annotate src/Predicates.v @ 499:2d7ce9e011f4

Pass through Chapter 8
author Adam Chlipala <adam@chlipala.net>
date Fri, 01 Feb 2013 17:19:15 -0500
parents 07f2fb4d9b36
children 8303abe4a61f
rev   line source
adam@394 1 (* Copyright (c) 2008-2012, Adam Chlipala
adamc@45 2 *
adamc@45 3 * This work is licensed under a
adamc@45 4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
adamc@45 5 * Unported License.
adamc@45 6 * The license text is available at:
adamc@45 7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
adamc@45 8 *)
adamc@45 9
adamc@45 10 (* begin hide *)
adamc@45 11 Require Import List.
adamc@45 12
adam@314 13 Require Import CpdtTactics.
adamc@45 14
adamc@45 15 Set Implicit Arguments.
adam@322 16
adam@322 17 (* Extra definitions to get coqdoc to choose the right fonts. *)
adam@322 18
adam@323 19 (* begin thide *)
adam@322 20 Inductive unit := tt.
adam@322 21 Inductive Empty_set := .
adam@322 22 Inductive bool := true | false.
adam@322 23 Inductive sum := .
adam@322 24 Inductive prod := .
adam@322 25 Inductive and := conj.
adam@322 26 Inductive or := or_introl | or_intror.
adam@322 27 Inductive ex := ex_intro.
adam@426 28 Inductive eq := eq_refl.
adam@322 29 Reset unit.
adam@323 30 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 31 (* end hide *)
adamc@45 32
adamc@45 33 (** %\chapter{Inductive Predicates}% *)
adamc@45 34
adam@322 35 (** The so-called %\index{Curry-Howard correspondence}``%#"#Curry-Howard correspondence#"#%''~\cite{Curry,Howard}% states a formal connection between functional programs and mathematical proofs. In the last chapter, we snuck in a first introduction to this subject in Coq. Witness the close similarity between the types [unit] and [True] from the standard library: *)
adamc@45 36
adamc@45 37 Print unit.
adam@440 38 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adamc@209 39 Inductive unit : Set := tt : unit
adam@302 40 ]]
adam@302 41 *)
adamc@45 42
adamc@45 43 Print True.
adam@440 44 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adamc@209 45 Inductive True : Prop := I : True
adam@322 46 ]]
adamc@45 47
adam@442 48 Recall that [unit] is the type with only one value, and [True] is the proposition that always holds. Despite this superficial difference between the two concepts, in both cases we can use the same inductive definition mechanism. The connection goes further than this. We see that we arrive at the definition of [True] by replacing [unit] by [True], [tt] by [I], and [Set] by [Prop]. The first two of these differences are superficial changes of names, while the third difference is the crucial one for separating programs from proofs. A term [T] of type [Set] is a type of programs, and a term of type [T] is a program. A term [T] of type [Prop] is a logical proposition, and its proofs are of type [T]. Chapter 12 goes into more detail about the theoretical differences between [Prop] and [Set]. For now, we will simply follow common intuitions about what a proof is.
adamc@45 49
adam@475 50 The type [unit] has one value, [tt]. The type [True] has one proof, [I]. Why distinguish between these two types? Many people who have read about Curry-Howard in an abstract context but who have not put it to use in proof engineering answer that the two types in fact _should not_ be distinguished. There is a certain aesthetic appeal to this point of view, but I want to argue that it is best to treat Curry-Howard very loosely in practical proving. There are Coq-specific reasons for preferring the distinction, involving efficient compilation and avoidance of paradoxes in the presence of classical math, but I will argue that there is a more general principle that should lead us to avoid conflating programming and proving.
adamc@45 51
adam@401 52 The essence of the argument is roughly this: to an engineer, not all functions of type [A -> B] are created equal, but all proofs of a proposition [P -> Q] are. This idea is known as%\index{proof irrelevance}% _proof irrelevance_, and its formalizations in logics prevent us from distinguishing between alternate proofs of the same proposition. Proof irrelevance is compatible with, but not derivable in, Gallina. Apart from this theoretical concern, I will argue that it is most effective to do engineering with Coq by employing different techniques for programs versus proofs. Most of this book is organized around that distinction, describing how to program, by applying standard functional programming techniques in the presence of dependent types; and how to prove, by writing custom Ltac decision procedures.
adamc@45 53
adam@421 54 With that perspective in mind, this chapter is sort of a mirror image of the last chapter, introducing how to define predicates with inductive definitions. We will point out similarities in places, but much of the effective Coq user's bag of tricks is disjoint for predicates versus "datatypes." This chapter is also a covert introduction to dependent types, which are the foundation on which interesting inductive predicates are built, though we will rely on tactics to build dependently typed proof terms for us for now. A future chapter introduces more manual application of dependent types. *)
adamc@45 55
adamc@45 56
adamc@48 57 (** * Propositional Logic *)
adamc@45 58
adam@471 59 (** Let us begin with a brief tour through the definitions of the connectives for propositional logic. We will work within a Coq section that provides us with a set of propositional variables. In Coq parlance, these are just variables of type [Prop]. *)
adamc@45 60
adamc@45 61 Section Propositional.
adamc@46 62 Variables P Q R : Prop.
adamc@45 63
adamc@45 64 (** In Coq, the most basic propositional connective is implication, written [->], which we have already used in almost every proof. Rather than being defined inductively, implication is built into Coq as the function type constructor.
adamc@45 65
adamc@45 66 We have also already seen the definition of [True]. For a demonstration of a lower-level way of establishing proofs of inductive predicates, we turn to this trivial theorem. *)
adamc@45 67
adamc@45 68 Theorem obvious : True.
adamc@55 69 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 70 apply I.
adamc@55 71 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 72 Qed.
adamc@45 73
adam@401 74 (** We may always use the [apply] tactic to take a proof step based on applying a particular constructor of the inductive predicate that we are trying to establish. Sometimes there is only one constructor that could possibly apply, in which case a shortcut is available:%\index{tactics!constructor}% *)
adamc@45 75
adamc@55 76 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 77 Theorem obvious' : True.
adamc@45 78 constructor.
adamc@45 79 Qed.
adamc@45 80
adamc@55 81 (* end thide *)
adamc@55 82
adamc@45 83 (** There is also a predicate [False], which is the Curry-Howard mirror image of [Empty_set] from the last chapter. *)
adamc@45 84
adamc@45 85 Print False.
adam@440 86 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adamc@209 87 Inductive False : Prop :=
adamc@209 88 ]]
adamc@45 89
adam@442 90 We can conclude anything from [False], doing case analysis on a proof of [False] in the same way we might do case analysis on, say, a natural number. Since there are no cases to consider, any such case analysis succeeds immediately in proving the goal. *)
adamc@45 91
adamc@45 92 Theorem False_imp : False -> 2 + 2 = 5.
adamc@55 93 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 94 destruct 1.
adamc@55 95 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 96 Qed.
adamc@45 97
adam@449 98 (** In a consistent context, we can never build a proof of [False]. In inconsistent contexts that appear in the courses of proofs, it is usually easiest to proceed by demonstrating the inconsistency with an explicit proof of [False]. *)
adamc@45 99
adamc@45 100 Theorem arith_neq : 2 + 2 = 5 -> 9 + 9 = 835.
adamc@55 101 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 102 intro.
adamc@45 103
adam@471 104 (** At this point, we have an inconsistent hypothesis [2 + 2 = 5], so the specific conclusion is not important. We use the %\index{tactics!elimtype}%[elimtype] tactic. For a full description of it, see the Coq manual. For our purposes, we only need the variant [elimtype False], which lets us replace any conclusion formula with [False], because any fact follows from an inconsistent context. *)
adamc@45 105
adamc@45 106 elimtype False.
adamc@45 107 (** [[
adamc@45 108 H : 2 + 2 = 5
adamc@45 109 ============================
adamc@45 110 False
adamc@209 111
adamc@209 112 ]]
adamc@45 113
adamc@209 114 For now, we will leave the details of this proof about arithmetic to [crush]. *)
adamc@45 115
adamc@45 116 crush.
adamc@55 117 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 118 Qed.
adamc@45 119
adamc@45 120 (** A related notion to [False] is logical negation. *)
adamc@45 121
adam@421 122 (* begin hide *)
adam@421 123 Definition foo := not.
adam@421 124 (* end hide *)
adam@421 125
adamc@45 126 Print not.
adamc@209 127 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@209 128 not = fun A : Prop => A -> False
adamc@209 129 : Prop -> Prop
adamc@209 130 ]]
adamc@45 131
adam@488 132 We see that [not] is just shorthand for implication of [False]. We can use that fact explicitly in proofs. The syntax [~ P] %(written with a tilde in ASCII)% expands to [not P]. *)
adamc@45 133
adamc@45 134 Theorem arith_neq' : ~ (2 + 2 = 5).
adamc@55 135 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 136 unfold not.
adamc@45 137 (** [[
adamc@45 138 ============================
adamc@45 139 2 + 2 = 5 -> False
adam@302 140 ]]
adam@302 141 *)
adamc@45 142
adamc@45 143 crush.
adamc@55 144 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 145 Qed.
adamc@45 146
adamc@45 147 (** We also have conjunction, which we introduced in the last chapter. *)
adamc@45 148
adamc@45 149 Print and.
adam@440 150 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adam@322 151 Inductive and (A : Prop) (B : Prop) : Prop := conj : A -> B -> A /\ B
adamc@209 152 ]]
adamc@209 153
adam@442 154 The interested reader can check that [and] has a Curry-Howard equivalent called %\index{Gallina terms!prod}%[prod], the type of pairs. However, it is generally most convenient to reason about conjunction using tactics. An explicit proof of commutativity of [and] illustrates the usual suspects for such tasks. The operator [/\] is an infix shorthand for [and]. *)
adamc@45 155
adamc@45 156 Theorem and_comm : P /\ Q -> Q /\ P.
adamc@209 157
adamc@55 158 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 159 (** We start by case analysis on the proof of [P /\ Q]. *)
adamc@45 160
adamc@45 161 destruct 1.
adamc@45 162 (** [[
adamc@45 163 H : P
adamc@45 164 H0 : Q
adamc@45 165 ============================
adamc@45 166 Q /\ P
adamc@209 167
adamc@209 168 ]]
adamc@45 169
adam@322 170 Every proof of a conjunction provides proofs for both conjuncts, so we get a single subgoal reflecting that. We can proceed by splitting this subgoal into a case for each conjunct of [Q /\ P].%\index{tactics!split}% *)
adamc@45 171
adamc@45 172 split.
adam@440 173 (** [[
adam@440 174 2 subgoals
adamc@45 175
adamc@45 176 H : P
adamc@45 177 H0 : Q
adamc@45 178 ============================
adamc@45 179 Q
adam@439 180
adam@439 181 subgoal 2 is
adam@439 182
adam@322 183 P
adamc@209 184
adamc@209 185 ]]
adamc@45 186
adam@322 187 In each case, the conclusion is among our hypotheses, so the %\index{tactics!assumption}%[assumption] tactic finishes the process. *)
adamc@45 188
adamc@45 189 assumption.
adamc@45 190 assumption.
adamc@55 191 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 192 Qed.
adamc@45 193
adam@322 194 (** Coq disjunction is called %\index{Gallina terms!or}%[or] and abbreviated with the infix operator [\/]. *)
adamc@45 195
adamc@45 196 Print or.
adam@440 197 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adamc@209 198 Inductive or (A : Prop) (B : Prop) : Prop :=
adamc@209 199 or_introl : A -> A \/ B | or_intror : B -> A \/ B
adamc@209 200 ]]
adamc@45 201
adam@449 202 We see that there are two ways to prove a disjunction: prove the first disjunct or prove the second. The Curry-Howard analogue of this is the Coq %\index{Gallina terms!sum}%[sum] type. We can demonstrate the main tactics here with another proof of commutativity. *)
adamc@45 203
adamc@45 204 Theorem or_comm : P \/ Q -> Q \/ P.
adamc@55 205
adamc@55 206 (* begin thide *)
adamc@45 207 (** As in the proof for [and], we begin with case analysis, though this time we are met by two cases instead of one. *)
adamc@209 208
adamc@45 209 destruct 1.
adam@439 210 (** [[
adam@439 211 2 subgoals
adamc@45 212
adamc@45 213 H : P
adamc@45 214 ============================
adamc@45 215 Q \/ P
adam@439 216
adam@439 217 subgoal 2 is
adam@439 218
adamc@45 219 Q \/ P
adamc@209 220
adamc@209 221 ]]
adamc@45 222
adam@401 223 We can see that, in the first subgoal, we want to prove the disjunction by proving its second disjunct. The %\index{tactics!right}%[right] tactic telegraphs this intent. *)
adam@322 224
adamc@45 225 right; assumption.
adamc@45 226
adam@322 227 (** The second subgoal has a symmetric proof.%\index{tactics!left}%
adamc@45 228
adamc@45 229 [[
adamc@45 230 1 subgoal
adamc@45 231
adamc@45 232 H : Q
adamc@45 233 ============================
adamc@45 234 Q \/ P
adam@302 235 ]]
adam@302 236 *)
adamc@45 237
adamc@45 238 left; assumption.
adam@322 239
adamc@55 240 (* end thide *)
adamc@45 241 Qed.
adamc@45 242
adamc@46 243
adamc@46 244 (* begin hide *)
adamc@46 245 (* In-class exercises *)
adamc@46 246
adamc@46 247 Theorem contra : P -> ~P -> R.
adamc@52 248 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 249 unfold not.
adamc@52 250 intros.
adamc@52 251 elimtype False.
adamc@52 252 apply H0.
adamc@52 253 assumption.
adamc@52 254 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 255 Admitted.
adamc@46 256
adamc@46 257 Theorem and_assoc : (P /\ Q) /\ R -> P /\ (Q /\ R).
adamc@52 258 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 259 intros.
adamc@52 260 destruct H.
adamc@52 261 destruct H.
adamc@52 262 split.
adamc@52 263 assumption.
adamc@52 264 split.
adamc@52 265 assumption.
adamc@52 266 assumption.
adamc@52 267 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 268 Admitted.
adamc@46 269
adamc@46 270 Theorem or_assoc : (P \/ Q) \/ R -> P \/ (Q \/ R).
adamc@52 271 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 272 intros.
adamc@52 273 destruct H.
adamc@52 274 destruct H.
adamc@52 275 left.
adamc@52 276 assumption.
adamc@52 277 right.
adamc@52 278 left.
adamc@52 279 assumption.
adamc@52 280 right.
adamc@52 281 right.
adamc@52 282 assumption.
adamc@52 283 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 284 Admitted.
adamc@46 285
adamc@46 286 (* end hide *)
adamc@46 287
adamc@46 288
adam@421 289 (** It would be a shame to have to plod manually through all proofs about propositional logic. Luckily, there is no need. One of the most basic Coq automation tactics is %\index{tactics!tauto}%[tauto], which is a complete decision procedure for constructive propositional logic. (More on what "constructive" means in the next section.) We can use [tauto] to dispatch all of the purely propositional theorems we have proved so far. *)
adamc@46 290
adamc@46 291 Theorem or_comm' : P \/ Q -> Q \/ P.
adamc@55 292 (* begin thide *)
adamc@46 293 tauto.
adamc@55 294 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 295 Qed.
adamc@46 296
adam@471 297 (** Sometimes propositional reasoning forms important plumbing for the proof of a theorem, but we still need to apply some other smarts about, say, arithmetic. The tactic %\index{tactics!intuition}%[intuition] is a generalization of [tauto] that proves everything it can using propositional reasoning. When some further facts must be established to finish the proof, [intuition] uses propositional laws to simplify them as far as possible. Consider this example, which uses the list concatenation operator %\coqdocnotation{%#<tt>#++#</tt>#%}% from the standard library. *)
adamc@46 298
adamc@46 299 Theorem arith_comm : forall ls1 ls2 : list nat,
adamc@46 300 length ls1 = length ls2 \/ length ls1 + length ls2 = 6
adamc@46 301 -> length (ls1 ++ ls2) = 6 \/ length ls1 = length ls2.
adamc@55 302 (* begin thide *)
adamc@46 303 intuition.
adamc@46 304
adamc@46 305 (** A lot of the proof structure has been generated for us by [intuition], but the final proof depends on a fact about lists. The remaining subgoal hints at what cleverness we need to inject. *)
adamc@46 306
adamc@46 307 (** [[
adamc@46 308 ls1 : list nat
adamc@46 309 ls2 : list nat
adamc@46 310 H0 : length ls1 + length ls2 = 6
adamc@46 311 ============================
adamc@46 312 length (ls1 ++ ls2) = 6 \/ length ls1 = length ls2
adamc@209 313
adamc@209 314 ]]
adamc@46 315
adamc@209 316 We can see that we need a theorem about lengths of concatenated lists, which we proved last chapter and is also in the standard library. *)
adamc@46 317
adamc@46 318 rewrite app_length.
adamc@46 319 (** [[
adamc@46 320 ls1 : list nat
adamc@46 321 ls2 : list nat
adamc@46 322 H0 : length ls1 + length ls2 = 6
adamc@46 323 ============================
adamc@46 324 length ls1 + length ls2 = 6 \/ length ls1 = length ls2
adamc@209 325
adamc@209 326 ]]
adamc@46 327
adamc@209 328 Now the subgoal follows by purely propositional reasoning. That is, we could replace [length ls1 + length ls2 = 6] with [P] and [length ls1 = length ls2] with [Q] and arrive at a tautology of propositional logic. *)
adamc@46 329
adamc@46 330 tauto.
adamc@55 331 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 332 Qed.
adamc@46 333
adam@322 334 (** The [intuition] tactic is one of the main bits of glue in the implementation of [crush], so, with a little help, we can get a short automated proof of the theorem. *)
adamc@46 335
adamc@55 336 (* begin thide *)
adamc@46 337 Theorem arith_comm' : forall ls1 ls2 : list nat,
adamc@46 338 length ls1 = length ls2 \/ length ls1 + length ls2 = 6
adamc@46 339 -> length (ls1 ++ ls2) = 6 \/ length ls1 = length ls2.
adam@375 340 Hint Rewrite app_length.
adamc@46 341
adamc@46 342 crush.
adamc@46 343 Qed.
adamc@55 344 (* end thide *)
adamc@46 345
adamc@45 346 End Propositional.
adamc@45 347
adam@322 348 (** Ending the section here has the same effect as always. Each of our propositional theorems becomes universally quantified over the propositional variables that we used. *)
adam@322 349
adamc@46 350
adamc@47 351 (** * What Does It Mean to Be Constructive? *)
adamc@46 352
adam@471 353 (** One potential point of confusion in the presentation so far is the distinction between [bool] and [Prop]. The datatype [bool] is built from two values [true] and [false], while [Prop] is a more primitive type that includes among its members [True] and [False]. Why not collapse these two concepts into one, and why must there be more than two states of mathematical truth, [True] and [False]?
adamc@46 354
adam@421 355 The answer comes from the fact that Coq implements%\index{constructive logic}% _constructive_ or%\index{intuitionistic logic|see{constructive logic}}% _intuitionistic_ logic, in contrast to the%\index{classical logic}% _classical_ logic that you may be more familiar with. In constructive logic, classical tautologies like [~ ~ P -> P] and [P \/ ~ P] do not always hold. In general, we can only prove these tautologies when [P] is%\index{decidability}% _decidable_, in the sense of %\index{computability|see{decidability}}%computability theory. The Curry-Howard encoding that Coq uses for [or] allows us to extract either a proof of [P] or a proof of [~ P] from any proof of [P \/ ~ P]. Since our proofs are just functional programs which we can run, a general %\index{law of the excluded middle}%law of the excluded middle would give us a decision procedure for the halting problem, where the instantiations of [P] would be formulas like "this particular Turing machine halts."
adamc@47 356
adam@471 357 A similar paradoxical situation would result if every proposition evaluated to either [True] or [False]. Evaluation in Coq is decidable, so we would be limiting ourselves to decidable propositions only.
adam@471 358
adam@421 359 Hence the distinction between [bool] and [Prop]. Programs of type [bool] are computational by construction; we can always run them to determine their results. Many [Prop]s are undecidable, and so we can write more expressive formulas with [Prop]s than with [bool]s, but the inevitable consequence is that we cannot simply "run a [Prop] to determine its truth."
adamc@47 360
adam@401 361 Constructive logic lets us define all of the logical connectives in an aesthetically appealing way, with orthogonal inductive definitions. That is, each connective is defined independently using a simple, shared mechanism. Constructivity also enables a trick called%\index{program extraction}% _program extraction_, where we write programs by phrasing them as theorems to be proved. Since our proofs are just functional programs, we can extract executable programs from our final proofs, which we could not do as naturally with classical proofs.
adamc@47 362
adamc@47 363 We will see more about Coq's program extraction facility in a later chapter. However, I think it is worth interjecting another warning at this point, following up on the prior warning about taking the Curry-Howard correspondence too literally. It is possible to write programs by theorem-proving methods in Coq, but hardly anyone does it. It is almost always most useful to maintain the distinction between programs and proofs. If you write a program by proving a theorem, you are likely to run into algorithmic inefficiencies that you introduced in your proof to make it easier to prove. It is a shame to have to worry about such situations while proving tricky theorems, and it is a happy state of affairs that you almost certainly will not need to, with the ideal of extracting programs from proofs being confined mostly to theoretical studies. *)
adamc@48 364
adamc@48 365
adamc@48 366 (** * First-Order Logic *)
adamc@48 367
adam@421 368 (** The %\index{Gallina terms!forall}%[forall] connective of first-order logic, which we have seen in many examples so far, is built into Coq. Getting ahead of ourselves a bit, we can see it as the dependent function type constructor. In fact, implication and universal quantification are just different syntactic shorthands for the same Coq mechanism. A formula [P -> Q] is equivalent to [forall x : P, Q], where [x] does not appear in [Q]. That is, the "real" type of the implication says "for every proof of [P], there exists a proof of [Q]."
adamc@48 369
adam@322 370 %\index{existential quantification}\index{Gallina terms!exists}\index{Gallina terms!ex}%Existential quantification is defined in the standard library. *)
adamc@48 371
adam@322 372 Print ex.
adam@440 373 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adamc@209 374 Inductive ex (A : Type) (P : A -> Prop) : Prop :=
adamc@209 375 ex_intro : forall x : A, P x -> ex P
adamc@209 376 ]]
adamc@48 377
adam@469 378 (Note that here, as always, each [forall] quantifier has the largest possible scope, so that the type of [ex_intro] could also be written [forall x : A, (P x -> ex P)].)
adam@469 379
adam@471 380 The family [ex] is parameterized by the type [A] that we quantify over, and by a predicate [P] over [A]s. We prove an existential by exhibiting some [x] of type [A], along with a proof of [P x]. As usual, there are tactics that save us from worrying about the low-level details most of the time.
adam@471 381
adam@471 382 Here is an example of a theorem statement with existential quantification. We use the equality operator [=], which, depending on the settings in which they learned logic, different people will say either is or is not part of first-order logic. For our purposes, it is. *)
adamc@48 383
adamc@48 384 Theorem exist1 : exists x : nat, x + 1 = 2.
adamc@55 385 (* begin thide *)
adamc@67 386 (** remove printing exists *)
adam@470 387 (** We can start this proof with a tactic %\index{tactics!exists}%[exists], which should not be confused with the formula constructor shorthand of the same name. %In the version of this document that you are reading, the reverse ``E'' appears instead of the text ``exists'' in formulas.% *)
adamc@209 388
adamc@48 389 exists 1.
adamc@48 390
adamc@209 391 (** The conclusion is replaced with a version using the existential witness that we announced.
adamc@48 392
adamc@209 393 [[
adamc@48 394 ============================
adamc@48 395 1 + 1 = 2
adam@302 396 ]]
adam@302 397 *)
adamc@48 398
adamc@48 399 reflexivity.
adamc@55 400 (* end thide *)
adamc@48 401 Qed.
adamc@48 402
adamc@48 403 (** printing exists $\exists$ *)
adamc@48 404
adamc@48 405 (** We can also use tactics to reason about existential hypotheses. *)
adamc@48 406
adamc@48 407 Theorem exist2 : forall n m : nat, (exists x : nat, n + x = m) -> n <= m.
adamc@55 408 (* begin thide *)
adamc@48 409 (** We start by case analysis on the proof of the existential fact. *)
adamc@209 410
adamc@48 411 destruct 1.
adamc@48 412 (** [[
adamc@48 413 n : nat
adamc@48 414 m : nat
adamc@48 415 x : nat
adamc@48 416 H : n + x = m
adamc@48 417 ============================
adamc@48 418 n <= m
adamc@209 419
adamc@209 420 ]]
adamc@48 421
adamc@209 422 The goal has been replaced by a form where there is a new free variable [x], and where we have a new hypothesis that the body of the existential holds with [x] substituted for the old bound variable. From here, the proof is just about arithmetic and is easy to automate. *)
adamc@48 423
adamc@48 424 crush.
adamc@55 425 (* end thide *)
adamc@48 426 Qed.
adamc@48 427
adamc@48 428
adamc@48 429 (* begin hide *)
adamc@48 430 (* In-class exercises *)
adamc@48 431
adamc@48 432 Theorem forall_exists_commute : forall (A B : Type) (P : A -> B -> Prop),
adamc@48 433 (exists x : A, forall y : B, P x y) -> (forall y : B, exists x : A, P x y).
adamc@52 434 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 435 intros.
adamc@52 436 destruct H.
adamc@52 437 exists x.
adamc@52 438 apply H.
adamc@52 439 (* end thide *)
adamc@48 440 Admitted.
adamc@48 441
adamc@48 442 (* end hide *)
adamc@48 443
adamc@48 444
adam@322 445 (** The tactic [intuition] has a first-order cousin called %\index{tactics!firstorder}%[firstorder], which proves many formulas when only first-order reasoning is needed, and it tries to perform first-order simplifications in any case. First-order reasoning is much harder than propositional reasoning, so [firstorder] is much more likely than [intuition] to get stuck in a way that makes it run for long enough to be useless. *)
adamc@49 446
adamc@49 447
adamc@49 448 (** * Predicates with Implicit Equality *)
adamc@49 449
adamc@49 450 (** We start our exploration of a more complicated class of predicates with a simple example: an alternative way of characterizing when a natural number is zero. *)
adamc@49 451
adamc@49 452 Inductive isZero : nat -> Prop :=
adamc@49 453 | IsZero : isZero 0.
adamc@49 454
adamc@49 455 Theorem isZero_zero : isZero 0.
adamc@55 456 (* begin thide *)
adamc@49 457 constructor.
adamc@55 458 (* end thide *)
adamc@49 459 Qed.
adamc@49 460
adam@449 461 (** We can call [isZero] a%\index{judgment}% _judgment_, in the sense often used in the semantics of programming languages. Judgments are typically defined in the style of%\index{natural deduction}% _natural deduction_, where we write a number of%\index{inference rules}% _inference rules_ with premises appearing above a solid line and a conclusion appearing below the line. In this example, the sole constructor [IsZero] of [isZero] can be thought of as the single inference rule for deducing [isZero], with nothing above the line and [isZero 0] below it. The proof of [isZero_zero] demonstrates how we can apply an inference rule. (Readers not familiar with formal semantics should not worry about not following this paragraph!)
adamc@49 462
adam@494 463 The definition of [isZero] differs in an important way from all of the other inductive definitions that we have seen in this and the previous chapter. Instead of writing just [Set] or [Prop] after the colon, here we write [nat -> Prop]. We saw examples of parameterized types like [list], but there the parameters appeared with names _before_ the colon. Every constructor of a parameterized inductive type must have a range type that uses the same parameter, whereas the form we use here enables us to choose different arguments to the type for different constructors.
adamc@49 464
adam@449 465 For instance, our definition [isZero] makes the predicate provable only when the argument is [0]. We can see that the concept of equality is somehow implicit in the inductive definition mechanism. The way this is accomplished is similar to the way that logic variables are used in %\index{Prolog}%Prolog (but worry not if not familiar with Prolog), and it is a very powerful mechanism that forms a foundation for formalizing all of mathematics. In fact, though it is natural to think of inductive types as folding in the functionality of equality, in Coq, the true situation is reversed, with equality defined as just another inductive type!%\index{Gallina terms!eq}\index{Gallina terms!refl\_equal}% *)
adamc@49 466
adamc@49 467 Print eq.
adam@440 468 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adam@426 469 Inductive eq (A : Type) (x : A) : A -> Prop := eq_refl : x = x
adamc@209 470 ]]
adamc@49 471
adam@442 472 Behind the scenes, uses of infix [=] are expanded to instances of [eq]. We see that [eq] has both a parameter [x] that is fixed and an extra unnamed argument of the same type. The type of [eq] allows us to state any equalities, even those that are provably false. However, examining the type of equality's sole constructor [eq_refl], we see that we can only _prove_ equality when its two arguments are syntactically equal. This definition turns out to capture all of the basic properties of equality, and the equality-manipulating tactics that we have seen so far, like [reflexivity] and [rewrite], are implemented treating [eq] as just another inductive type with a well-chosen definition. Another way of stating that definition is: equality is defined as the least reflexive relation.
adamc@49 473
adam@322 474 Returning to the example of [isZero], we can see how to work with hypotheses that use this predicate. *)
adamc@49 475
adamc@49 476 Theorem isZero_plus : forall n m : nat, isZero m -> n + m = n.
adamc@55 477 (* begin thide *)
adamc@49 478 (** We want to proceed by cases on the proof of the assumption about [isZero]. *)
adamc@209 479
adamc@49 480 destruct 1.
adamc@49 481 (** [[
adamc@49 482 n : nat
adamc@49 483 ============================
adamc@49 484 n + 0 = n
adamc@209 485
adamc@209 486 ]]
adamc@49 487
adamc@209 488 Since [isZero] has only one constructor, we are presented with only one subgoal. The argument [m] to [isZero] is replaced with that type's argument from the single constructor [IsZero]. From this point, the proof is trivial. *)
adamc@49 489
adamc@49 490 crush.
adamc@55 491 (* end thide *)
adamc@49 492 Qed.
adamc@49 493
adamc@49 494 (** Another example seems at first like it should admit an analogous proof, but in fact provides a demonstration of one of the most basic gotchas of Coq proving. *)
adamc@49 495
adamc@49 496 Theorem isZero_contra : isZero 1 -> False.
adamc@55 497 (* begin thide *)
adamc@49 498 (** Let us try a proof by cases on the assumption, as in the last proof. *)
adamc@209 499
adamc@49 500 destruct 1.
adamc@49 501 (** [[
adamc@49 502 ============================
adamc@49 503 False
adamc@209 504
adamc@209 505 ]]
adamc@49 506
adamc@209 507 It seems that case analysis has not helped us much at all! Our sole hypothesis disappears, leaving us, if anything, worse off than we were before. What went wrong? We have met an important restriction in tactics like [destruct] and [induction] when applied to types with arguments. If the arguments are not already free variables, they will be replaced by new free variables internally before doing the case analysis or induction. Since the argument [1] to [isZero] is replaced by a fresh variable, we lose the crucial fact that it is not equal to [0].
adamc@49 508
adam@449 509 Why does Coq use this restriction? We will discuss the issue in detail in a future chapter, when we see the dependently typed programming techniques that would allow us to write this proof term manually. For now, we just say that the algorithmic problem of "logically complete case analysis" is undecidable when phrased in Coq's logic. A few tactics and design patterns that we will present in this chapter suffice in almost all cases. For the current example, what we want is a tactic called %\index{tactics!inversion}%[inversion], which corresponds to the concept of inversion that is frequently used with natural deduction proof systems. (Again, worry not if the semantics-oriented terminology from this last sentence is unfamiliar.) *)
adamc@49 510
adamc@49 511 Undo.
adamc@49 512 inversion 1.
adamc@55 513 (* end thide *)
adamc@49 514 Qed.
adamc@49 515
adamc@49 516 (** What does [inversion] do? Think of it as a version of [destruct] that does its best to take advantage of the structure of arguments to inductive types. In this case, [inversion] completed the proof immediately, because it was able to detect that we were using [isZero] with an impossible argument.
adamc@49 517
adamc@49 518 Sometimes using [destruct] when you should have used [inversion] can lead to confusing results. To illustrate, consider an alternate proof attempt for the last theorem. *)
adamc@49 519
adamc@49 520 Theorem isZero_contra' : isZero 1 -> 2 + 2 = 5.
adamc@49 521 destruct 1.
adamc@49 522 (** [[
adamc@49 523 ============================
adamc@49 524 1 + 1 = 4
adamc@209 525
adamc@209 526 ]]
adamc@49 527
adam@469 528 What on earth happened here? Internally, [destruct] replaced [1] with a fresh variable, and, trying to be helpful, it also replaced the occurrence of [1] within the unary representation of each number in the goal. Then, within the [O] case of the proof, we replace the fresh variable with [O]. This has the net effect of decrementing each of these numbers. *)
adamc@209 529
adamc@49 530 Abort.
adamc@49 531
adam@280 532 (** To see more clearly what is happening, we can consider the type of [isZero]'s induction principle. *)
adam@280 533
adam@280 534 Check isZero_ind.
adam@280 535 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adam@280 536 isZero_ind
adam@280 537 : forall P : nat -> Prop, P 0 -> forall n : nat, isZero n -> P n
adam@280 538 ]]
adam@280 539
adam@442 540 In our last proof script, [destruct] chose to instantiate [P] as [fun n => S n + S n = S (S (S (S n)))]. You can verify for yourself that this specialization of the principle applies to the goal and that the hypothesis [P 0] then matches the subgoal we saw generated. If you are doing a proof and encounter a strange transmutation like this, there is a good chance that you should go back and replace a use of [destruct] with [inversion]. *)
adam@280 541
adamc@49 542
adamc@49 543 (* begin hide *)
adamc@49 544 (* In-class exercises *)
adamc@49 545
adamc@49 546 (* EX: Define an inductive type capturing when a list has exactly two elements. Prove that your predicate does not hold of the empty list, and prove that, whenever it holds of a list, the length of that list is two. *)
adamc@49 547
adamc@52 548 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 549 Section twoEls.
adamc@52 550 Variable A : Type.
adamc@52 551
adamc@52 552 Inductive twoEls : list A -> Prop :=
adamc@52 553 | TwoEls : forall x y, twoEls (x :: y :: nil).
adamc@52 554
adamc@52 555 Theorem twoEls_nil : twoEls nil -> False.
adamc@52 556 inversion 1.
adamc@52 557 Qed.
adamc@52 558
adamc@52 559 Theorem twoEls_two : forall ls, twoEls ls -> length ls = 2.
adamc@52 560 inversion 1.
adamc@52 561 reflexivity.
adamc@52 562 Qed.
adamc@52 563 End twoEls.
adamc@52 564 (* end thide *)
adamc@52 565
adamc@49 566 (* end hide *)
adamc@49 567
adamc@50 568
adamc@50 569 (** * Recursive Predicates *)
adamc@50 570
adamc@50 571 (** We have already seen all of the ingredients we need to build interesting recursive predicates, like this predicate capturing even-ness. *)
adamc@50 572
adamc@50 573 Inductive even : nat -> Prop :=
adamc@50 574 | EvenO : even O
adamc@50 575 | EvenSS : forall n, even n -> even (S (S n)).
adamc@50 576
adam@401 577 (** Think of [even] as another judgment defined by natural deduction rules. The rule [EvenO] has nothing above the line and [even O] below the line, and [EvenSS] is a rule with [even n] above the line and [even (S (S n))] below.
adamc@50 578
adamc@50 579 The proof techniques of the last section are easily adapted. *)
adamc@50 580
adamc@50 581 Theorem even_0 : even 0.
adamc@55 582 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 583 constructor.
adamc@55 584 (* end thide *)
adamc@50 585 Qed.
adamc@50 586
adamc@50 587 Theorem even_4 : even 4.
adamc@55 588 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 589 constructor; constructor; constructor.
adamc@55 590 (* end thide *)
adamc@50 591 Qed.
adamc@50 592
adam@375 593 (** It is not hard to see that sequences of constructor applications like the above can get tedious. We can avoid them using Coq's hint facility, with a new [Hint] variant that asks to consider all constructors of an inductive type during proof search. The tactic %\index{tactics!auto}%[auto] performs exhaustive proof search up to a fixed depth, considering only the proof steps we have registered as hints. *)
adamc@50 594
adamc@55 595 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 596 Hint Constructors even.
adamc@50 597
adamc@50 598 Theorem even_4' : even 4.
adamc@50 599 auto.
adamc@50 600 Qed.
adamc@50 601
adamc@55 602 (* end thide *)
adamc@55 603
adam@322 604 (** We may also use [inversion] with [even]. *)
adam@322 605
adamc@50 606 Theorem even_1_contra : even 1 -> False.
adamc@55 607 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 608 inversion 1.
adamc@55 609 (* end thide *)
adamc@50 610 Qed.
adamc@50 611
adamc@50 612 Theorem even_3_contra : even 3 -> False.
adamc@55 613 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 614 inversion 1.
adamc@50 615 (** [[
adamc@50 616 H : even 3
adamc@50 617 n : nat
adamc@50 618 H1 : even 1
adamc@50 619 H0 : n = 1
adamc@50 620 ============================
adamc@50 621 False
adamc@209 622
adamc@209 623 ]]
adamc@50 624
adam@322 625 The [inversion] tactic can be a little overzealous at times, as we can see here with the introduction of the unused variable [n] and an equality hypothesis about it. For more complicated predicates, though, adding such assumptions is critical to dealing with the undecidability of general inversion. More complex inductive definitions and theorems can cause [inversion] to generate equalities where neither side is a variable. *)
adamc@50 626
adamc@50 627 inversion H1.
adamc@55 628 (* end thide *)
adamc@50 629 Qed.
adamc@50 630
adamc@50 631 (** We can also do inductive proofs about [even]. *)
adamc@50 632
adamc@50 633 Theorem even_plus : forall n m, even n -> even m -> even (n + m).
adamc@55 634 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 635 (** It seems a reasonable first choice to proceed by induction on [n]. *)
adamc@209 636
adamc@50 637 induction n; crush.
adamc@50 638 (** [[
adamc@50 639 n : nat
adamc@50 640 IHn : forall m : nat, even n -> even m -> even (n + m)
adamc@50 641 m : nat
adamc@50 642 H : even (S n)
adamc@50 643 H0 : even m
adamc@50 644 ============================
adamc@50 645 even (S (n + m))
adamc@209 646
adamc@209 647 ]]
adamc@50 648
adamc@209 649 We will need to use the hypotheses [H] and [H0] somehow. The most natural choice is to invert [H]. *)
adamc@50 650
adamc@50 651 inversion H.
adamc@50 652 (** [[
adamc@50 653 n : nat
adamc@50 654 IHn : forall m : nat, even n -> even m -> even (n + m)
adamc@50 655 m : nat
adamc@50 656 H : even (S n)
adamc@50 657 H0 : even m
adamc@50 658 n0 : nat
adamc@50 659 H2 : even n0
adamc@50 660 H1 : S n0 = n
adamc@50 661 ============================
adamc@50 662 even (S (S n0 + m))
adamc@209 663
adamc@209 664 ]]
adamc@50 665
adamc@209 666 Simplifying the conclusion brings us to a point where we can apply a constructor. *)
adamc@209 667
adamc@50 668 simpl.
adamc@50 669 (** [[
adamc@50 670 ============================
adamc@50 671 even (S (S (n0 + m)))
adam@302 672 ]]
adam@302 673 *)
adamc@50 674
adamc@50 675 constructor.
adam@322 676
adam@401 677 (** [[
adamc@50 678 ============================
adamc@50 679 even (n0 + m)
adamc@209 680
adamc@209 681 ]]
adamc@50 682
adamc@209 683 At this point, we would like to apply the inductive hypothesis, which is:
adamc@209 684
adamc@209 685 [[
adamc@50 686 IHn : forall m : nat, even n -> even m -> even (n + m)
adam@440 687
adamc@209 688 ]]
adamc@50 689
adam@421 690 Unfortunately, the goal mentions [n0] where it would need to mention [n] to match [IHn]. We could keep looking for a way to finish this proof from here, but it turns out that we can make our lives much easier by changing our basic strategy. Instead of inducting on the structure of [n], we should induct _on the structure of one of the [even] proofs_. This technique is commonly called%\index{rule induction}% _rule induction_ in programming language semantics. In the setting of Coq, we have already seen how predicates are defined using the same inductive type mechanism as datatypes, so the fundamental unity of rule induction with "normal" induction is apparent.
adamc@50 691
adam@322 692 Recall that tactics like [induction] and [destruct] may be passed numbers to refer to unnamed lefthand sides of implications in the conclusion, where the argument [n] refers to the [n]th such hypothesis. *)
adam@322 693
adamc@50 694 Restart.
adamc@50 695
adamc@50 696 induction 1.
adamc@50 697 (** [[
adamc@50 698 m : nat
adamc@50 699 ============================
adamc@50 700 even m -> even (0 + m)
adam@322 701 ]]
adamc@50 702
adam@322 703 %\noindent \coqdockw{subgoal} 2 \coqdockw{is}:%#<tt>subgoal 2 is</tt>#
adam@322 704 [[
adamc@50 705 even m -> even (S (S n) + m)
adamc@209 706
adamc@209 707 ]]
adamc@50 708
adamc@209 709 The first case is easily discharged by [crush], based on the hint we added earlier to try the constructors of [even]. *)
adamc@50 710
adamc@50 711 crush.
adamc@50 712
adamc@50 713 (** Now we focus on the second case: *)
adamc@209 714
adamc@50 715 intro.
adamc@50 716 (** [[
adamc@50 717 m : nat
adamc@50 718 n : nat
adamc@50 719 H : even n
adamc@50 720 IHeven : even m -> even (n + m)
adamc@50 721 H0 : even m
adamc@50 722 ============================
adamc@50 723 even (S (S n) + m)
adamc@209 724
adamc@209 725 ]]
adamc@50 726
adamc@209 727 We simplify and apply a constructor, as in our last proof attempt. *)
adamc@50 728
adamc@50 729 simpl; constructor.
adam@322 730
adam@401 731 (** [[
adamc@50 732 ============================
adamc@50 733 even (n + m)
adamc@209 734
adamc@209 735 ]]
adamc@50 736
adamc@209 737 Now we have an exact match with our inductive hypothesis, and the remainder of the proof is trivial. *)
adamc@50 738
adamc@50 739 apply IHeven; assumption.
adamc@50 740
adamc@50 741 (** In fact, [crush] can handle all of the details of the proof once we declare the induction strategy. *)
adamc@50 742
adamc@50 743 Restart.
adam@322 744
adamc@50 745 induction 1; crush.
adamc@55 746 (* end thide *)
adamc@50 747 Qed.
adamc@50 748
adamc@50 749 (** Induction on recursive predicates has similar pitfalls to those we encountered with inversion in the last section. *)
adamc@50 750
adamc@50 751 Theorem even_contra : forall n, even (S (n + n)) -> False.
adamc@55 752 (* begin thide *)
adamc@50 753 induction 1.
adamc@50 754 (** [[
adamc@50 755 n : nat
adamc@50 756 ============================
adamc@50 757 False
adam@322 758 ]]
adamc@50 759
adam@322 760 %\noindent \coqdockw{subgoal} 2 \coqdockw{is}:%#<tt>subgoal 2 is</tt>#
adam@322 761 [[
adamc@50 762 False
adamc@209 763
adamc@209 764 ]]
adamc@50 765
adam@280 766 We are already sunk trying to prove the first subgoal, since the argument to [even] was replaced by a fresh variable internally. This time, we find it easier to prove this theorem by way of a lemma. Instead of trusting [induction] to replace expressions with fresh variables, we do it ourselves, explicitly adding the appropriate equalities as new assumptions. *)
adamc@209 767
adamc@50 768 Abort.
adamc@50 769
adamc@50 770 Lemma even_contra' : forall n', even n' -> forall n, n' = S (n + n) -> False.
adamc@50 771 induction 1; crush.
adamc@50 772
adamc@54 773 (** At this point, it is useful to consider all cases of [n] and [n0] being zero or nonzero. Only one of these cases has any trickiness to it. *)
adamc@209 774
adamc@50 775 destruct n; destruct n0; crush.
adamc@50 776
adamc@50 777 (** [[
adamc@50 778 n : nat
adamc@50 779 H : even (S n)
adamc@50 780 IHeven : forall n0 : nat, S n = S (n0 + n0) -> False
adamc@50 781 n0 : nat
adamc@50 782 H0 : S n = n0 + S n0
adamc@50 783 ============================
adamc@50 784 False
adamc@209 785
adamc@209 786 ]]
adamc@50 787
adam@280 788 At this point it is useful to use a theorem from the standard library, which we also proved with a different name in the last chapter. We can search for a theorem that allows us to rewrite terms of the form [x + S y]. *)
adamc@209 789
adam@280 790 SearchRewrite (_ + S _).
adam@440 791 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
adam@280 792 plus_n_Sm : forall n m : nat, S (n + m) = n + S m
adam@302 793 ]]
adam@302 794 *)
adamc@50 795
adamc@50 796 rewrite <- plus_n_Sm in H0.
adamc@50 797
adam@322 798 (** The induction hypothesis lets us complete the proof, if we use a variant of [apply] that has a %\index{tactics!with}%[with] clause to give instantiations of quantified variables. *)
adamc@209 799
adamc@50 800 apply IHeven with n0; assumption.
adamc@50 801
adam@322 802 (** As usual, we can rewrite the proof to avoid referencing any locally generated names, which makes our proof script more readable and more robust to changes in the theorem statement. We use the notation [<-] to request a hint that does right-to-left rewriting, just like we can with the [rewrite] tactic. *)
adamc@209 803
adamc@209 804 Restart.
adam@322 805
adam@375 806 Hint Rewrite <- plus_n_Sm.
adamc@50 807
adamc@50 808 induction 1; crush;
adamc@50 809 match goal with
adamc@50 810 | [ H : S ?N = ?N0 + ?N0 |- _ ] => destruct N; destruct N0
adamc@50 811 end; crush; eauto.
adamc@50 812 Qed.
adamc@50 813
adam@322 814 (** We write the proof in a way that avoids the use of local variable or hypothesis names, using the %\index{tactics!match}%[match] tactic form to do pattern-matching on the goal. We use unification variables prefixed by question marks in the pattern, and we take advantage of the possibility to mention a unification variable twice in one pattern, to enforce equality between occurrences. The hint to rewrite with [plus_n_Sm] in a particular direction saves us from having to figure out the right place to apply that theorem, and we also take critical advantage of a new tactic, %\index{tactics!eauto}%[eauto].
adamc@50 815
adam@471 816 The [crush] tactic uses the tactic [intuition], which, when it runs out of tricks to try using only propositional logic, by default tries the tactic [auto], which we saw in an earlier example. For now, think of [eauto] as a potentially more expensive version of [auto] that considers more possible proofs; see Chapter 13 for more detail. The quick summary is that [eauto] considers applying a lemma even when the form of the current goal doesn not uniquely determine the values of all of the lemma's quantified variables.
adamc@50 817
adamc@50 818 The original theorem now follows trivially from our lemma. *)
adamc@50 819
adamc@50 820 Theorem even_contra : forall n, even (S (n + n)) -> False.
adamc@52 821 intros; eapply even_contra'; eauto.
adamc@50 822 Qed.
adamc@52 823
adam@398 824 (** We use a variant %\index{tactics!apply}%[eapply] of [apply] which has the same relationship to [apply] as [eauto] has to [auto]. An invocation of [apply] only succeeds if all arguments to the rule being used can be determined from the form of the goal, whereas [eapply] will introduce unification variables for undetermined arguments. In this case, [eauto] is able to determine the right values for those unification variables, using (unsurprisingly) a variant of the classic algorithm for _unification_ %\cite{unification}%.
adamc@52 825
adamc@52 826 By considering an alternate attempt at proving the lemma, we can see another common pitfall of inductive proofs in Coq. Imagine that we had tried to prove [even_contra'] with all of the [forall] quantifiers moved to the front of the lemma statement. *)
adamc@52 827
adamc@52 828 Lemma even_contra'' : forall n' n, even n' -> n' = S (n + n) -> False.
adamc@52 829 induction 1; crush;
adamc@52 830 match goal with
adamc@52 831 | [ H : S ?N = ?N0 + ?N0 |- _ ] => destruct N; destruct N0
adamc@52 832 end; crush; eauto.
adamc@52 833
adamc@209 834 (** One subgoal remains:
adamc@52 835
adamc@209 836 [[
adamc@52 837 n : nat
adamc@52 838 H : even (S (n + n))
adamc@52 839 IHeven : S (n + n) = S (S (S (n + n))) -> False
adamc@52 840 ============================
adamc@52 841 False
adamc@209 842
adamc@209 843 ]]
adamc@52 844
adam@398 845 We are out of luck here. The inductive hypothesis is trivially true, since its assumption is false. In the version of this proof that succeeded, [IHeven] had an explicit quantification over [n]. This is because the quantification of [n] _appeared after the thing we are inducting on_ in the theorem statement. In general, quantified variables and hypotheses that appear before the induction object in the theorem statement stay fixed throughout the inductive proof. Variables and hypotheses that are quantified after the induction object may be varied explicitly in uses of inductive hypotheses. *)
adamc@52 846
adam@322 847 Abort.
adam@322 848
adam@322 849 (** Why should Coq implement [induction] this way? One answer is that it avoids burdening this basic tactic with additional heuristic smarts, but that is not the whole picture. Imagine that [induction] analyzed dependencies among variables and reordered quantifiers to preserve as much freedom as possible in later uses of inductive hypotheses. This could make the inductive hypotheses more complex, which could in turn cause particular automation machinery to fail when it would have succeeded before. In general, we want to avoid quantifiers in our proofs whenever we can, and that goal is furthered by the refactoring that the [induction] tactic forces us to do. *)
adamc@55 850 (* end thide *)
adamc@209 851
adam@322 852
adamc@51 853
adamc@52 854
adamc@52 855 (* begin hide *)
adamc@52 856 (* In-class exercises *)
adamc@52 857
adam@448 858 (* EX: Define a type [prop] of simple Boolean formulas made up only of truth, falsehood, binary conjunction, and binary disjunction. Define an inductive predicate [holds] that captures when [prop]s are valid, and define a predicate [falseFree] that captures when a [prop] does not contain the "false" formula. Prove that every false-free [prop] is valid. *)
adamc@52 859
adamc@52 860 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 861 Inductive prop : Set :=
adamc@52 862 | Tru : prop
adamc@52 863 | Fals : prop
adamc@52 864 | And : prop -> prop -> prop
adamc@52 865 | Or : prop -> prop -> prop.
adamc@52 866
adamc@52 867 Inductive holds : prop -> Prop :=
adamc@52 868 | HTru : holds Tru
adamc@52 869 | HAnd : forall p1 p2, holds p1 -> holds p2 -> holds (And p1 p2)
adamc@52 870 | HOr1 : forall p1 p2, holds p1 -> holds (Or p1 p2)
adamc@52 871 | HOr2 : forall p1 p2, holds p2 -> holds (Or p1 p2).
adamc@52 872
adamc@52 873 Inductive falseFree : prop -> Prop :=
adamc@52 874 | FFTru : falseFree Tru
adamc@52 875 | FFAnd : forall p1 p2, falseFree p1 -> falseFree p2 -> falseFree (And p1 p2)
adamc@52 876 | FFNot : forall p1 p2, falseFree p1 -> falseFree p2 -> falseFree (Or p1 p2).
adamc@52 877
adamc@52 878 Hint Constructors holds.
adamc@52 879
adamc@52 880 Theorem falseFree_holds : forall p, falseFree p -> holds p.
adamc@52 881 induction 1; crush.
adamc@52 882 Qed.
adamc@52 883 (* end thide *)
adamc@52 884
adamc@52 885
adamc@52 886 (* EX: Define an inductive type [prop'] that is the same as [prop] but omits the possibility for falsehood. Define a proposition [holds'] for [prop'] that is analogous to [holds]. Define a function [propify] for translating [prop']s to [prop]s. Prove that, for any [prop'] [p], if [propify p] is valid, then so is [p]. *)
adamc@52 887
adamc@52 888 (* begin thide *)
adamc@52 889 Inductive prop' : Set :=
adamc@52 890 | Tru' : prop'
adamc@52 891 | And' : prop' -> prop' -> prop'
adamc@52 892 | Or' : prop' -> prop' -> prop'.
adamc@52 893
adamc@52 894 Inductive holds' : prop' -> Prop :=
adamc@52 895 | HTru' : holds' Tru'
adamc@52 896 | HAnd' : forall p1 p2, holds' p1 -> holds' p2 -> holds' (And' p1 p2)
adamc@52 897 | HOr1' : forall p1 p2, holds' p1 -> holds' (Or' p1 p2)
adamc@52 898 | HOr2' : forall p1 p2, holds' p2 -> holds' (Or' p1 p2).
adamc@52 899
adamc@52 900 Fixpoint propify (p : prop') : prop :=
adamc@52 901 match p with
adamc@52 902 | Tru' => Tru
adamc@52 903 | And' p1 p2 => And (propify p1) (propify p2)
adamc@52 904 | Or' p1 p2 => Or (propify p1) (propify p2)
adamc@52 905 end.
adamc@52 906
adamc@52 907 Hint Constructors holds'.
adamc@52 908
adamc@52 909 Lemma propify_holds' : forall p', holds p' -> forall p, p' = propify p -> holds' p.
adamc@52 910 induction 1; crush; destruct p; crush.
adamc@52 911 Qed.
adamc@52 912
adamc@52 913 Theorem propify_holds : forall p, holds (propify p) -> holds' p.
adamc@52 914 intros; eapply propify_holds'; eauto.
adamc@52 915 Qed.
adamc@52 916 (* end thide *)
adamc@52 917
adamc@52 918 (* end hide *)