adamc@118
|
1 (* Copyright (c) 2008, Adam Chlipala
|
adamc@118
|
2 *
|
adamc@118
|
3 * This work is licensed under a
|
adamc@118
|
4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
|
adamc@118
|
5 * Unported License.
|
adamc@118
|
6 * The license text is available at:
|
adamc@118
|
7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
|
adamc@118
|
8 *)
|
adamc@118
|
9
|
adamc@118
|
10 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@120
|
11 Require Import Eqdep JMeq List.
|
adamc@118
|
12
|
adamc@118
|
13 Require Import Tactics.
|
adamc@118
|
14
|
adamc@118
|
15 Set Implicit Arguments.
|
adamc@118
|
16 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@118
|
17
|
adamc@118
|
18
|
adamc@118
|
19 (** %\chapter{Reasoning About Equality Proofs}% *)
|
adamc@118
|
20
|
adamc@118
|
21 (** In traditional mathematics, the concept of equality is usually taken as a given. On the other hand, in type theory, equality is a very contentious subject. There are at least three different notions of equality that are important, and researchers are actively investigating new definitions of what it means for two terms to be equal. Even once we fix a notion of equality, there are inevitably tricky issues that arise in proving properties of programs that manipulate equality proofs explicitly. In this chapter, we will focus on design patterns for circumventing these tricky issues, and we will introduce the different notions of equality as they are germane. *)
|
adamc@118
|
22
|
adamc@118
|
23
|
adamc@122
|
24 (** * The Definitional Equality *)
|
adamc@122
|
25
|
adamc@122
|
26 (** We have seen many examples so far where proof goals follow "by computation." That is, we apply computational reduction rules to reduce the goal to a normal form, at which point it follows trivially. Exactly when this works and when it does not depends on the details of Coq's %\textit{%#<i>#definitional equality#</i>#%}%. This is an untyped binary relation appearing in the formal metatheory of CIC. CIC contains a typing rule allowing the conclusion $E : T$ from the premise $E : T'$ and a proof that $T$ and $T'$ are definitionally equal.
|
adamc@122
|
27
|
adamc@122
|
28 The [cbv] tactic will help us illustrate the rules of Coq's definitional equality. We redefine the natural number predecessor function in a somewhat convoluted way and construct a manual proof that it returns [1] when applied to [0]. *)
|
adamc@122
|
29
|
adamc@122
|
30 Definition pred' (x : nat) :=
|
adamc@122
|
31 match x with
|
adamc@122
|
32 | O => O
|
adamc@122
|
33 | S n' => let y := n' in y
|
adamc@122
|
34 end.
|
adamc@122
|
35
|
adamc@122
|
36 Theorem reduce_me : pred' 1 = 0.
|
adamc@122
|
37 (** CIC follows the traditions of lambda calculus in associating reduction rules with Greek letters. Coq can certainly be said to support the familiar alpha reduction rule, which allows capture-avoiding renaming of bound variables, but we never need to apply alpha explicitly, since Coq uses a de Bruijn representation that encodes terms canonically.
|
adamc@122
|
38
|
adamc@122
|
39 The delta rule is for unfolding global definitions. We can use it here to unfold the definition of [pred']. We do this with the [cbv] tactic, which takes a list of reduction rules and makes as many call-by-value reduction steps as possible, using only those rules. There is an analogous tactic [lazy] for call-by-name reduction. *)
|
adamc@122
|
40
|
adamc@122
|
41 cbv delta.
|
adamc@122
|
42 (** [[
|
adamc@122
|
43
|
adamc@122
|
44 ============================
|
adamc@122
|
45 (fun x : nat => match x with
|
adamc@122
|
46 | 0 => 0
|
adamc@122
|
47 | S n' => let y := n' in y
|
adamc@122
|
48 end) 1 = 0
|
adamc@122
|
49 ]]
|
adamc@122
|
50
|
adamc@122
|
51 At this point, we want to apply the famous beta reduction of lambda calculus, to simplify the application of a known function abstraction. *)
|
adamc@122
|
52
|
adamc@122
|
53 cbv beta.
|
adamc@122
|
54 (** [[
|
adamc@122
|
55
|
adamc@122
|
56 ============================
|
adamc@122
|
57 match 1 with
|
adamc@122
|
58 | 0 => 0
|
adamc@122
|
59 | S n' => let y := n' in y
|
adamc@122
|
60 end = 0
|
adamc@122
|
61 ]]
|
adamc@122
|
62
|
adamc@122
|
63 Next on the list is the iota reduction, which simplifies a single [match] term by determining which pattern matches. *)
|
adamc@122
|
64
|
adamc@122
|
65 cbv iota.
|
adamc@122
|
66 (** [[
|
adamc@122
|
67
|
adamc@122
|
68 ============================
|
adamc@122
|
69 (fun n' : nat => let y := n' in y) 0 = 0
|
adamc@122
|
70 ]]
|
adamc@122
|
71
|
adamc@122
|
72 Now we need another beta reduction. *)
|
adamc@122
|
73
|
adamc@122
|
74 cbv beta.
|
adamc@122
|
75 (** [[
|
adamc@122
|
76
|
adamc@122
|
77 ============================
|
adamc@122
|
78 (let y := 0 in y) = 0
|
adamc@122
|
79 ]]
|
adamc@122
|
80
|
adamc@122
|
81 The final reduction rule is zeta, which replaces a [let] expression by its body with the appropriate term subsituted. *)
|
adamc@122
|
82
|
adamc@122
|
83 cbv zeta.
|
adamc@122
|
84 (** [[
|
adamc@122
|
85
|
adamc@122
|
86 ============================
|
adamc@122
|
87 0 = 0
|
adamc@122
|
88 ]] *)
|
adamc@122
|
89
|
adamc@122
|
90 reflexivity.
|
adamc@122
|
91 Qed.
|
adamc@122
|
92
|
adamc@122
|
93 (** The standard [eq] relation is critically dependent on the definitional equality. [eq] is often called a %\textit{%#<i>#propositional equality#</i>#%}%, because it reifies definitional equality as a proposition that may or may not hold. Standard axiomatizations of an equality predicate in first-order logic define equality in terms of properties it has, like reflexivity, symmetry, and transitivity. In contrast, for [eq] in Coq, those properties are implicit in the properties of the definitional equality, which are built into CIC's metatheory and the implementation of Gallina. We could add new rules to the definitional equality, and [eq] would keep its definition and methods of use.
|
adamc@122
|
94
|
adamc@122
|
95 This all may make it sound like the choice of [eq]'s definition is unimportant. To the contrary, in this chapter, we will see examples where alternate definitions may simplify proofs. Before that point, we will introduce effective proof methods for goals that use proofs of the standard propositional equality "as data." *)
|
adamc@122
|
96
|
adamc@122
|
97
|
adamc@118
|
98 (** * Heterogeneous Lists Revisited *)
|
adamc@118
|
99
|
adamc@118
|
100 (** One of our example dependent data structures from the last chapter was heterogeneous lists and their associated "cursor" type. *)
|
adamc@118
|
101
|
adamc@118
|
102 Section fhlist.
|
adamc@118
|
103 Variable A : Type.
|
adamc@118
|
104 Variable B : A -> Type.
|
adamc@118
|
105
|
adamc@118
|
106 Fixpoint fhlist (ls : list A) : Type :=
|
adamc@118
|
107 match ls with
|
adamc@118
|
108 | nil => unit
|
adamc@118
|
109 | x :: ls' => B x * fhlist ls'
|
adamc@118
|
110 end%type.
|
adamc@118
|
111
|
adamc@118
|
112 Variable elm : A.
|
adamc@118
|
113
|
adamc@118
|
114 Fixpoint fmember (ls : list A) : Type :=
|
adamc@118
|
115 match ls with
|
adamc@118
|
116 | nil => Empty_set
|
adamc@118
|
117 | x :: ls' => (x = elm) + fmember ls'
|
adamc@118
|
118 end%type.
|
adamc@118
|
119
|
adamc@118
|
120 Fixpoint fhget (ls : list A) : fhlist ls -> fmember ls -> B elm :=
|
adamc@118
|
121 match ls return fhlist ls -> fmember ls -> B elm with
|
adamc@118
|
122 | nil => fun _ idx => match idx with end
|
adamc@118
|
123 | _ :: ls' => fun mls idx =>
|
adamc@118
|
124 match idx with
|
adamc@118
|
125 | inl pf => match pf with
|
adamc@118
|
126 | refl_equal => fst mls
|
adamc@118
|
127 end
|
adamc@118
|
128 | inr idx' => fhget ls' (snd mls) idx'
|
adamc@118
|
129 end
|
adamc@118
|
130 end.
|
adamc@118
|
131 End fhlist.
|
adamc@118
|
132
|
adamc@118
|
133 Implicit Arguments fhget [A B elm ls].
|
adamc@118
|
134
|
adamc@118
|
135 (** We can define a [map]-like function for [fhlist]s. *)
|
adamc@118
|
136
|
adamc@118
|
137 Section fhlist_map.
|
adamc@118
|
138 Variables A : Type.
|
adamc@118
|
139 Variables B C : A -> Type.
|
adamc@118
|
140 Variable f : forall x, B x -> C x.
|
adamc@118
|
141
|
adamc@118
|
142 Fixpoint fhmap (ls : list A) : fhlist B ls -> fhlist C ls :=
|
adamc@118
|
143 match ls return fhlist B ls -> fhlist C ls with
|
adamc@118
|
144 | nil => fun _ => tt
|
adamc@118
|
145 | _ :: _ => fun hls => (f (fst hls), fhmap _ (snd hls))
|
adamc@118
|
146 end.
|
adamc@118
|
147
|
adamc@118
|
148 Implicit Arguments fhmap [ls].
|
adamc@118
|
149
|
adamc@118
|
150 (** For the inductive versions of the [ilist] definitions, we proved a lemma about the interaction of [get] and [imap]. It was a strategic choice not to attempt such a proof for the definitions that we just gave, because that sets us on a collision course with the problems that are the subject of this chapter. *)
|
adamc@118
|
151
|
adamc@118
|
152 Variable elm : A.
|
adamc@118
|
153
|
adamc@118
|
154 Theorem get_imap : forall ls (mem : fmember elm ls) (hls : fhlist B ls),
|
adamc@118
|
155 fhget (fhmap hls) mem = f (fhget hls mem).
|
adamc@118
|
156 induction ls; crush.
|
adamc@118
|
157
|
adamc@118
|
158 (** Part of our single remaining subgoal is:
|
adamc@118
|
159
|
adamc@118
|
160 [[
|
adamc@118
|
161
|
adamc@118
|
162 a0 : a = elm
|
adamc@118
|
163 ============================
|
adamc@118
|
164 match a0 in (_ = a2) return (C a2) with
|
adamc@118
|
165 | refl_equal => f a1
|
adamc@118
|
166 end = f match a0 in (_ = a2) return (B a2) with
|
adamc@118
|
167 | refl_equal => a1
|
adamc@118
|
168 end
|
adamc@118
|
169 ]]
|
adamc@118
|
170
|
adamc@118
|
171 This seems like a trivial enough obligation. The equality proof [a0] must be [refl_equal], since that is the only constructor of [eq]. Therefore, both the [match]es reduce to the point where the conclusion follows by reflexivity.
|
adamc@118
|
172
|
adamc@118
|
173 [[
|
adamc@118
|
174
|
adamc@118
|
175 destruct a0.
|
adamc@118
|
176
|
adamc@118
|
177 [[
|
adamc@118
|
178 User error: Cannot solve a second-order unification problem
|
adamc@118
|
179 ]]
|
adamc@118
|
180
|
adamc@118
|
181 This is one of Coq's standard error messages for informing us that its heuristics for attempting an instance of an undecidable problem about dependent typing have failed. We might try to nudge things in the right direction by stating the lemma that we believe makes the conclusion trivial.
|
adamc@118
|
182
|
adamc@118
|
183 [[
|
adamc@118
|
184
|
adamc@118
|
185 assert (a0 = refl_equal _).
|
adamc@118
|
186
|
adamc@118
|
187 [[
|
adamc@118
|
188 The term "refl_equal ?98" has type "?98 = ?98"
|
adamc@118
|
189 while it is expected to have type "a = elm"
|
adamc@118
|
190 ]]
|
adamc@118
|
191
|
adamc@118
|
192 In retrospect, the problem is not so hard to see. Reflexivity proofs only show [x = x] for particular values of [x], whereas here we are thinking in terms of a proof of [a = elm], where the two sides of the equality are not equal syntactically. Thus, the essential lemma we need does not even type-check!
|
adamc@118
|
193
|
adamc@118
|
194 Is it time to throw in the towel? Luckily, the answer is "no." In this chapter, we will see several useful patterns for proving obligations like this.
|
adamc@118
|
195
|
adamc@118
|
196 For this particular example, the solution is surprisingly straightforward. [destruct] has a simpler sibling [case] which should behave identically for any inductive type with one constructor of no arguments. *)
|
adamc@118
|
197
|
adamc@118
|
198 case a0.
|
adamc@118
|
199 (** [[
|
adamc@118
|
200
|
adamc@118
|
201 ============================
|
adamc@118
|
202 f a1 = f a1
|
adamc@118
|
203 ]]
|
adamc@118
|
204
|
adamc@118
|
205 It seems that [destruct] was trying to be too smart for its own good. *)
|
adamc@118
|
206
|
adamc@118
|
207 reflexivity.
|
adamc@118
|
208 Qed.
|
adamc@118
|
209
|
adamc@118
|
210 (** It will be helpful to examine the proof terms generated by this sort of strategy. A simpler example illustrates what is going on. *)
|
adamc@118
|
211
|
adamc@118
|
212 Lemma lemma1 : forall x (pf : x = elm), O = match pf with refl_equal => O end.
|
adamc@118
|
213 simple destruct pf; reflexivity.
|
adamc@118
|
214 Qed.
|
adamc@118
|
215
|
adamc@118
|
216 (** [simple destruct pf] is a convenient form for applying [case]. It runs [intro] to bring into scope all quantified variables up to its argument. *)
|
adamc@118
|
217
|
adamc@118
|
218 Print lemma1.
|
adamc@118
|
219
|
adamc@118
|
220 (** [[
|
adamc@118
|
221
|
adamc@118
|
222 lemma1 =
|
adamc@118
|
223 fun (x : A) (pf : x = elm) =>
|
adamc@118
|
224 match pf as e in (_ = y) return (0 = match e with
|
adamc@118
|
225 | refl_equal => 0
|
adamc@118
|
226 end) with
|
adamc@118
|
227 | refl_equal => refl_equal 0
|
adamc@118
|
228 end
|
adamc@118
|
229 : forall (x : A) (pf : x = elm), 0 = match pf with
|
adamc@118
|
230 | refl_equal => 0
|
adamc@118
|
231 end
|
adamc@118
|
232 ]]
|
adamc@118
|
233
|
adamc@118
|
234 Using what we know about shorthands for [match] annotations, we can write this proof in shorter form manually. *)
|
adamc@118
|
235
|
adamc@118
|
236 Definition lemma1' :=
|
adamc@118
|
237 fun (x : A) (pf : x = elm) =>
|
adamc@118
|
238 match pf return (0 = match pf with
|
adamc@118
|
239 | refl_equal => 0
|
adamc@118
|
240 end) with
|
adamc@118
|
241 | refl_equal => refl_equal 0
|
adamc@118
|
242 end.
|
adamc@118
|
243
|
adamc@118
|
244 (** Surprisingly, what seems at first like a %\textit{%#<i>#simpler#</i>#%}% lemma is harder to prove. *)
|
adamc@118
|
245
|
adamc@118
|
246 Lemma lemma2 : forall (x : A) (pf : x = x), O = match pf with refl_equal => O end.
|
adamc@118
|
247 (** [[
|
adamc@118
|
248
|
adamc@118
|
249 simple destruct pf.
|
adamc@118
|
250
|
adamc@118
|
251 [[
|
adamc@118
|
252
|
adamc@118
|
253 User error: Cannot solve a second-order unification problem
|
adamc@118
|
254 ]] *)
|
adamc@118
|
255 Abort.
|
adamc@118
|
256
|
adamc@118
|
257 (** Nonetheless, we can adapt the last manual proof to handle this theorem. *)
|
adamc@118
|
258
|
adamc@118
|
259 Definition lemma2' :=
|
adamc@118
|
260 fun (x : A) (pf : x = x) =>
|
adamc@118
|
261 match pf return (0 = match pf with
|
adamc@118
|
262 | refl_equal => 0
|
adamc@118
|
263 end) with
|
adamc@118
|
264 | refl_equal => refl_equal 0
|
adamc@118
|
265 end.
|
adamc@118
|
266
|
adamc@118
|
267 (** We can try to prove a lemma that would simplify proofs of many facts like [lemma2]: *)
|
adamc@118
|
268
|
adamc@118
|
269 Lemma lemma3 : forall (x : A) (pf : x = x), pf = refl_equal x.
|
adamc@118
|
270 (** [[
|
adamc@118
|
271
|
adamc@118
|
272 simple destruct pf.
|
adamc@118
|
273
|
adamc@118
|
274 [[
|
adamc@118
|
275
|
adamc@118
|
276 User error: Cannot solve a second-order unification problem
|
adamc@118
|
277 ]] *)
|
adamc@118
|
278 Abort.
|
adamc@118
|
279
|
adamc@118
|
280 (** This time, even our manual attempt fails.
|
adamc@118
|
281
|
adamc@118
|
282 [[
|
adamc@118
|
283
|
adamc@118
|
284 Definition lemma3' :=
|
adamc@118
|
285 fun (x : A) (pf : x = x) =>
|
adamc@118
|
286 match pf as pf' in (_ = x') return (pf' = refl_equal x') with
|
adamc@118
|
287 | refl_equal => refl_equal _
|
adamc@118
|
288 end.
|
adamc@118
|
289
|
adamc@118
|
290 [[
|
adamc@118
|
291
|
adamc@118
|
292 The term "refl_equal x'" has type "x' = x'" while it is expected to have type
|
adamc@118
|
293 "x = x'"
|
adamc@118
|
294 ]]
|
adamc@118
|
295
|
adamc@118
|
296 The type error comes from our [return] annotation. In that annotation, the [as]-bound variable [pf'] has type [x = x'], refering to the [in]-bound variable [x']. To do a dependent [match], we %\textit{%#<i>#must#</i>#%}% choose a fresh name for the second argument of [eq]. We are just as constrained to use the "real" value [x] for the first argument. Thus, within the [return] clause, the proof we are matching on %\textit{%#<i>#must#</i>#%}% equate two non-matching terms, which makes it impossible to equate that proof with reflexivity.
|
adamc@118
|
297
|
adamc@118
|
298 Nonetheless, it turns out that, with one catch, we %\textit{%#<i>#can#</i>#%}% prove this lemma. *)
|
adamc@118
|
299
|
adamc@118
|
300 Lemma lemma3 : forall (x : A) (pf : x = x), pf = refl_equal x.
|
adamc@118
|
301 intros; apply UIP_refl.
|
adamc@118
|
302 Qed.
|
adamc@118
|
303
|
adamc@118
|
304 Check UIP_refl.
|
adamc@118
|
305 (** [[
|
adamc@118
|
306
|
adamc@118
|
307 UIP_refl
|
adamc@118
|
308 : forall (U : Type) (x : U) (p : x = x), p = refl_equal x
|
adamc@118
|
309 ]]
|
adamc@118
|
310
|
adamc@118
|
311 [UIP_refl] comes from the [Eqdep] module of the standard library. Do the Coq authors know of some clever trick for building such proofs that we have not seen yet? If they do, they did not use it for this proof. Rather, the proof is based on an %\textit{%#<i>#axiom#</i>#%}%. *)
|
adamc@118
|
312
|
adamc@118
|
313 Print eq_rect_eq.
|
adamc@118
|
314 (** [[
|
adamc@118
|
315
|
adamc@118
|
316 eq_rect_eq =
|
adamc@118
|
317 fun U : Type => Eq_rect_eq.eq_rect_eq U
|
adamc@118
|
318 : forall (U : Type) (p : U) (Q : U -> Type) (x : Q p) (h : p = p),
|
adamc@118
|
319 x = eq_rect p Q x p h
|
adamc@118
|
320 ]]
|
adamc@118
|
321
|
adamc@118
|
322 [eq_rect_eq] states a "fact" that seems like common sense, once the notation is deciphered. [eq_rect] is the automatically-generated recursion principle for [eq]. Calling [eq_rect] is another way of [match]ing on an equality proof. The proof we match on is the argument [h], and [x] is the body of the [match]. [eq_rect_eq] just says that [match]es on proofs of [p = p], for any [p], are superfluous and may be removed.
|
adamc@118
|
323
|
adamc@118
|
324 Perhaps surprisingly, we cannot prove [eq_rect_eq] from within Coq. This proposition is introduced as an axiom; that is, a proposition asserted as true without proof. We cannot assert just any statement without proof. Adding [False] as an axiom would allow us to prove any proposition, for instance, defeating the point of using a proof assistant. In general, we need to be sure that we never assert %\textit{%#<i>#inconsistent#</i>#%}% sets of axioms. A set of axioms is inconsistent if its conjunction implies [False]. For the case of [eq_rect_eq], consistency has been verified outside of Coq via "informal" metatheory.
|
adamc@118
|
325
|
adamc@118
|
326 This axiom is equivalent to another that is more commonly known and mentioned in type theory circles. *)
|
adamc@118
|
327
|
adamc@118
|
328 Print Streicher_K.
|
adamc@118
|
329 (** [[
|
adamc@118
|
330
|
adamc@118
|
331 Streicher_K =
|
adamc@118
|
332 fun U : Type => UIP_refl__Streicher_K U (UIP_refl U)
|
adamc@118
|
333 : forall (U : Type) (x : U) (P : x = x -> Prop),
|
adamc@118
|
334 P (refl_equal x) -> forall p : x = x, P p
|
adamc@118
|
335 ]]
|
adamc@118
|
336
|
adamc@118
|
337 This is the unfortunately-named "Streicher's axiom K," which says that a predicate on properly-typed equality proofs holds of all such proofs if it holds of reflexivity. *)
|
adamc@118
|
338
|
adamc@118
|
339 End fhlist_map.
|
adamc@118
|
340
|
adamc@119
|
341
|
adamc@119
|
342 (** * Type-Casts in Theorem Statements *)
|
adamc@119
|
343
|
adamc@119
|
344 (** Sometimes we need to use tricks with equality just to state the theorems that we care about. To illustrate, we start by defining a concatenation function for [fhlist]s. *)
|
adamc@119
|
345
|
adamc@119
|
346 Section fhapp.
|
adamc@119
|
347 Variable A : Type.
|
adamc@119
|
348 Variable B : A -> Type.
|
adamc@119
|
349
|
adamc@119
|
350 Fixpoint fhapp (ls1 ls2 : list A) {struct ls1}
|
adamc@119
|
351 : fhlist B ls1 -> fhlist B ls2 -> fhlist B (ls1 ++ ls2) :=
|
adamc@119
|
352 match ls1 return fhlist _ ls1 -> _ -> fhlist _ (ls1 ++ ls2) with
|
adamc@119
|
353 | nil => fun _ hls2 => hls2
|
adamc@119
|
354 | _ :: _ => fun hls1 hls2 => (fst hls1, fhapp _ _ (snd hls1) hls2)
|
adamc@119
|
355 end.
|
adamc@119
|
356
|
adamc@119
|
357 Implicit Arguments fhapp [ls1 ls2].
|
adamc@119
|
358
|
adamc@119
|
359 (** We might like to prove that [fhapp] is associative.
|
adamc@119
|
360
|
adamc@119
|
361 [[
|
adamc@119
|
362
|
adamc@119
|
363 Theorem fhapp_ass : forall ls1 ls2 ls3
|
adamc@119
|
364 (hls1 : fhlist B ls1) (hls2 : fhlist B ls2) (hls3 : fhlist B ls3),
|
adamc@119
|
365 fhapp hls1 (fhapp hls2 hls3) = fhapp (fhapp hls1 hls2) hls3.
|
adamc@119
|
366
|
adamc@119
|
367 [[
|
adamc@119
|
368
|
adamc@119
|
369 The term
|
adamc@119
|
370 "fhapp (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3) (fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) hls1 hls2)
|
adamc@119
|
371 hls3" has type "fhlist B ((ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3)"
|
adamc@119
|
372 while it is expected to have type "fhlist B (ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)"
|
adamc@119
|
373 ]]
|
adamc@119
|
374
|
adamc@119
|
375 This first cut at the theorem statement does not even type-check. We know that the two [fhlist] types appearing in the error message are always equal, by associativity of normal list append, but this fact is not apparent to the type checker. This stems from the fact that Coq's equality is %\textit{%#<i>#intensional#</i>#%}%, in the sense that type equality theorems can never be applied after the fact to get a term to type-check. Instead, we need to make use of equality explicitly in the theorem statement. *)
|
adamc@119
|
376
|
adamc@119
|
377 Theorem fhapp_ass : forall ls1 ls2 ls3
|
adamc@119
|
378 (pf : (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = ls1 ++ (ls2 ++ ls3))
|
adamc@119
|
379 (hls1 : fhlist B ls1) (hls2 : fhlist B ls2) (hls3 : fhlist B ls3),
|
adamc@119
|
380 fhapp hls1 (fhapp hls2 hls3)
|
adamc@119
|
381 = match pf in (_ = ls) return fhlist _ ls with
|
adamc@119
|
382 | refl_equal => fhapp (fhapp hls1 hls2) hls3
|
adamc@119
|
383 end.
|
adamc@119
|
384 induction ls1; crush.
|
adamc@119
|
385
|
adamc@119
|
386 (** The first remaining subgoal looks trivial enough:
|
adamc@119
|
387
|
adamc@119
|
388 [[
|
adamc@119
|
389
|
adamc@119
|
390 ============================
|
adamc@119
|
391 fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3 =
|
adamc@119
|
392 match pf in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
|
adamc@119
|
393 | refl_equal => fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3
|
adamc@119
|
394 end
|
adamc@119
|
395 ]]
|
adamc@119
|
396
|
adamc@119
|
397 We can try what worked in previous examples.
|
adamc@119
|
398
|
adamc@119
|
399 [[
|
adamc@119
|
400 case pf.
|
adamc@119
|
401
|
adamc@119
|
402 [[
|
adamc@119
|
403
|
adamc@119
|
404 User error: Cannot solve a second-order unification problem
|
adamc@119
|
405 ]]
|
adamc@119
|
406
|
adamc@119
|
407 It seems we have reached another case where it is unclear how to use a dependent [match] to implement case analysis on our proof. The [UIP_refl] theorem can come to our rescue again. *)
|
adamc@119
|
408
|
adamc@119
|
409 rewrite (UIP_refl _ _ pf).
|
adamc@119
|
410 (** [[
|
adamc@119
|
411
|
adamc@119
|
412 ============================
|
adamc@119
|
413 fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3 =
|
adamc@119
|
414 fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3
|
adamc@119
|
415 ]] *)
|
adamc@119
|
416
|
adamc@119
|
417 reflexivity.
|
adamc@119
|
418
|
adamc@119
|
419 (** Our second subgoal is trickier.
|
adamc@119
|
420
|
adamc@119
|
421 [[
|
adamc@119
|
422
|
adamc@119
|
423 pf : a :: (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3
|
adamc@119
|
424 ============================
|
adamc@119
|
425 (a0,
|
adamc@119
|
426 fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2 ++ ls3) b
|
adamc@119
|
427 (fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3)) =
|
adamc@119
|
428 match pf in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
|
adamc@119
|
429 | refl_equal =>
|
adamc@119
|
430 (a0,
|
adamc@119
|
431 fhapp (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3)
|
adamc@119
|
432 (fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) b hls2) hls3)
|
adamc@119
|
433 end
|
adamc@119
|
434 ]]
|
adamc@119
|
435
|
adamc@119
|
436
|
adamc@119
|
437 [[
|
adamc@119
|
438
|
adamc@119
|
439 rewrite (UIP_refl _ _ pf).
|
adamc@119
|
440
|
adamc@119
|
441 [[
|
adamc@119
|
442 The term "pf" has type "a :: (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3"
|
adamc@119
|
443 while it is expected to have type "?556 = ?556"
|
adamc@119
|
444 ]]
|
adamc@119
|
445
|
adamc@119
|
446 We can only apply [UIP_refl] on proofs of equality with syntactically equal operands, which is not the case of [pf] here. We will need to manipulate the form of this subgoal to get us to a point where we may use [UIP_refl]. A first step is obtaining a proof suitable to use in applying the induction hypothesis. Inversion on the structure of [pf] is sufficient for that. *)
|
adamc@119
|
447
|
adamc@119
|
448 injection pf; intro pf'.
|
adamc@119
|
449 (** [[
|
adamc@119
|
450
|
adamc@119
|
451 pf : a :: (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3
|
adamc@119
|
452 pf' : (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3
|
adamc@119
|
453 ============================
|
adamc@119
|
454 (a0,
|
adamc@119
|
455 fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2 ++ ls3) b
|
adamc@119
|
456 (fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3)) =
|
adamc@119
|
457 match pf in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
|
adamc@119
|
458 | refl_equal =>
|
adamc@119
|
459 (a0,
|
adamc@119
|
460 fhapp (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3)
|
adamc@119
|
461 (fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) b hls2) hls3)
|
adamc@119
|
462 end
|
adamc@119
|
463 ]]
|
adamc@119
|
464
|
adamc@119
|
465 Now we can rewrite using the inductive hypothesis. *)
|
adamc@119
|
466
|
adamc@119
|
467 rewrite (IHls1 _ _ pf').
|
adamc@119
|
468 (** [[
|
adamc@119
|
469
|
adamc@119
|
470 ============================
|
adamc@119
|
471 (a0,
|
adamc@119
|
472 match pf' in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
|
adamc@119
|
473 | refl_equal =>
|
adamc@119
|
474 fhapp (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3)
|
adamc@119
|
475 (fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) b hls2) hls3
|
adamc@119
|
476 end) =
|
adamc@119
|
477 match pf in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
|
adamc@119
|
478 | refl_equal =>
|
adamc@119
|
479 (a0,
|
adamc@119
|
480 fhapp (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3)
|
adamc@119
|
481 (fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) b hls2) hls3)
|
adamc@119
|
482 end
|
adamc@119
|
483 ]]
|
adamc@119
|
484
|
adamc@119
|
485 We have made an important bit of progress, as now only a single call to [fhapp] appears in the conclusion. Trying case analysis on our proofs still will not work, but there is a move we can make to enable it. Not only does just one call to [fhapp] matter to us now, but it also %\textit{%#<i>#does not matter what the result of the call is#</i>#%}%. In other words, the subgoal should remain true if we replace this [fhapp] call with a fresh variable. The [generalize] tactic helps us do exactly that. *)
|
adamc@119
|
486
|
adamc@119
|
487 generalize (fhapp (fhapp b hls2) hls3).
|
adamc@119
|
488 (** [[
|
adamc@119
|
489
|
adamc@119
|
490 forall f : fhlist B ((ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3),
|
adamc@119
|
491 (a0,
|
adamc@119
|
492 match pf' in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
|
adamc@119
|
493 | refl_equal => f
|
adamc@119
|
494 end) =
|
adamc@119
|
495 match pf in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
|
adamc@119
|
496 | refl_equal => (a0, f)
|
adamc@119
|
497 end
|
adamc@119
|
498 ]]
|
adamc@119
|
499
|
adamc@119
|
500 The conclusion has gotten markedly simpler. It seems counterintuitive that we can have an easier time of proving a more general theorem, but that is exactly the case here and for many other proofs that use dependent types heavily. Speaking informally, the reason why this kind of activity helps is that [match] annotations only support variables in certain positions. By reducing more elements of a goal to variables, built-in tactics can have more success building [match] terms under the hood.
|
adamc@119
|
501
|
adamc@119
|
502 In this case, it is helpful to generalize over our two proofs as well. *)
|
adamc@119
|
503
|
adamc@119
|
504 generalize pf pf'.
|
adamc@119
|
505 (** [[
|
adamc@119
|
506
|
adamc@119
|
507 forall (pf0 : a :: (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)
|
adamc@119
|
508 (pf'0 : (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)
|
adamc@119
|
509 (f : fhlist B ((ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3)),
|
adamc@119
|
510 (a0,
|
adamc@119
|
511 match pf'0 in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
|
adamc@119
|
512 | refl_equal => f
|
adamc@119
|
513 end) =
|
adamc@119
|
514 match pf0 in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
|
adamc@119
|
515 | refl_equal => (a0, f)
|
adamc@119
|
516 end
|
adamc@119
|
517 ]]
|
adamc@119
|
518
|
adamc@119
|
519 To an experienced dependent types hacker, the appearance of this goal term calls for a celebration. The formula has a critical property that indicates that our problems are over. To get our proofs into the right form to apply [UIP_refl], we need to use associativity of list append to rewrite their types. We could not do that before because other parts of the goal require the proofs to retain their original types. In particular, the call to [fhapp] that we generalized must have type [(ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3], for some values of the list variables. If we rewrite the type of the proof used to type-cast this value to something like [ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3 = ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3], then the lefthand side of the equality would no longer match the type of the term we are trying to cast.
|
adamc@119
|
520
|
adamc@119
|
521 However, now that we have generalized over the [fhapp] call, the type of the term being type-cast appears explicitly in the goal and %\textit{%#<i>#may be rewritten as well#</i>#%}%. In particular, the final masterstroke is rewriting everywhere in our goal using associativity of list append. *)
|
adamc@119
|
522
|
adamc@119
|
523 rewrite app_ass.
|
adamc@119
|
524 (** [[
|
adamc@119
|
525
|
adamc@119
|
526 ============================
|
adamc@119
|
527 forall (pf0 : a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3 = a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)
|
adamc@119
|
528 (pf'0 : ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3 = ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)
|
adamc@119
|
529 (f : fhlist B (ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)),
|
adamc@119
|
530 (a0,
|
adamc@119
|
531 match pf'0 in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
|
adamc@119
|
532 | refl_equal => f
|
adamc@119
|
533 end) =
|
adamc@119
|
534 match pf0 in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
|
adamc@119
|
535 | refl_equal => (a0, f)
|
adamc@119
|
536 end
|
adamc@119
|
537 ]]
|
adamc@119
|
538
|
adamc@119
|
539 We can see that we have achieved the crucial property: the type of each generalized equality proof has syntactically equal operands. This makes it easy to finish the proof with [UIP_refl]. *)
|
adamc@119
|
540
|
adamc@119
|
541 intros.
|
adamc@119
|
542 rewrite (UIP_refl _ _ pf0).
|
adamc@119
|
543 rewrite (UIP_refl _ _ pf'0).
|
adamc@119
|
544 reflexivity.
|
adamc@119
|
545 Qed.
|
adamc@119
|
546 End fhapp.
|
adamc@120
|
547
|
adamc@120
|
548 Implicit Arguments fhapp [A B ls1 ls2].
|
adamc@120
|
549
|
adamc@120
|
550
|
adamc@120
|
551 (** * Heterogeneous Equality *)
|
adamc@120
|
552
|
adamc@120
|
553 (** There is another equality predicate, defined in the [JMeq] module of the standard library, implementing %\textit{%#<i>#heterogeneous equality#</i>#%}%. *)
|
adamc@120
|
554
|
adamc@120
|
555 Print JMeq.
|
adamc@120
|
556 (** [[
|
adamc@120
|
557
|
adamc@120
|
558 Inductive JMeq (A : Type) (x : A) : forall B : Type, B -> Prop :=
|
adamc@120
|
559 JMeq_refl : JMeq x x
|
adamc@120
|
560 ]]
|
adamc@120
|
561
|
adamc@120
|
562 [JMeq] stands for "John Major equality," a name coined by Conor McBride as a sort of pun about British politics. [JMeq] starts out looking a lot like [eq]. The crucial difference is that we may use [JMeq] %\textit{%#<i>#on arguments of different types#</i>#%}%. For instance, a lemma that we failed to establish before is trivial with [JMeq]. It makes for prettier theorem statements to define some syntactic shorthand first. *)
|
adamc@120
|
563
|
adamc@120
|
564 Infix "==" := JMeq (at level 70, no associativity).
|
adamc@120
|
565
|
adamc@121
|
566 Definition UIP_refl' (A : Type) (x : A) (pf : x = x) : pf == refl_equal x :=
|
adamc@120
|
567 match pf return (pf == refl_equal _) with
|
adamc@120
|
568 | refl_equal => JMeq_refl _
|
adamc@120
|
569 end.
|
adamc@120
|
570
|
adamc@120
|
571 (** There is no quick way to write such a proof by tactics, but the underlying proof term that we want is trivial.
|
adamc@120
|
572
|
adamc@121
|
573 Suppose that we want to use [UIP_refl'] to establish another lemma of the kind of we have run into several times so far. *)
|
adamc@120
|
574
|
adamc@120
|
575 Lemma lemma4 : forall (A : Type) (x : A) (pf : x = x),
|
adamc@120
|
576 O = match pf with refl_equal => O end.
|
adamc@121
|
577 intros; rewrite (UIP_refl' pf); reflexivity.
|
adamc@120
|
578 Qed.
|
adamc@120
|
579
|
adamc@120
|
580 (** All in all, refreshingly straightforward, but there really is no such thing as a free lunch. The use of [rewrite] is implemented in terms of an axiom: *)
|
adamc@120
|
581
|
adamc@120
|
582 Check JMeq_eq.
|
adamc@120
|
583 (** [[
|
adamc@120
|
584
|
adamc@120
|
585 JMeq_eq
|
adamc@120
|
586 : forall (A : Type) (x y : A), x == y -> x = y
|
adamc@120
|
587 ]] *)
|
adamc@120
|
588
|
adamc@120
|
589 (** It may be surprising that we cannot prove that heterogeneous equality implies normal equality. The difficulties are the same kind we have seen so far, based on limitations of [match] annotations.
|
adamc@120
|
590
|
adamc@120
|
591 We can redo our [fhapp] associativity proof based around [JMeq]. *)
|
adamc@120
|
592
|
adamc@120
|
593 Section fhapp'.
|
adamc@120
|
594 Variable A : Type.
|
adamc@120
|
595 Variable B : A -> Type.
|
adamc@120
|
596
|
adamc@120
|
597 (** This time, the naive theorem statement type-checks. *)
|
adamc@120
|
598
|
adamc@120
|
599 Theorem fhapp_ass' : forall ls1 ls2 ls3
|
adamc@120
|
600 (hls1 : fhlist B ls1) (hls2 : fhlist B ls2) (hls3 : fhlist B ls3),
|
adamc@120
|
601 fhapp hls1 (fhapp hls2 hls3) == fhapp (fhapp hls1 hls2) hls3.
|
adamc@120
|
602 induction ls1; crush.
|
adamc@120
|
603
|
adamc@120
|
604 (** Even better, [crush] discharges the first subgoal automatically. The second subgoal is:
|
adamc@120
|
605
|
adamc@120
|
606 [[
|
adamc@120
|
607
|
adamc@120
|
608 ============================
|
adamc@120
|
609 (a0,
|
adamc@120
|
610 fhapp (B:=B) (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2 ++ ls3) b
|
adamc@120
|
611 (fhapp (B:=B) (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3)) ==
|
adamc@120
|
612 (a0,
|
adamc@120
|
613 fhapp (B:=B) (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3)
|
adamc@120
|
614 (fhapp (B:=B) (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) b hls2) hls3)
|
adamc@120
|
615 ]]
|
adamc@120
|
616
|
adamc@120
|
617 It looks like one rewrite with the inductive hypothesis should be enough to make the goal trivial.
|
adamc@120
|
618
|
adamc@120
|
619 [[
|
adamc@120
|
620
|
adamc@120
|
621 rewrite IHls1.
|
adamc@120
|
622
|
adamc@120
|
623 [[
|
adamc@120
|
624
|
adamc@120
|
625 Error: Impossible to unify "fhlist B ((ls1 ++ ?1572) ++ ?1573)" with
|
adamc@120
|
626 "fhlist B (ls1 ++ ?1572 ++ ?1573)"
|
adamc@120
|
627 ]]
|
adamc@120
|
628
|
adamc@120
|
629 We see that [JMeq] is not a silver bullet. We can use it to simplify the statements of equality facts, but the Coq type-checker uses non-trivial heterogeneous equality facts no more readily than it uses standard equality facts. Here, the problem is that the form [(e1, e2)] is syntactic sugar for an explicit application of a constructor of an inductive type. That application mentions the type of each tuple element explicitly, and our [rewrite] tries to change one of those elements without updating the corresponding type argument.
|
adamc@120
|
630
|
adamc@120
|
631 We can get around this problem by another multiple use of [generalize]. We want to bring into the goal the proper instance of the inductive hypothesis, and we also want to generalize the two relevant uses of [fhapp]. *)
|
adamc@120
|
632
|
adamc@120
|
633 generalize (fhapp b (fhapp hls2 hls3))
|
adamc@120
|
634 (fhapp (fhapp b hls2) hls3)
|
adamc@120
|
635 (IHls1 _ _ b hls2 hls3).
|
adamc@120
|
636 (** [[
|
adamc@120
|
637
|
adamc@120
|
638 ============================
|
adamc@120
|
639 forall (f : fhlist B (ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3))
|
adamc@120
|
640 (f0 : fhlist B ((ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3)), f == f0 -> (a0, f) == (a0, f0)
|
adamc@120
|
641 ]]
|
adamc@120
|
642
|
adamc@120
|
643 Now we can rewrite with append associativity, as before. *)
|
adamc@120
|
644
|
adamc@120
|
645 rewrite app_ass.
|
adamc@120
|
646 (** [[
|
adamc@120
|
647
|
adamc@120
|
648 ============================
|
adamc@120
|
649 forall f f0 : fhlist B (ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3), f == f0 -> (a0, f) == (a0, f0)
|
adamc@120
|
650 ]]
|
adamc@120
|
651
|
adamc@120
|
652 From this point, the goal is trivial. *)
|
adamc@120
|
653
|
adamc@120
|
654 intros f f0 H; rewrite H; reflexivity.
|
adamc@120
|
655 Qed.
|
adamc@120
|
656 End fhapp'.
|
adamc@121
|
657
|
adamc@121
|
658
|
adamc@121
|
659 (** * Equivalence of Equality Axioms *)
|
adamc@121
|
660
|
adamc@121
|
661 (** Assuming axioms (like axiom K and [JMeq_eq]) is a hazardous business. The due diligence associated with it is necessarily global in scope, since two axioms may be consistent alone but inconsistent together. It turns out that all of the major axioms proposed for reasoning about equality in Coq are logically equivalent, so that we only need to pick one to assert without proof. In this section, we demonstrate this by showing how each the previous two sections' approaches reduces to the other logically.
|
adamc@121
|
662
|
adamc@121
|
663 To show that [JMeq] and its axiom let us prove [UIP_refl], we start from the lemma [UIP_refl'] from the previous section. The rest of the proof is trivial. *)
|
adamc@121
|
664
|
adamc@121
|
665 Lemma UIP_refl'' : forall (A : Type) (x : A) (pf : x = x), pf = refl_equal x.
|
adamc@121
|
666 intros; rewrite (UIP_refl' pf); reflexivity.
|
adamc@121
|
667 Qed.
|
adamc@121
|
668
|
adamc@121
|
669 (** The other direction is perhaps more interesting. Assume that we only have the axiom of the [Eqdep] module available. We can define [JMeq] in a way that satisfies the same interface as the combination of the [JMeq] module's inductive definition and axiom. *)
|
adamc@121
|
670
|
adamc@121
|
671 Definition JMeq' (A : Type) (x : A) (B : Type) (y : B) : Prop :=
|
adamc@121
|
672 exists pf : B = A, x = match pf with refl_equal => y end.
|
adamc@121
|
673
|
adamc@121
|
674 Infix "===" := JMeq' (at level 70, no associativity).
|
adamc@121
|
675
|
adamc@121
|
676 (** We say that, by definition, [x] and [y] are equal if and only if there exists a proof [pf] that their types are equal, such that [x] equals the result of casting [y] with [pf]. This statement can look strange from the standpoint of classical math, where we almost never mention proofs explicitly with quantifiers in formulas, but it is perfectly legal Coq code.
|
adamc@121
|
677
|
adamc@121
|
678 We can easily prove a theorem with the same type as that of the [JMeq_refl] constructor of [JMeq]. *)
|
adamc@121
|
679
|
adamc@121
|
680 (** remove printing exists *)
|
adamc@121
|
681 Theorem JMeq_refl' : forall (A : Type) (x : A), x === x.
|
adamc@121
|
682 intros; unfold JMeq'; exists (refl_equal A); reflexivity.
|
adamc@121
|
683 Qed.
|
adamc@121
|
684
|
adamc@121
|
685 (** printing exists $\exists$ *)
|
adamc@121
|
686
|
adamc@121
|
687 (** The proof of an analogue to [JMeq_eq] is a little more interesting, but most of the action is in appealing to [UIP_refl]. *)
|
adamc@121
|
688
|
adamc@121
|
689 Theorem JMeq_eq' : forall (A : Type) (x y : A),
|
adamc@121
|
690 x === y -> x = y.
|
adamc@121
|
691 unfold JMeq'; intros.
|
adamc@121
|
692 (** [[
|
adamc@121
|
693
|
adamc@121
|
694 H : exists pf : A = A,
|
adamc@121
|
695 x = match pf in (_ = T) return T with
|
adamc@121
|
696 | refl_equal => y
|
adamc@121
|
697 end
|
adamc@121
|
698 ============================
|
adamc@121
|
699 x = y
|
adamc@121
|
700 ]] *)
|
adamc@121
|
701
|
adamc@121
|
702 destruct H.
|
adamc@121
|
703 (** [[
|
adamc@121
|
704
|
adamc@121
|
705 x0 : A = A
|
adamc@121
|
706 H : x = match x0 in (_ = T) return T with
|
adamc@121
|
707 | refl_equal => y
|
adamc@121
|
708 end
|
adamc@121
|
709 ============================
|
adamc@121
|
710 x = y
|
adamc@121
|
711 ]] *)
|
adamc@121
|
712
|
adamc@121
|
713 rewrite H.
|
adamc@121
|
714 (** [[
|
adamc@121
|
715
|
adamc@121
|
716 x0 : A = A
|
adamc@121
|
717 ============================
|
adamc@121
|
718 match x0 in (_ = T) return T with
|
adamc@121
|
719 | refl_equal => y
|
adamc@121
|
720 end = y
|
adamc@121
|
721 ]] *)
|
adamc@121
|
722
|
adamc@121
|
723 rewrite (UIP_refl _ _ x0); reflexivity.
|
adamc@121
|
724 Qed.
|
adamc@121
|
725
|
adamc@121
|
726 (** We see that, in a very formal sense, we are free to switch back and forth between the two styles of proofs about equality proofs. One style may be more convenient than the other for some proofs, but we can always intercovert between our results. The style that does not use heterogeneous equality may be preferable in cases where many results do not require the tricks of this chapter, since then the use of axioms is avoided altogether for the simple cases, and a wider audience will be able to follow those "simple" proofs. On the other hand, heterogeneous equality often makes for shorter and more readable theorem statements. *)
|