc@145
|
346 end.
|
adamc@145
|
347
|
adamc@146
|
348 (** We can make short work of theorems like this one: *)
|
adamc@146
|
349
|
adamc@148
|
350 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@148
|
351
|
adamc@145
|
352 Theorem t1 : forall a b c d, a + b + c + d = a + (b + c) + d.
|
adamc@146
|
353 intros; monoid.
|
adamc@146
|
354 (** [[
|
adamc@146
|
355 ============================
|
adamc@146
|
356 a + (b + (c + (d + e))) = a + (b + (c + (d + e)))
|
adamc@221
|
357
|
adamc@146
|
358 ]]
|
adamc@146
|
359
|
adam@360
|
360 Our tactic has canonicalized both sides of the equality, such that we can finish the proof by reflexivity. *)
|
adamc@146
|
361
|
adamc@145
|
362 reflexivity.
|
adamc@145
|
363 Qed.
|
adamc@146
|
364
|
adamc@146
|
365 (** It is interesting to look at the form of the proof. *)
|
adamc@146
|
366
|
adamc@146
|
367 Print t1.
|
adamc@221
|
368 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@146
|
369 t1 =
|
adamc@146
|
370 fun a b c d : A =>
|
adamc@146
|
371 monoid_reflect (Op (Op (Op (Var a) (Var b)) (Var c)) (Var d))
|
adamc@146
|
372 (Op (Op (Var a) (Op (Var b) (Var c))) (Var d))
|
adam@426
|
373 (eq_refl (a + (b + (c + (d + e)))))
|
adamc@146
|
374 : forall a b c d : A, a + b + c + d = a + (b + c) + d
|
adamc@146
|
375 ]]
|
adamc@146
|
376
|
adam@360
|
377 The proof term contains only restatements of the equality operands in reified form, followed by a use of reflexivity on the shared canonical form. *)
|
adamc@221
|
378
|
adamc@145
|
379 End monoid.
|
adamc@145
|
380
|
adam@360
|
381 (** Extensions of this basic approach are used in the implementations of the %\index{tactics!ring}%[ring] and %\index{tactics!field}%[field] tactics that come packaged with Coq. *)
|
adamc@146
|
382
|
adamc@145
|
383
|
adamc@144
|
384 (** * A Smarter Tautology Solver *)
|
adamc@144
|
385
|
adam@412
|
386 (** Now we are ready to revisit our earlier tautology solver example. We want to broaden the scope of the tactic to include formulas whose truth is not syntactically apparent. We will want to allow injection of arbitrary formulas, like we allowed arbitrary monoid expressions in the last example. Since we are working in a richer theory, it is important to be able to use equalities between different injected formulas. For instance, we cannot prove [P -> P] by translating the formula into a value like [Imp (Var P) (Var P)], because a Gallina function has no way of comparing the two [P]s for equality.
|
adamc@147
|
387
|
adam@360
|
388 To arrive at a nice implementation satisfying these criteria, we introduce the %\index{tactics!quote}%[quote] tactic and its associated library. *)
|
adamc@147
|
389
|
adamc@144
|
390 Require Import Quote.
|
adamc@144
|
391
|
adamc@148
|
392 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@144
|
393 Inductive formula : Set :=
|
adamc@144
|
394 | Atomic : index -> formula
|
adamc@144
|
395 | Truth : formula
|
adamc@144
|
396 | Falsehood : formula
|
adamc@144
|
397 | And : formula -> formula -> formula
|
adamc@144
|
398 | Or : formula -> formula -> formula
|
adamc@144
|
399 | Imp : formula -> formula -> formula.
|
adam@362
|
400 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@144
|
401
|
adam@360
|
402 (** The type %\index{Gallina terms!index}%[index] comes from the [Quote] library and represents a countable variable type. The rest of [formula]'s definition should be old hat by now.
|
adamc@147
|
403
|
adam@484
|
404 The [quote] tactic will implement injection from [Prop] into [formula] for us, but it is not quite as smart as we might like. In particular, it wants to treat function types specially, so it gets confused if function types are part of the structure we want to encode syntactically. To trick [quote] into not noticing our uses of function types to express logical implication, we will need to declare a wrapper definition for implication, as we did in the last chapter. *)
|
adamc@144
|
405
|
adamc@144
|
406 Definition imp (P1 P2 : Prop) := P1 -> P2.
|
adamc@144
|
407 Infix "-->" := imp (no associativity, at level 95).
|
adamc@144
|
408
|
adamc@147
|
409 (** Now we can define our denotation function. *)
|
adamc@147
|
410
|
adamc@147
|
411 Definition asgn := varmap Prop.
|
adamc@147
|
412
|
adam@362
|
413 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@144
|
414 Fixpoint formulaDenote (atomics : asgn) (f : formula) : Prop :=
|
adamc@144
|
415 match f with
|
adamc@144
|
416 | Atomic v => varmap_find False v atomics
|
adamc@144
|
417 | Truth => True
|
adamc@144
|
418 | Falsehood => False
|
adamc@144
|
419 | And f1 f2 => formulaDenote atomics f1 /\ formulaDenote atomics f2
|
adamc@144
|
420 | Or f1 f2 => formulaDenote atomics f1 \/ formulaDenote atomics f2
|
adamc@144
|
421 | Imp f1 f2 => formulaDenote atomics f1 --> formulaDenote atomics f2
|
adamc@144
|
422 end.
|
adam@362
|
423 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@144
|
424
|
adam@461
|
425 (** The %\index{Gallina terms!varmap}%[varmap] type family implements maps from [index] values. In this case, we define an assignment as a map from variables to [Prop]s. Our interpretation function [formulaDenote] works with an assignment, and we use the [varmap_find] function to consult the assignment in the [Atomic] case. The first argument to [varmap_find] is a default value, in case the variable is not found. *)
|
adamc@147
|
426
|
adamc@144
|
427 Section my_tauto.
|
adamc@144
|
428 Variable atomics : asgn.
|
adamc@144
|
429
|
adamc@144
|
430 Definition holds (v : index) := varmap_find False v atomics.
|
adamc@144
|
431
|
adamc@147
|
432 (** We define some shorthand for a particular variable being true, and now we are ready to define some helpful functions based on the [ListSet] module of the standard library, which (unsurprisingly) presents a view of lists as sets. *)
|
adamc@147
|
433
|
adamc@144
|
434 Require Import ListSet.
|
adamc@144
|
435
|
adamc@144
|
436 Definition index_eq : forall x y : index, {x = y} + {x <> y}.
|
adamc@144
|
437 decide equality.
|
adamc@144
|
438 Defined.
|
adamc@144
|
439
|
adamc@144
|
440 Definition add (s : set index) (v : index) := set_add index_eq v s.
|
adamc@147
|
441
|
adamc@221
|
442 Definition In_dec : forall v (s : set index), {In v s} + {~ In v s}.
|
adamc@221
|
443 Local Open Scope specif_scope.
|
adamc@144
|
444
|
adamc@221
|
445 intro; refine (fix F (s : set index) : {In v s} + {~ In v s} :=
|
adamc@221
|
446 match s with
|
adamc@144
|
447 | nil => No
|
adamc@144
|
448 | v' :: s' => index_eq v' v || F s'
|
adamc@144
|
449 end); crush.
|
adamc@144
|
450 Defined.
|
adamc@144
|
451
|
adamc@147
|
452 (** We define what it means for all members of an index set to represent true propositions, and we prove some lemmas about this notion. *)
|
adamc@147
|
453
|
adamc@144
|
454 Fixpoint allTrue (s : set index) : Prop :=
|
adamc@144
|
455 match s with
|
adamc@144
|
456 | nil => True
|
adamc@144
|
457 | v :: s' => holds v /\ allTrue s'
|
adamc@144
|
458 end.
|
adamc@144
|
459
|
adamc@144
|
460 Theorem allTrue_add : forall v s,
|
adamc@144
|
461 allTrue s
|
adamc@144
|
462 -> holds v
|
adamc@144
|
463 -> allTrue (add s v).
|
adamc@144
|
464 induction s; crush;
|
adamc@144
|
465 match goal with
|
adamc@144
|
466 | [ |- context[if ?E then _ else _] ] => destruct E
|
adamc@144
|
467 end; crush.
|
adamc@144
|
468 Qed.
|
adamc@144
|
469
|
adamc@144
|
470 Theorem allTrue_In : forall v s,
|
adamc@144
|
471 allTrue s
|
adamc@144
|
472 -> set_In v s
|
adamc@144
|
473 -> varmap_find False v atomics.
|
adamc@144
|
474 induction s; crush.
|
adamc@144
|
475 Qed.
|
adamc@144
|
476
|
adamc@144
|
477 Hint Resolve allTrue_add allTrue_In.
|
adamc@144
|
478
|
adamc@221
|
479 Local Open Scope partial_scope.
|
adamc@144
|
480
|
adam@484
|
481 (** Now we can write a function [forward] that implements deconstruction of hypotheses, expanding a compound formula into a set of sets of atomic formulas covering all possible cases introduced with use of [Or]. To handle consideration of multiple cases, the function takes in a continuation argument, which will be called once for each case.
|
adam@484
|
482
|
adam@484
|
483 The [forward] function has a dependent type, in the style of Chapter 6, guaranteeing correctness. The arguments to [forward] are a goal formula [f], a set [known] of atomic formulas that we may assume are true, a hypothesis formula [hyp], and a success continuation [cont] that we call when we have extended [known] to hold new truths implied by [hyp]. *)
|
adamc@147
|
484
|
adam@297
|
485 Definition forward : forall (f : formula) (known : set index) (hyp : formula)
|
adam@297
|
486 (cont : forall known', [allTrue known' -> formulaDenote atomics f]),
|
adam@297
|
487 [allTrue known -> formulaDenote atomics hyp -> formulaDenote atomics f].
|
adamc@144
|
488 refine (fix F (f : formula) (known : set index) (hyp : formula)
|
adamc@221
|
489 (cont : forall known', [allTrue known' -> formulaDenote atomics f])
|
adamc@144
|
490 : [allTrue known -> formulaDenote atomics hyp -> formulaDenote atomics f] :=
|
adamc@221
|
491 match hyp with
|
adamc@144
|
492 | Atomic v => Reduce (cont (add known v))
|
adamc@144
|
493 | Truth => Reduce (cont known)
|
adamc@144
|
494 | Falsehood => Yes
|
adamc@144
|
495 | And h1 h2 =>
|
adamc@144
|
496 Reduce (F (Imp h2 f) known h1 (fun known' =>
|
adamc@144
|
497 Reduce (F f known' h2 cont)))
|
adamc@144
|
498 | Or h1 h2 => F f known h1 cont && F f known h2 cont
|
adamc@144
|
499 | Imp _ _ => Reduce (cont known)
|
adamc@144
|
500 end); crush.
|
adamc@144
|
501 Defined.
|
adamc@144
|
502
|
adamc@147
|
503 (** A [backward] function implements analysis of the final goal. It calls [forward] to handle implications. *)
|
adamc@147
|
504
|
adam@362
|
505 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@297
|
506 Definition backward : forall (known : set index) (f : formula),
|
adam@297
|
507 [allTrue known -> formulaDenote atomics f].
|
adamc@221
|
508 refine (fix F (known : set index) (f : formula)
|
adamc@221
|
509 : [allTrue known -> formulaDenote atomics f] :=
|
adamc@221
|
510 match f with
|
adamc@144
|
511 | Atomic v => Reduce (In_dec v known)
|
adamc@144
|
512 | Truth => Yes
|
adamc@144
|
513 | Falsehood => No
|
adamc@144
|
514 | And f1 f2 => F known f1 && F known f2
|
adamc@144
|
515 | Or f1 f2 => F known f1 || F known f2
|
adamc@144
|
516 | Imp f1 f2 => forward f2 known f1 (fun known' => F known' f2)
|
adamc@144
|
517 end); crush; eauto.
|
adamc@144
|
518 Defined.
|
adam@362
|
519 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@144
|
520
|
adamc@147
|
521 (** A simple wrapper around [backward] gives us the usual type of a partial decision procedure. *)
|
adamc@147
|
522
|
adam@297
|
523 Definition my_tauto : forall f : formula, [formulaDenote atomics f].
|
adam@362
|
524 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@144
|
525 intro; refine (Reduce (backward nil f)); crush.
|
adamc@144
|
526 Defined.
|
adam@362
|
527 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@144
|
528 End my_tauto.
|
adamc@144
|
529
|
adam@360
|
530 (** Our final tactic implementation is now fairly straightforward. First, we [intro] all quantifiers that do not bind [Prop]s. Then we call the [quote] tactic, which implements the reification for us. Finally, we are able to construct an exact proof via [partialOut] and the [my_tauto] Gallina function. *)
|
adamc@147
|
531
|
adamc@144
|
532 Ltac my_tauto :=
|
adamc@144
|
533 repeat match goal with
|
adamc@144
|
534 | [ |- forall x : ?P, _ ] =>
|
adamc@144
|
535 match type of P with
|
adamc@144
|
536 | Prop => fail 1
|
adamc@144
|
537 | _ => intro
|
adamc@144
|
538 end
|
adamc@144
|
539 end;
|
adamc@144
|
540 quote formulaDenote;
|
adamc@144
|
541 match goal with
|
adamc@144
|
542 | [ |- formulaDenote ?m ?f ] => exact (partialOut (my_tauto m f))
|
adamc@144
|
543 end.
|
adamc@148
|
544 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@144
|
545
|
adamc@147
|
546 (** A few examples demonstrate how the tactic works. *)
|
adamc@147
|
547
|
adamc@144
|
548 Theorem mt1 : True.
|
adamc@144
|
549 my_tauto.
|
adamc@144
|
550 Qed.
|
adamc@144
|
551
|
adamc@144
|
552 Print mt1.
|
adamc@221
|
553 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@147
|
554 mt1 = partialOut (my_tauto (Empty_vm Prop) Truth)
|
adamc@147
|
555 : True
|
adamc@147
|
556 ]]
|
adamc@147
|
557
|
adamc@147
|
558 We see [my_tauto] applied with an empty [varmap], since every subformula is handled by [formulaDenote]. *)
|
adamc@144
|
559
|
adamc@144
|
560 Theorem mt2 : forall x y : nat, x = y --> x = y.
|
adamc@144
|
561 my_tauto.
|
adamc@144
|
562 Qed.
|
adamc@144
|
563
|
adam@432
|
564 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@437
|
565 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@432
|
566 Definition nvm := (Node_vm, Empty_vm, End_idx, Left_idx, Right_idx).
|
adam@437
|
567 (* end thide *)
|
adam@432
|
568 (* end hide *)
|
adam@432
|
569
|
adamc@144
|
570 Print mt2.
|
adamc@221
|
571 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@147
|
572 mt2 =
|
adamc@147
|
573 fun x y : nat =>
|
adamc@147
|
574 partialOut
|
adamc@147
|
575 (my_tauto (Node_vm (x = y) (Empty_vm Prop) (Empty_vm Prop))
|
adamc@147
|
576 (Imp (Atomic End_idx) (Atomic End_idx)))
|
adamc@147
|
577 : forall x y : nat, x = y --> x = y
|
adamc@147
|
578 ]]
|
adamc@147
|
579
|
adamc@147
|
580 Crucially, both instances of [x = y] are represented with the same index, [End_idx]. The value of this index only needs to appear once in the [varmap], whose form reveals that [varmap]s are represented as binary trees, where [index] values denote paths from tree roots to leaves. *)
|
adamc@144
|
581
|
adamc@144
|
582 Theorem mt3 : forall x y z,
|
adamc@144
|
583 (x < y /\ y > z) \/ (y > z /\ x < S y)
|
adamc@144
|
584 --> y > z /\ (x < y \/ x < S y).
|
adamc@144
|
585 my_tauto.
|
adamc@144
|
586 Qed.
|
adamc@144
|
587
|
adamc@144
|
588 Print mt3.
|
adamc@221
|
589 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@147
|
590 fun x y z : nat =>
|
adamc@147
|
591 partialOut
|
adamc@147
|
592 (my_tauto
|
adamc@147
|
593 (Node_vm (x < S y) (Node_vm (x < y) (Empty_vm Prop) (Empty_vm Prop))
|
adamc@147
|
594 (Node_vm (y > z) (Empty_vm Prop) (Empty_vm Prop)))
|
adamc@147
|
595 (Imp
|
adamc@147
|
596 (Or (And (Atomic (Left_idx End_idx)) (Atomic (Right_idx End_idx)))
|
adamc@147
|
597 (And (Atomic (Right_idx End_idx)) (Atomic End_idx)))
|
adamc@147
|
598 (And (Atomic (Right_idx End_idx))
|
adamc@147
|
599 (Or (Atomic (Left_idx End_idx)) (Atomic End_idx)))))
|
adamc@147
|
600 : forall x y z : nat,
|
adamc@147
|
601 x < y /\ y > z \/ y > z /\ x < S y --> y > z /\ (x < y \/ x < S y)
|
adamc@147
|
602 ]]
|
adamc@147
|
603
|
adamc@147
|
604 Our goal contained three distinct atomic formulas, and we see that a three-element [varmap] is generated.
|
adamc@147
|
605
|
adamc@147
|
606 It can be interesting to observe differences between the level of repetition in proof terms generated by [my_tauto] and [tauto] for especially trivial theorems. *)
|
adamc@144
|
607
|
adamc@144
|
608 Theorem mt4 : True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ False --> False.
|
adamc@144
|
609 my_tauto.
|
adamc@144
|
610 Qed.
|
adamc@144
|
611
|
adamc@144
|
612 Print mt4.
|
adamc@221
|
613 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@147
|
614 mt4 =
|
adamc@147
|
615 partialOut
|
adamc@147
|
616 (my_tauto (Empty_vm Prop)
|
adamc@147
|
617 (Imp
|
adamc@147
|
618 (And Truth
|
adamc@147
|
619 (And Truth
|
adamc@147
|
620 (And Truth (And Truth (And Truth (And Truth Falsehood))))))
|
adamc@147
|
621 Falsehood))
|
adamc@147
|
622 : True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ False --> False
|
adam@302
|
623 ]]
|
adam@302
|
624 *)
|
adamc@144
|
625
|
adamc@144
|
626 Theorem mt4' : True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ False -> False.
|
adamc@144
|
627 tauto.
|
adamc@144
|
628 Qed.
|
adamc@144
|
629
|
adam@432
|
630 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@437
|
631 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@432
|
632 Definition fi := False_ind.
|
adam@437
|
633 (* end thide *)
|
adam@432
|
634 (* end hide *)
|
adam@432
|
635
|
adamc@144
|
636 Print mt4'.
|
adamc@221
|
637 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@147
|
638 mt4' =
|
adamc@147
|
639 fun H : True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ False =>
|
adamc@147
|
640 and_ind
|
adamc@147
|
641 (fun (_ : True) (H1 : True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ False) =>
|
adamc@147
|
642 and_ind
|
adamc@147
|
643 (fun (_ : True) (H3 : True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ False) =>
|
adamc@147
|
644 and_ind
|
adamc@147
|
645 (fun (_ : True) (H5 : True /\ True /\ True /\ False) =>
|
adamc@147
|
646 and_ind
|
adamc@147
|
647 (fun (_ : True) (H7 : True /\ True /\ False) =>
|
adamc@147
|
648 and_ind
|
adamc@147
|
649 (fun (_ : True) (H9 : True /\ False) =>
|
adamc@147
|
650 and_ind (fun (_ : True) (H11 : False) => False_ind False H11)
|
adamc@147
|
651 H9) H7) H5) H3) H1) H
|
adamc@147
|
652 : True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ False -> False
|
adam@302
|
653 ]]
|
adam@360
|
654
|
adam@360
|
655 The traditional [tauto] tactic introduces a quadratic blow-up in the size of the proof term, whereas proofs produced by [my_tauto] always have linear size. *)
|
adamc@147
|
656
|
adam@361
|
657 (** ** Manual Reification of Terms with Variables *)
|
adam@361
|
658
|
adam@362
|
659 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@361
|
660 (** The action of the [quote] tactic above may seem like magic. Somehow it performs equality comparison between subterms of arbitrary types, so that these subterms may be represented with the same reified variable. While [quote] is implemented in OCaml, we can code the reification process completely in Ltac, as well. To make our job simpler, we will represent variables as [nat]s, indexing into a simple list of variable values that may be referenced.
|
adam@361
|
661
|
adam@485
|
662 Step one of the process is to crawl over a term, building a duplicate-free list of all values that appear in positions we will encode as variables. A useful helper function adds an element to a list, preventing duplicates. Note how we use Ltac pattern matching to implement an equality test on Gallina terms; this is simple syntactic equality, not even the richer definitional equality. We also represent lists as nested tuples, to allow different list elements to have different Gallina types. *)
|
adam@361
|
663
|
adam@361
|
664 Ltac inList x xs :=
|
adam@361
|
665 match xs with
|
adam@361
|
666 | tt => false
|
adam@361
|
667 | (x, _) => true
|
adam@361
|
668 | (_, ?xs') => inList x xs'
|
adam@361
|
669 end.
|
adam@361
|
670
|
adam@361
|
671 Ltac addToList x xs :=
|
adam@361
|
672 let b := inList x xs in
|
adam@361
|
673 match b with
|
adam@361
|
674 | true => xs
|
adam@361
|
675 | false => constr:(x, xs)
|
adam@361
|
676 end.
|
adam@361
|
677
|
adam@361
|
678 (** Now we can write our recursive function to calculate the list of variable values we will want to use to represent a term. *)
|
adam@361
|
679
|
adam@361
|
680 Ltac allVars xs e :=
|
adam@361
|
681 match e with
|
adam@361
|
682 | True => xs
|
adam@361
|
683 | False => xs
|
adam@361
|
684 | ?e1 /\ ?e2 =>
|
adam@361
|
685 let xs := allVars xs e1 in
|
adam@361
|
686 allVars xs e2
|
adam@361
|
687 | ?e1 \/ ?e2 =>
|
adam@361
|
688 let xs := allVars xs e1 in
|
adam@361
|
689 allVars xs e2
|
adam@361
|
690 | ?e1 -> ?e2 =>
|
adam@361
|
691 let xs := allVars xs e1 in
|
adam@361
|
692 allVars xs e2
|
adam@361
|
693 | _ => addToList e xs
|
adam@361
|
694 end.
|
adam@361
|
695
|
adam@361
|
696 (** We will also need a way to map a value to its position in a list. *)
|
adam@361
|
697
|
adam@361
|
698 Ltac lookup x xs :=
|
adam@361
|
699 match xs with
|
adam@361
|
700 | (x, _) => O
|
adam@361
|
701 | (_, ?xs') =>
|
adam@361
|
702 let n := lookup x xs' in
|
adam@361
|
703 constr:(S n)
|
adam@361
|
704 end.
|
adam@361
|
705
|
adam@461
|
706 (** The next building block is a procedure for reifying a term, given a list of all allowed variable values. We are free to make this procedure partial, where tactic failure may be triggered upon attempting to reify a term containing subterms not included in the list of variables. The type of the output term is a copy of [formula] where [index] is replaced by [nat], in the type of the constructor for atomic formulas. *)
|
adam@361
|
707
|
adam@361
|
708 Inductive formula' : Set :=
|
adam@361
|
709 | Atomic' : nat -> formula'
|
adam@361
|
710 | Truth' : formula'
|
adam@361
|
711 | Falsehood' : formula'
|
adam@361
|
712 | And' : formula' -> formula' -> formula'
|
adam@361
|
713 | Or' : formula' -> formula' -> formula'
|
adam@361
|
714 | Imp' : formula' -> formula' -> formula'.
|
adam@361
|
715
|
adam@361
|
716 (** Note that, when we write our own Ltac procedure, we can work directly with the normal [->] operator, rather than needing to introduce a wrapper for it. *)
|
adam@361
|
717
|
adam@361
|
718 Ltac reifyTerm xs e :=
|
adam@361
|
719 match e with
|
adam@432
|
720 | True => constr:Truth'
|
adam@432
|
721 | False => constr:Falsehood'
|
adam@361
|
722 | ?e1 /\ ?e2 =>
|
adam@361
|
723 let p1 := reifyTerm xs e1 in
|
adam@361
|
724 let p2 := reifyTerm xs e2 in
|
adam@361
|
725 constr:(And' p1 p2)
|
adam@361
|
726 | ?e1 \/ ?e2 =>
|
adam@361
|
727 let p1 := reifyTerm xs e1 in
|
adam@361
|
728 let p2 := reifyTerm xs e2 in
|
adam@361
|
729 constr:(Or' p1 p2)
|
adam@361
|
730 | ?e1 -> ?e2 =>
|
adam@361
|
731 let p1 := reifyTerm xs e1 in
|
adam@361
|
732 let p2 := reifyTerm xs e2 in
|
adam@361
|
733 constr:(Imp' p1 p2)
|
adam@361
|
734 | _ =>
|
adam@361
|
735 let n := lookup e xs in
|
adam@361
|
736 constr:(Atomic' n)
|
adam@361
|
737 end.
|
adam@361
|
738
|
adam@361
|
739 (** Finally, we bring all the pieces together. *)
|
adam@361
|
740
|
adam@361
|
741 Ltac reify :=
|
adam@361
|
742 match goal with
|
adam@361
|
743 | [ |- ?G ] => let xs := allVars tt G in
|
adam@361
|
744 let p := reifyTerm xs G in
|
adam@361
|
745 pose p
|
adam@361
|
746 end.
|
adam@361
|
747
|
adam@361
|
748 (** A quick test verifies that we are doing reification correctly. *)
|
adam@361
|
749
|
adam@361
|
750 Theorem mt3' : forall x y z,
|
adam@361
|
751 (x < y /\ y > z) \/ (y > z /\ x < S y)
|
adam@361
|
752 -> y > z /\ (x < y \/ x < S y).
|
adam@361
|
753 do 3 intro; reify.
|
adam@361
|
754
|
adam@361
|
755 (** Our simple tactic adds the translated term as a new variable:
|
adam@361
|
756 [[
|
adam@361
|
757 f := Imp'
|
adam@361
|
758 (Or' (And' (Atomic' 2) (Atomic' 1)) (And' (Atomic' 1) (Atomic' 0)))
|
adam@361
|
759 (And' (Atomic' 1) (Or' (Atomic' 2) (Atomic' 0))) : formula'
|
adam@361
|
760 ]]
|
adam@361
|
761 *)
|
adam@361
|
762 Abort.
|
adam@361
|
763
|
adam@361
|
764 (** More work would be needed to complete the reflective tactic, as we must connect our new syntax type with the real meanings of formulas, but the details are the same as in our prior implementation with [quote]. *)
|
adam@362
|
765 (* end thide *)
|
adam@378
|
766
|
adam@378
|
767
|
adam@378
|
768 (** * Building a Reification Tactic that Recurses Under Binders *)
|
adam@378
|
769
|
adam@378
|
770 (** All of our examples so far have stayed away from reifying the syntax of terms that use such features as quantifiers and [fun] function abstractions. Such cases are complicated by the fact that different subterms may be allowed to reference different sets of free variables. Some cleverness is needed to clear this hurdle, but a few simple patterns will suffice. Consider this example of a simple dependently typed term language, where a function abstraction body is represented conveniently with a Coq function. *)
|
adam@378
|
771
|
adam@378
|
772 Inductive type : Type :=
|
adam@378
|
773 | Nat : type
|
adam@378
|
774 | NatFunc : type -> type.
|
adam@378
|
775
|
adam@378
|
776 Inductive term : type -> Type :=
|
adam@378
|
777 | Const : nat -> term Nat
|
adam@378
|
778 | Plus : term Nat -> term Nat -> term Nat
|
adam@378
|
779 | Abs : forall t, (nat -> term t) -> term (NatFunc t).
|
adam@378
|
780
|
adam@378
|
781 Fixpoint typeDenote (t : type) : Type :=
|
adam@378
|
782 match t with
|
adam@378
|
783 | Nat => nat
|
adam@378
|
784 | NatFunc t => nat -> typeDenote t
|
adam@378
|
785 end.
|
adam@378
|
786
|
adam@378
|
787 Fixpoint termDenote t (e : term t) : typeDenote t :=
|
adam@378
|
788 match e with
|
adam@378
|
789 | Const n => n
|
adam@378
|
790 | Plus e1 e2 => termDenote e1 + termDenote e2
|
adam@378
|
791 | Abs _ e1 => fun x => termDenote (e1 x)
|
adam@378
|
792 end.
|
adam@378
|
793
|
adam@484
|
794 (** Here is a %\%naive%{}% first attempt at a reification tactic. *)
|
adam@378
|
795
|
adam@378
|
796 Ltac refl' e :=
|
adam@378
|
797 match e with
|
adam@378
|
798 | ?E1 + ?E2 =>
|
adam@378
|
799 let r1 := refl' E1 in
|
adam@378
|
800 let r2 := refl' E2 in
|
adam@378
|
801 constr:(Plus r1 r2)
|
adam@378
|
802
|
adam@378
|
803 | fun x : nat => ?E1 =>
|
adam@378
|
804 let r1 := refl' E1 in
|
adam@378
|
805 constr:(Abs (fun x => r1 x))
|
adam@378
|
806
|
adam@378
|
807 | _ => constr:(Const e)
|
adam@378
|
808 end.
|
adam@378
|
809
|
adam@484
|
810 (** Recall that a regular Ltac pattern variable [?X] only matches terms that _do not mention new variables introduced within the pattern_. In our %\%naive%{}% implementation, the case for matching function abstractions matches the function body in a way that prevents it from mentioning the function argument! Our code above plays fast and loose with the function body in a way that leads to independent problems, but we could change the code so that it indeed handles function abstractions that ignore their arguments.
|
adam@378
|
811
|
adam@484
|
812 To handle functions in general, we will use the pattern variable form [@?X], which allows [X] to mention newly introduced variables that are declared explicitly. A use of [@?X] must be followed by a list of the local variables that may be mentioned. The variable [X] then comes to stand for a Gallina function over the values of those variables. For instance: *)
|
adam@378
|
813
|
adam@378
|
814 Reset refl'.
|
adam@378
|
815 Ltac refl' e :=
|
adam@378
|
816 match e with
|
adam@378
|
817 | ?E1 + ?E2 =>
|
adam@378
|
818 let r1 := refl' E1 in
|
adam@378
|
819 let r2 := refl' E2 in
|
adam@378
|
820 constr:(Plus r1 r2)
|
adam@378
|
821
|
adam@378
|
822 | fun x : nat => @?E1 x =>
|
adam@378
|
823 let r1 := refl' E1 in
|
adam@378
|
824 constr:(Abs r1)
|
adam@378
|
825
|
adam@378
|
826 | _ => constr:(Const e)
|
adam@378
|
827 end.
|
adam@378
|
828
|
adam@398
|
829 (** Now, in the abstraction case, we bind [E1] as a function from an [x] value to the value of the abstraction body. Unfortunately, our recursive call there is not destined for success. It will match the same abstraction pattern and trigger another recursive call, and so on through infinite recursion. One last refactoring yields a working procedure. The key idea is to consider every input to [refl'] as _a function over the values of variables introduced during recursion_. *)
|
adam@378
|
830
|
adam@378
|
831 Reset refl'.
|
adam@378
|
832 Ltac refl' e :=
|
adam@378
|
833 match eval simpl in e with
|
adam@378
|
834 | fun x : ?T => @?E1 x + @?E2 x =>
|
adam@378
|
835 let r1 := refl' E1 in
|
adam@378
|
836 let r2 := refl' E2 in
|
adam@378
|
837 constr:(fun x => Plus (r1 x) (r2 x))
|
adam@378
|
838
|
adam@378
|
839 | fun (x : ?T) (y : nat) => @?E1 x y =>
|
adam@378
|
840 let r1 := refl' (fun p : T * nat => E1 (fst p) (snd p)) in
|
adam@378
|
841 constr:(fun x => Abs (fun y => r1 (x, y)))
|
adam@378
|
842
|
adam@378
|
843 | _ => constr:(fun x => Const (e x))
|
adam@378
|
844 end.
|
adam@378
|
845
|
adam@378
|
846 (** Note how now even the addition case works in terms of functions, with [@?X] patterns. The abstraction case introduces a new variable by extending the type used to represent the free variables. In particular, the argument to [refl'] used type [T] to represent all free variables. We extend the type to [T * nat] for the type representing free variable values within the abstraction body. A bit of bookkeeping with pairs and their projections produces an appropriate version of the abstraction body to pass in a recursive call. To ensure that all this repackaging of terms does not interfere with pattern matching, we add an extra [simpl] reduction on the function argument, in the first line of the body of [refl'].
|
adam@378
|
847
|
adam@378
|
848 Now one more tactic provides an example of how to apply reification. Let us consider goals that are equalities between terms that can be reified. We want to change such goals into equalities between appropriate calls to [termDenote]. *)
|
adam@378
|
849
|
adam@378
|
850 Ltac refl :=
|
adam@378
|
851 match goal with
|
adam@378
|
852 | [ |- ?E1 = ?E2 ] =>
|
adam@378
|
853 let E1' := refl' (fun _ : unit => E1) in
|
adam@378
|
854 let E2' := refl' (fun _ : unit => E2) in
|
adam@378
|
855 change (termDenote (E1' tt) = termDenote (E2' tt));
|
adam@378
|
856 cbv beta iota delta [fst snd]
|
adam@378
|
857 end.
|
adam@378
|
858
|
adam@378
|
859 Goal (fun (x y : nat) => x + y + 13) = (fun (_ z : nat) => z).
|
adam@378
|
860 refl.
|
adam@378
|
861 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@378
|
862 ============================
|
adam@378
|
863 termDenote
|
adam@378
|
864 (Abs
|
adam@378
|
865 (fun y : nat =>
|
adam@378
|
866 Abs (fun y0 : nat => Plus (Plus (Const y) (Const y0)) (Const 13)))) =
|
adam@378
|
867 termDenote (Abs (fun _ : nat => Abs (fun y0 : nat => Const y0)))
|
adam@378
|
868 ]]
|
adam@378
|
869 *)
|
adam@378
|
870
|
adam@378
|
871 Abort.
|
adam@378
|
872
|
adam@484
|
873 (** Our encoding here uses Coq functions to represent binding within the terms we reify, which makes it difficult to implement certain functions over reified terms. An alternative would be to represent variables with numbers. This can be done by writing a slightly smarter reification function that identifies variable references by detecting when term arguments are just compositions of [fst] and [snd]; from the order of the compositions we may read off the variable number. We leave the details as an exercise (though not a trivial one!) for the reader. *)
|