adam@398
|
1 (* Copyright (c) 2008-2012, Adam Chlipala
|
adamc@26
|
2 *
|
adamc@26
|
3 * This work is licensed under a
|
adamc@26
|
4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
|
adamc@26
|
5 * Unported License.
|
adamc@26
|
6 * The license text is available at:
|
adamc@26
|
7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
|
adamc@26
|
8 *)
|
adamc@26
|
9
|
adamc@26
|
10 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@26
|
11 Require Import List.
|
adamc@26
|
12
|
adam@314
|
13 Require Import CpdtTactics.
|
adamc@26
|
14
|
adamc@26
|
15 Set Implicit Arguments.
|
adamc@26
|
16 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@26
|
17
|
adamc@26
|
18
|
adamc@74
|
19 (** %\part{Basic Programming and Proving}
|
adamc@74
|
20
|
adamc@74
|
21 \chapter{Introducing Inductive Types}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
22
|
adam@315
|
23 (** In a sense, CIC is built from just two relatively straightforward features: function types and inductive types. From this modest foundation, we can prove effectively all of the theorems of math and carry out effectively all program verifications, with enough effort expended. This chapter introduces induction and recursion for functional programming in Coq. Most of our examples reproduce functionality from the Coq standard library, and we have tried to copy the standard library's choices of identifiers, where possible, so many of the definitions here are already available in the default Coq environment.
|
adam@315
|
24
|
adam@315
|
25 The last chapter took a deep dive into some of the more advanced Coq features, to highlight the unusual approach that I advocate in this book. However, from this point on, we will rewind and go back to basics, presenting the relevant features of Coq in a more bottom-up manner. A useful first step is a discussion of the differences and relationships between proofs and programs in Coq. *)
|
adam@315
|
26
|
adam@315
|
27
|
adam@315
|
28 (** * Proof Terms *)
|
adam@315
|
29
|
adam@420
|
30 (** Mainstream presentations of mathematics treat proofs as objects that exist outside of the universe of mathematical objects. However, for a variety of reasoning tasks, it is convenient to encode proofs, traditional mathematical objects, and programs within a single formal language. Validity checks on mathematical objects are useful in any setting, to catch typoes and other uninteresting errors. The benefits of static typing for programs are widely recognized, and Coq brings those benefits to both mathematical objects and programs via a uniform mechanism. In fact, from this point on, we will not bother to distinguish between programs and mathematical objects. Many mathematical formalisms are most easily encoded in terms of programs.
|
adam@315
|
31
|
adam@400
|
32 Proofs are fundamentally different from programs, because any two proofs of a theorem are considered equivalent, from a formal standpoint if not from an engineering standpoint. However, we can use the same type-checking technology to check proofs as we use to validate our programs. This is the%\index{Curry-Howard correspondence}% _Curry-Howard correspondence_ %\cite{Curry,Howard}%, an approach for relating proofs and programs. We represent mathematical theorems as types, such that a theorem's proofs are exactly those programs that type-check at the corresponding type.
|
adam@315
|
33
|
adam@315
|
34 The last chapter's example already snuck in an instance of Curry-Howard. We used the token [->] to stand for both function types and logical implications. One reasonable conclusion upon seeing this might be that some fancy overloading of notations is at work. In fact, functions and implications are precisely identical according to Curry-Howard! That is, they are just two ways of describing the same computational phenomenon.
|
adam@315
|
35
|
adam@315
|
36 A short demonstration should explain how this can be. The identity function over the natural numbers is certainly not a controversial program. *)
|
adam@315
|
37
|
adam@315
|
38 Check (fun x : nat => x).
|
adam@315
|
39 (** [: nat -> nat] *)
|
adam@315
|
40
|
adam@315
|
41 (** Consider this alternate program, which is almost identical to the last one. *)
|
adam@315
|
42
|
adam@315
|
43 Check (fun x : True => x).
|
adam@315
|
44 (** [: True -> True] *)
|
adam@315
|
45
|
adam@315
|
46 (** The identity program is interpreted as a proof that %\index{Gallina terms!True}%[True], the always-true proposition, implies itself! What we see is that Curry-Howard interprets implications as functions, where an input is a proposition being assumed and an output is a proposition being deduced. This intuition is not too far from a common one for informal theorem proving, where we might already think of an implication proof as a process for transforming a hypothesis into a conclusion.
|
adam@315
|
47
|
adam@315
|
48 There are also more primitive proof forms available. For instance, the term %\index{Gallina terms!I}%[I] is the single proof of [True], applicable in any context. *)
|
adam@315
|
49
|
adam@315
|
50 Check I.
|
adam@315
|
51 (** [: True] *)
|
adam@315
|
52
|
adam@315
|
53 (** With [I], we can prove another simple propositional theorem. *)
|
adam@315
|
54
|
adam@315
|
55 Check (fun _ : False => I).
|
adam@315
|
56 (** [: False -> True] *)
|
adam@315
|
57
|
adam@315
|
58 (** No proofs of %\index{Gallina terms!False}%[False] exist in the top-level context, but the implication-as-function analogy gives us an easy way to, for example, show that [False] implies itself. *)
|
adam@315
|
59
|
adam@315
|
60 Check (fun x : False => x).
|
adam@315
|
61 (** [: False -> False] *)
|
adam@315
|
62
|
adam@315
|
63 (** In fact, [False] implies anything, and we can take advantage of this fact with an odd looking [match] expression that has no branches. Since there are no rules for deducing [False], there are no cases to consider! *)
|
adam@315
|
64
|
adam@315
|
65 Check (fun x : False => match x with end : True).
|
adam@315
|
66 (** [: False -> True] *)
|
adam@315
|
67
|
adam@420
|
68 (** Every one of these example programs whose type looks like a logical formula is a%\index{proof term}% _proof term_. We use that name for any Gallina term of a logical type, and we will elaborate shortly on what makes a type logical.
|
adam@315
|
69
|
adam@317
|
70 In the rest of this chapter, we will introduce different ways of defining types. Every example type can be interpreted alternatively as a type of programs or %\index{proposition}%propositions (i.e., formulas or theorem statements).
|
adam@317
|
71
|
adam@398
|
72 One of the first types we introduce will be [bool], with constructors [true] and [false]. Newcomers to Coq often wonder about the distinction between [True] and [true] and the distinction between [False] and [false]. One glib answer is that [True] and [False] are types, but [true] and [false] are not. A more useful answer is that Coq's metatheory guarantees that any term of type [bool] _evaluates_ to either [true] or [false]. This means that we have an _algorithm_ for answering any question phrased as an expression of type [bool]. Conversely, most propositions do not evaluate to [True] or [False]; the language of inductively defined propositions is much richer than that. We ought to be glad that we have no algorithm for deciding mathematical truth, since otherwise it would be clear that we could not formalize undecidable properties, like most any properties of general-purpose programs. *)
|
adamc@26
|
73
|
adamc@26
|
74
|
adamc@26
|
75 (** * Enumerations *)
|
adamc@26
|
76
|
adam@419
|
77 (** Coq inductive types generalize the %\index{algebraic datatypes}%algebraic datatypes found in %\index{Haskell}%Haskell and %\index{ML}%ML. Confusingly enough, inductive types also generalize %\index{generalized algebraic datatypes}%generalized algebraic datatypes (GADTs), by adding the possibility for type dependency. Even so, it is worth backing up from the examples of the last chapter and going over basic, algebraic datatype uses of inductive datatypes, because the chance to prove things about the values of these types adds new wrinkles beyond usual practice in Haskell and ML.
|
adamc@26
|
78
|
adam@315
|
79 The singleton type [unit] is an inductive type:%\index{Gallina terms!unit}\index{Gallina terms!tt}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
80
|
adamc@26
|
81 Inductive unit : Set :=
|
adamc@26
|
82 | tt.
|
adamc@26
|
83
|
adamc@26
|
84 (** This vernacular command defines a new inductive type [unit] whose only value is [tt], as we can see by checking the types of the two identifiers: *)
|
adamc@26
|
85
|
adamc@26
|
86 Check unit.
|
adamc@208
|
87 (** [unit : Set] *)
|
adamc@26
|
88
|
adamc@26
|
89 Check tt.
|
adamc@208
|
90 (** [tt : unit] *)
|
adamc@26
|
91
|
adamc@26
|
92 (** We can prove that [unit] is a genuine singleton type. *)
|
adamc@26
|
93
|
adamc@26
|
94 Theorem unit_singleton : forall x : unit, x = tt.
|
adamc@208
|
95
|
adam@315
|
96 (** The important thing about an inductive type is, unsurprisingly, that you can do induction over its values, and induction is the key to proving this theorem. We ask to proceed by induction on the variable [x].%\index{tactics!induction}% *)
|
adamc@208
|
97
|
adamc@41
|
98 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@26
|
99 induction x.
|
adamc@26
|
100
|
adamc@208
|
101 (** The goal changes to:
|
adamc@208
|
102 [[
|
adamc@26
|
103 tt = tt
|
adam@302
|
104 ]]
|
adam@302
|
105 *)
|
adamc@208
|
106
|
adamc@26
|
107 (** ...which we can discharge trivially. *)
|
adamc@208
|
108
|
adamc@26
|
109 reflexivity.
|
adamc@26
|
110 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
111 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@26
|
112
|
adam@315
|
113 (** It seems kind of odd to write a proof by induction with no inductive hypotheses. We could have arrived at the same result by beginning the proof with:%\index{tactics!destruct}% [[
|
adamc@26
|
114
|
adamc@26
|
115 destruct x.
|
adamc@205
|
116
|
adamc@205
|
117 ]]
|
adamc@205
|
118
|
adam@420
|
119 %\noindent%...which corresponds to "proof by case analysis" in classical math. For non-recursive inductive types, the two tactics will always have identical behavior. Often case analysis is sufficient, even in proofs about recursive types, and it is nice to avoid introducing unneeded induction hypotheses.
|
adamc@26
|
120
|
adam@398
|
121 What exactly _is_ the %\index{induction principles}%induction principle for [unit]? We can ask Coq: *)
|
adamc@26
|
122
|
adamc@26
|
123 Check unit_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
124 (** [unit_ind : forall P : unit -> Prop, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u] *)
|
adamc@26
|
125
|
adam@315
|
126 (** Every [Inductive] command defining a type [T] also defines an induction principle named [T_ind]. Recall from the last section that our type, operations over it, and principles for reasoning about it all live in the same language and are described by the same type system. The key to telling what is a program and what is a proof lies in the distinction between the type %\index{Gallina terms!Prop}%[Prop], which appears in our induction principle; and the type %\index{Gallina terms!Set}%[Set], which we have seen a few times already.
|
adamc@26
|
127
|
adam@315
|
128 The convention goes like this: [Set] is the type of normal types used in programming, and the values of such types are programs. [Prop] is the type of logical propositions, and the values of such types are proofs. Thus, an induction principle has a type that shows us that it is a function for building proofs.
|
adamc@26
|
129
|
adam@400
|
130 Specifically, [unit_ind] quantifies over a predicate [P] over [unit] values. If we can present a proof that [P] holds of [tt], then we are rewarded with a proof that [P] holds for any value [u] of type [unit]. In our last proof, the predicate was [(fun u : unit => u = tt)].
|
adam@315
|
131
|
adam@315
|
132 The definition of [unit] places the type in [Set]. By replacing [Set] with [Prop], [unit] with [True], and [tt] with [I], we arrive at precisely the definition of [True] that the Coq standard library employs! The program type [unit] is the Curry-Howard equivalent of the proposition [True]. We might make the tongue-in-cheek claim that, while philosophers have expended much ink on the nature of truth, we have now determined that truth is the [unit] type of functional programming.
|
adamc@26
|
133
|
adamc@26
|
134 %\medskip%
|
adamc@26
|
135
|
adam@315
|
136 We can define an inductive type even simpler than [unit]:%\index{Gallina terms!Empty\_set}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
137
|
adamc@26
|
138 Inductive Empty_set : Set := .
|
adamc@26
|
139
|
adamc@26
|
140 (** [Empty_set] has no elements. We can prove fun theorems about it: *)
|
adamc@26
|
141
|
adamc@26
|
142 Theorem the_sky_is_falling : forall x : Empty_set, 2 + 2 = 5.
|
adamc@41
|
143 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@26
|
144 destruct 1.
|
adamc@26
|
145 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
146 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@26
|
147
|
adam@317
|
148 (** Because [Empty_set] has no elements, the fact of having an element of this type implies anything. We use [destruct 1] instead of [destruct x] in the proof because unused quantified variables are relegated to being referred to by number. (There is a good reason for this, related to the unity of quantifiers and implication. At least within Coq's logical foundation of %\index{constructive logic}%constructive logic, which we elaborate on more in the next chapter, an implication is just a quantification over a proof, where the quantified variable is never used. It generally makes more sense to refer to implication hypotheses by number than by name, and Coq treats our quantifier over an unused variable as an implication in determining the proper behavior.)
|
adamc@26
|
149
|
adamc@26
|
150 We can see the induction principle that made this proof so easy: *)
|
adamc@26
|
151
|
adamc@26
|
152 Check Empty_set_ind.
|
adam@400
|
153 (** [Empty_set_ind : forall (P : Empty_set -> Prop) (e : Empty_set), P e] *)
|
adamc@26
|
154
|
adam@400
|
155 (** In other words, any predicate over values from the empty set holds vacuously of every such element. In the last proof, we chose the predicate [(fun _ : Empty_set => 2 + 2 = 5)].
|
adamc@26
|
156
|
adamc@26
|
157 We can also apply this get-out-of-jail-free card programmatically. Here is a lazy way of converting values of [Empty_set] to values of [unit]: *)
|
adamc@26
|
158
|
adamc@26
|
159 Definition e2u (e : Empty_set) : unit := match e with end.
|
adamc@26
|
160
|
adam@315
|
161 (** We employ [match] pattern matching as in the last chapter. Since we match on a value whose type has no constructors, there is no need to provide any branches. This idiom may look familiar; we employed it with proofs of [False] in the last section. In fact, [Empty_set] is the Curry-Howard equivalent of [False]. As for why [Empty_set] starts with a capital letter and not a lowercase letter like [unit] does, we must refer the reader to the authors of the Coq standard library, to which we try to be faithful.
|
adamc@26
|
162
|
adamc@26
|
163 %\medskip%
|
adamc@26
|
164
|
adam@315
|
165 Moving up the ladder of complexity, we can define the booleans:%\index{Gallina terms!bool}\index{Gallina terms!true}\index{Gallina terms!false}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
166
|
adamc@26
|
167 Inductive bool : Set :=
|
adamc@26
|
168 | true
|
adamc@26
|
169 | false.
|
adamc@26
|
170
|
adam@316
|
171 (** We can use less vacuous pattern matching to define boolean negation.%\index{Gallina terms!negb}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
172
|
adam@279
|
173 Definition negb (b : bool) : bool :=
|
adamc@26
|
174 match b with
|
adamc@26
|
175 | true => false
|
adamc@26
|
176 | false => true
|
adamc@26
|
177 end.
|
adamc@26
|
178
|
adam@317
|
179 (** An alternative definition desugars to the above, thanks to an %\index{Gallina terms!if}%[if] notation overloaded to work with any inductive type that has exactly two constructors: *)
|
adamc@27
|
180
|
adam@279
|
181 Definition negb' (b : bool) : bool :=
|
adamc@27
|
182 if b then false else true.
|
adamc@27
|
183
|
adam@279
|
184 (** We might want to prove that [negb] is its own inverse operation. *)
|
adamc@26
|
185
|
adam@279
|
186 Theorem negb_inverse : forall b : bool, negb (negb b) = b.
|
adamc@41
|
187 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@26
|
188 destruct b.
|
adamc@26
|
189
|
adamc@208
|
190 (** After we case-analyze on [b], we are left with one subgoal for each constructor of [bool].
|
adamc@26
|
191
|
adam@315
|
192 %\vspace{.1in} \noindent 2 \coqdockw{subgoals}\vspace{-.1in}%#<tt>2 subgoals</tt>#
|
adam@315
|
193
|
adamc@26
|
194 [[
|
adamc@26
|
195 ============================
|
adam@279
|
196 negb (negb true) = true
|
adamc@26
|
197 ]]
|
adam@315
|
198 %\noindent \coqdockw{subgoal} 2 \coqdockw{is}:%#<tt>subgoal 2 is</tt>#
|
adamc@26
|
199 [[
|
adam@279
|
200 negb (negb false) = false
|
adamc@208
|
201
|
adamc@26
|
202 ]]
|
adamc@26
|
203
|
adamc@26
|
204 The first subgoal follows by Coq's rules of computation, so we can dispatch it easily: *)
|
adamc@26
|
205
|
adamc@26
|
206 reflexivity.
|
adamc@26
|
207
|
adam@315
|
208 (** Likewise for the second subgoal, so we can restart the proof and give a very compact justification.%\index{Vernacular commands!Restart}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
209
|
adamc@26
|
210 Restart.
|
adam@315
|
211
|
adamc@26
|
212 destruct b; reflexivity.
|
adamc@26
|
213 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
214 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@27
|
215
|
adam@315
|
216 (** Another theorem about booleans illustrates another useful tactic.%\index{tactics!discriminate}% *)
|
adamc@27
|
217
|
adam@279
|
218 Theorem negb_ineq : forall b : bool, negb b <> b.
|
adamc@41
|
219 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@27
|
220 destruct b; discriminate.
|
adamc@27
|
221 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
222 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@27
|
223
|
adamc@27
|
224 (** [discriminate] is used to prove that two values of an inductive type are not equal, whenever the values are formed with different constructors. In this case, the different constructors are [true] and [false].
|
adamc@27
|
225
|
adamc@27
|
226 At this point, it is probably not hard to guess what the underlying induction principle for [bool] is. *)
|
adamc@27
|
227
|
adamc@27
|
228 Check bool_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
229 (** [bool_ind : forall P : bool -> Prop, P true -> P false -> forall b : bool, P b] *)
|
adamc@28
|
230
|
adam@315
|
231 (** That is, to prove that a property describes all [bool]s, prove that it describes both [true] and [false].
|
adam@315
|
232
|
adam@392
|
233 There is no interesting Curry-Howard analogue of [bool]. Of course, we can define such a type by replacing [Set] by [Prop] above, but the proposition we arrive at is not very useful. It is logically equivalent to [True], but it provides two indistinguishable primitive proofs, [true] and [false]. In the rest of the chapter, we will skip commenting on Curry-Howard versions of inductive definitions where such versions are not interesting. *)
|
adam@315
|
234
|
adamc@28
|
235
|
adamc@28
|
236 (** * Simple Recursive Types *)
|
adamc@28
|
237
|
adam@315
|
238 (** The natural numbers are the simplest common example of an inductive type that actually deserves the name.%\index{Gallina terms!nat}\index{Gallina terms!O}\index{Gallina terms!S}% *)
|
adamc@28
|
239
|
adamc@28
|
240 Inductive nat : Set :=
|
adamc@28
|
241 | O : nat
|
adamc@28
|
242 | S : nat -> nat.
|
adamc@28
|
243
|
adam@400
|
244 (** [O] is zero, and [S] is the successor function, so that [0] is syntactic sugar for [O], [1] for [S O], [2] for [S (S O)], and so on.
|
adamc@28
|
245
|
adam@316
|
246 Pattern matching works as we demonstrated in the last chapter:%\index{Gallina terms!pred}% *)
|
adamc@28
|
247
|
adamc@28
|
248 Definition isZero (n : nat) : bool :=
|
adamc@28
|
249 match n with
|
adamc@28
|
250 | O => true
|
adamc@28
|
251 | S _ => false
|
adamc@28
|
252 end.
|
adamc@28
|
253
|
adamc@28
|
254 Definition pred (n : nat) : nat :=
|
adamc@28
|
255 match n with
|
adamc@28
|
256 | O => O
|
adamc@28
|
257 | S n' => n'
|
adamc@28
|
258 end.
|
adamc@28
|
259
|
adamc@28
|
260 (** We can prove theorems by case analysis: *)
|
adamc@28
|
261
|
adamc@28
|
262 Theorem S_isZero : forall n : nat, isZero (pred (S (S n))) = false.
|
adamc@41
|
263 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
264 destruct n; reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
265 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
266 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
267
|
adam@316
|
268 (** We can also now get into genuine inductive theorems. First, we will need a recursive function, to make things interesting.%\index{Gallina terms!plus}% *)
|
adamc@28
|
269
|
adamc@208
|
270 Fixpoint plus (n m : nat) : nat :=
|
adamc@28
|
271 match n with
|
adamc@28
|
272 | O => m
|
adamc@28
|
273 | S n' => S (plus n' m)
|
adamc@28
|
274 end.
|
adamc@28
|
275
|
adamc@208
|
276 (** Recall that [Fixpoint] is Coq's mechanism for recursive function definitions. Some theorems about [plus] can be proved without induction. *)
|
adamc@28
|
277
|
adamc@28
|
278 Theorem O_plus_n : forall n : nat, plus O n = n.
|
adamc@41
|
279 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
280 intro; reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
281 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
282 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
283
|
adamc@208
|
284 (** Coq's computation rules automatically simplify the application of [plus], because unfolding the definition of [plus] gives us a [match] expression where the branch to be taken is obvious from syntax alone. If we just reverse the order of the arguments, though, this no longer works, and we need induction. *)
|
adamc@28
|
285
|
adamc@28
|
286 Theorem n_plus_O : forall n : nat, plus n O = n.
|
adamc@41
|
287 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
288 induction n.
|
adamc@28
|
289
|
adam@398
|
290 (** Our first subgoal is [plus O O = O], which _is_ trivial by computation. *)
|
adamc@28
|
291
|
adamc@28
|
292 reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
293
|
adamc@28
|
294 (** Our second subgoal is more work and also demonstrates our first inductive hypothesis.
|
adamc@28
|
295
|
adamc@28
|
296 [[
|
adamc@28
|
297 n : nat
|
adamc@28
|
298 IHn : plus n O = n
|
adamc@28
|
299 ============================
|
adamc@28
|
300 plus (S n) O = S n
|
adamc@208
|
301
|
adamc@28
|
302 ]]
|
adamc@28
|
303
|
adam@315
|
304 We can start out by using computation to simplify the goal as far as we can.%\index{tactics!simpl}% *)
|
adamc@28
|
305
|
adamc@28
|
306 simpl.
|
adamc@28
|
307
|
adam@400
|
308 (** Now the conclusion is [S (plus n O) = S n]. Using our inductive hypothesis: *)
|
adamc@28
|
309
|
adamc@28
|
310 rewrite IHn.
|
adamc@28
|
311
|
adamc@28
|
312 (** ...we get a trivial conclusion [S n = S n]. *)
|
adamc@28
|
313
|
adamc@28
|
314 reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
315
|
adam@315
|
316 (** Not much really went on in this proof, so the [crush] tactic from the [CpdtTactics] module can prove this theorem automatically. *)
|
adamc@28
|
317
|
adamc@28
|
318 Restart.
|
adam@315
|
319
|
adamc@28
|
320 induction n; crush.
|
adamc@28
|
321 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
322 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
323
|
adamc@28
|
324 (** We can check out the induction principle at work here: *)
|
adamc@28
|
325
|
adamc@28
|
326 Check nat_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
327 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
328 nat_ind : forall P : nat -> Prop,
|
adamc@208
|
329 P O -> (forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) -> forall n : nat, P n
|
adamc@208
|
330
|
adamc@208
|
331 ]]
|
adamc@28
|
332
|
adam@400
|
333 Each of the two cases of our last proof came from the type of one of the arguments to [nat_ind]. We chose [P] to be [(fun n : nat => plus n O = n)]. The first proof case corresponded to [P O] and the second case to [(forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n))]. The free variable [n] and inductive hypothesis [IHn] came from the argument types given here.
|
adamc@28
|
334
|
adam@315
|
335 Since [nat] has a constructor that takes an argument, we may sometimes need to know that that constructor is injective.%\index{tactics!injection}\index{tactics!trivial}% *)
|
adamc@28
|
336
|
adamc@28
|
337 Theorem S_inj : forall n m : nat, S n = S m -> n = m.
|
adamc@41
|
338 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
339 injection 1; trivial.
|
adamc@28
|
340 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
341 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@28
|
342
|
adam@400
|
343 (** The [injection] tactic refers to a premise by number, adding new equalities between the corresponding arguments of equated terms that are formed with the same constructor. We end up needing to prove [n = m -> n = m], so it is unsurprising that a tactic named [trivial] is able to finish the proof.
|
adamc@28
|
344
|
adam@417
|
345 There is also a very useful tactic called %\index{tactics!congruence}%[congruence] that can prove this theorem immediately. The [congruence] tactic generalizes [discriminate] and [injection], and it also adds reasoning about the general properties of equality, such as that a function returns equal results on equal arguments. That is, [congruence] is a%\index{theory of equality and uninterpreted functions}% _complete decision procedure for the theory of equality and uninterpreted functions_, plus some smarts about inductive types.
|
adamc@29
|
346
|
adamc@29
|
347 %\medskip%
|
adamc@29
|
348
|
adamc@29
|
349 We can define a type of lists of natural numbers. *)
|
adamc@29
|
350
|
adamc@29
|
351 Inductive nat_list : Set :=
|
adamc@29
|
352 | NNil : nat_list
|
adamc@29
|
353 | NCons : nat -> nat_list -> nat_list.
|
adamc@29
|
354
|
adamc@29
|
355 (** Recursive definitions are straightforward extensions of what we have seen before. *)
|
adamc@29
|
356
|
adamc@29
|
357 Fixpoint nlength (ls : nat_list) : nat :=
|
adamc@29
|
358 match ls with
|
adamc@29
|
359 | NNil => O
|
adamc@29
|
360 | NCons _ ls' => S (nlength ls')
|
adamc@29
|
361 end.
|
adamc@29
|
362
|
adamc@208
|
363 Fixpoint napp (ls1 ls2 : nat_list) : nat_list :=
|
adamc@29
|
364 match ls1 with
|
adamc@29
|
365 | NNil => ls2
|
adamc@29
|
366 | NCons n ls1' => NCons n (napp ls1' ls2)
|
adamc@29
|
367 end.
|
adamc@29
|
368
|
adamc@29
|
369 (** Inductive theorem proving can again be automated quite effectively. *)
|
adamc@29
|
370
|
adamc@29
|
371 Theorem nlength_napp : forall ls1 ls2 : nat_list, nlength (napp ls1 ls2)
|
adamc@29
|
372 = plus (nlength ls1) (nlength ls2).
|
adamc@41
|
373 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@29
|
374 induction ls1; crush.
|
adamc@29
|
375 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
376 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@29
|
377
|
adamc@29
|
378 Check nat_list_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
379 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
380 nat_list_ind
|
adamc@29
|
381 : forall P : nat_list -> Prop,
|
adamc@29
|
382 P NNil ->
|
adamc@29
|
383 (forall (n : nat) (n0 : nat_list), P n0 -> P (NCons n n0)) ->
|
adamc@29
|
384 forall n : nat_list, P n
|
adamc@29
|
385 ]]
|
adamc@29
|
386
|
adamc@29
|
387 %\medskip%
|
adamc@29
|
388
|
adam@420
|
389 In general, we can implement any "tree" types as inductive types. For example, here are binary trees of naturals. *)
|
adamc@29
|
390
|
adamc@29
|
391 Inductive nat_btree : Set :=
|
adamc@29
|
392 | NLeaf : nat_btree
|
adamc@29
|
393 | NNode : nat_btree -> nat -> nat_btree -> nat_btree.
|
adamc@29
|
394
|
adamc@29
|
395 Fixpoint nsize (tr : nat_btree) : nat :=
|
adamc@29
|
396 match tr with
|
adamc@35
|
397 | NLeaf => S O
|
adamc@29
|
398 | NNode tr1 _ tr2 => plus (nsize tr1) (nsize tr2)
|
adamc@29
|
399 end.
|
adamc@29
|
400
|
adamc@208
|
401 Fixpoint nsplice (tr1 tr2 : nat_btree) : nat_btree :=
|
adamc@29
|
402 match tr1 with
|
adamc@35
|
403 | NLeaf => NNode tr2 O NLeaf
|
adamc@29
|
404 | NNode tr1' n tr2' => NNode (nsplice tr1' tr2) n tr2'
|
adamc@29
|
405 end.
|
adamc@29
|
406
|
adamc@29
|
407 Theorem plus_assoc : forall n1 n2 n3 : nat, plus (plus n1 n2) n3 = plus n1 (plus n2 n3).
|
adamc@41
|
408 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@29
|
409 induction n1; crush.
|
adamc@29
|
410 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
411 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@29
|
412
|
adamc@29
|
413 Theorem nsize_nsplice : forall tr1 tr2 : nat_btree, nsize (nsplice tr1 tr2)
|
adamc@29
|
414 = plus (nsize tr2) (nsize tr1).
|
adamc@41
|
415 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@375
|
416 Hint Rewrite n_plus_O plus_assoc.
|
adamc@29
|
417
|
adamc@29
|
418 induction tr1; crush.
|
adamc@29
|
419 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
420 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@29
|
421
|
adam@315
|
422 (** It is convenient that these proofs go through so easily, but it is useful to check that the tree induction principle works as usual. *)
|
adam@315
|
423
|
adamc@29
|
424 Check nat_btree_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
425 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
426 nat_btree_ind
|
adamc@29
|
427 : forall P : nat_btree -> Prop,
|
adamc@29
|
428 P NLeaf ->
|
adamc@29
|
429 (forall n : nat_btree,
|
adamc@29
|
430 P n -> forall (n0 : nat) (n1 : nat_btree), P n1 -> P (NNode n n0 n1)) ->
|
adamc@29
|
431 forall n : nat_btree, P n
|
adam@302
|
432 ]]
|
adam@315
|
433
|
adam@315
|
434 We have the usual two cases, one for each constructor of [nat_btree]. *)
|
adamc@30
|
435
|
adamc@30
|
436
|
adamc@30
|
437 (** * Parameterized Types *)
|
adamc@30
|
438
|
adam@316
|
439 (** We can also define %\index{polymorphism}%polymorphic inductive types, as with algebraic datatypes in Haskell and ML.%\index{Gallina terms!list}\index{Gallina terms!Nil}\index{Gallina terms!Cons}\index{Gallina terms!length}\index{Gallina terms!app}% *)
|
adamc@30
|
440
|
adamc@30
|
441 Inductive list (T : Set) : Set :=
|
adamc@30
|
442 | Nil : list T
|
adamc@30
|
443 | Cons : T -> list T -> list T.
|
adamc@30
|
444
|
adamc@30
|
445 Fixpoint length T (ls : list T) : nat :=
|
adamc@30
|
446 match ls with
|
adamc@30
|
447 | Nil => O
|
adamc@30
|
448 | Cons _ ls' => S (length ls')
|
adamc@30
|
449 end.
|
adamc@30
|
450
|
adamc@208
|
451 Fixpoint app T (ls1 ls2 : list T) : list T :=
|
adamc@30
|
452 match ls1 with
|
adamc@30
|
453 | Nil => ls2
|
adamc@30
|
454 | Cons x ls1' => Cons x (app ls1' ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
455 end.
|
adamc@30
|
456
|
adamc@30
|
457 Theorem length_app : forall T (ls1 ls2 : list T), length (app ls1 ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
458 = plus (length ls1) (length ls2).
|
adamc@41
|
459 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@30
|
460 induction ls1; crush.
|
adamc@30
|
461 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
462 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@30
|
463
|
adam@420
|
464 (** There is a useful shorthand for writing many definitions that share the same parameter, based on Coq's%\index{sections}\index{Vernacular commands!Section}\index{Vernacular commands!Variable}% _section_ mechanism. The following block of code is equivalent to the above: *)
|
adamc@30
|
465
|
adamc@30
|
466 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@30
|
467 Reset list.
|
adamc@30
|
468 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@30
|
469
|
adamc@30
|
470 Section list.
|
adamc@30
|
471 Variable T : Set.
|
adamc@30
|
472
|
adamc@30
|
473 Inductive list : Set :=
|
adamc@30
|
474 | Nil : list
|
adamc@30
|
475 | Cons : T -> list -> list.
|
adamc@30
|
476
|
adamc@30
|
477 Fixpoint length (ls : list) : nat :=
|
adamc@30
|
478 match ls with
|
adamc@30
|
479 | Nil => O
|
adamc@30
|
480 | Cons _ ls' => S (length ls')
|
adamc@30
|
481 end.
|
adamc@30
|
482
|
adamc@208
|
483 Fixpoint app (ls1 ls2 : list) : list :=
|
adamc@30
|
484 match ls1 with
|
adamc@30
|
485 | Nil => ls2
|
adamc@30
|
486 | Cons x ls1' => Cons x (app ls1' ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
487 end.
|
adamc@30
|
488
|
adamc@30
|
489 Theorem length_app : forall ls1 ls2 : list, length (app ls1 ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
490 = plus (length ls1) (length ls2).
|
adamc@41
|
491 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@30
|
492 induction ls1; crush.
|
adamc@30
|
493 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
494 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@30
|
495 End list.
|
adamc@30
|
496
|
adamc@35
|
497 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@35
|
498 Implicit Arguments Nil [T].
|
adamc@35
|
499 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@35
|
500
|
adamc@210
|
501 (** After we end the section, the [Variable]s we used are added as extra function parameters for each defined identifier, as needed. We verify that this has happened using the [Print] command, a cousin of [Check] which shows the definition of a symbol, rather than just its type. *)
|
adamc@30
|
502
|
adamc@202
|
503 Print list.
|
adamc@208
|
504 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
505 Inductive list (T : Set) : Set :=
|
adam@316
|
506 Nil : list T | Cons : T -> list T -> list T
|
adamc@208
|
507
|
adamc@202
|
508 ]]
|
adamc@30
|
509
|
adamc@202
|
510 The final definition is the same as what we wrote manually before. The other elements of the section are altered similarly, turning out exactly as they were before, though we managed to write their definitions more succinctly. *)
|
adamc@30
|
511
|
adamc@30
|
512 Check length.
|
adamc@208
|
513 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
514 length
|
adamc@30
|
515 : forall T : Set, list T -> nat
|
adamc@30
|
516 ]]
|
adamc@30
|
517
|
adamc@202
|
518 The parameter [T] is treated as a new argument to the induction principle, too. *)
|
adamc@30
|
519
|
adamc@30
|
520 Check list_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
521 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
522 list_ind
|
adamc@30
|
523 : forall (T : Set) (P : list T -> Prop),
|
adamc@30
|
524 P (Nil T) ->
|
adamc@30
|
525 (forall (t : T) (l : list T), P l -> P (Cons t l)) ->
|
adamc@30
|
526 forall l : list T, P l
|
adamc@30
|
527 ]]
|
adamc@30
|
528
|
adamc@30
|
529 Thus, even though we just saw that [T] is added as an extra argument to the constructor [Cons], there is no quantifier for [T] in the type of the inductive case like there is for each of the other arguments. *)
|
adamc@31
|
530
|
adamc@31
|
531
|
adamc@31
|
532 (** * Mutually Inductive Types *)
|
adamc@31
|
533
|
adamc@31
|
534 (** We can define inductive types that refer to each other: *)
|
adamc@31
|
535
|
adamc@31
|
536 Inductive even_list : Set :=
|
adamc@31
|
537 | ENil : even_list
|
adamc@31
|
538 | ECons : nat -> odd_list -> even_list
|
adamc@31
|
539
|
adamc@31
|
540 with odd_list : Set :=
|
adamc@31
|
541 | OCons : nat -> even_list -> odd_list.
|
adamc@31
|
542
|
adamc@31
|
543 Fixpoint elength (el : even_list) : nat :=
|
adamc@31
|
544 match el with
|
adamc@31
|
545 | ENil => O
|
adamc@31
|
546 | ECons _ ol => S (olength ol)
|
adamc@31
|
547 end
|
adamc@31
|
548
|
adamc@31
|
549 with olength (ol : odd_list) : nat :=
|
adamc@31
|
550 match ol with
|
adamc@31
|
551 | OCons _ el => S (elength el)
|
adamc@31
|
552 end.
|
adamc@31
|
553
|
adamc@208
|
554 Fixpoint eapp (el1 el2 : even_list) : even_list :=
|
adamc@31
|
555 match el1 with
|
adamc@31
|
556 | ENil => el2
|
adamc@31
|
557 | ECons n ol => ECons n (oapp ol el2)
|
adamc@31
|
558 end
|
adamc@31
|
559
|
adamc@208
|
560 with oapp (ol : odd_list) (el : even_list) : odd_list :=
|
adamc@31
|
561 match ol with
|
adamc@31
|
562 | OCons n el' => OCons n (eapp el' el)
|
adamc@31
|
563 end.
|
adamc@31
|
564
|
adamc@31
|
565 (** Everything is going roughly the same as in past examples, until we try to prove a theorem similar to those that came before. *)
|
adamc@31
|
566
|
adamc@31
|
567 Theorem elength_eapp : forall el1 el2 : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
568 elength (eapp el1 el2) = plus (elength el1) (elength el2).
|
adamc@41
|
569 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@31
|
570 induction el1; crush.
|
adamc@31
|
571
|
adamc@31
|
572 (** One goal remains: [[
|
adamc@31
|
573
|
adamc@31
|
574 n : nat
|
adamc@31
|
575 o : odd_list
|
adamc@31
|
576 el2 : even_list
|
adamc@31
|
577 ============================
|
adamc@31
|
578 S (olength (oapp o el2)) = S (plus (olength o) (elength el2))
|
adamc@31
|
579 ]]
|
adamc@31
|
580
|
adamc@31
|
581 We have no induction hypothesis, so we cannot prove this goal without starting another induction, which would reach a similar point, sending us into a futile infinite chain of inductions. The problem is that Coq's generation of [T_ind] principles is incomplete. We only get non-mutual induction principles generated by default. *)
|
adamc@31
|
582
|
adamc@31
|
583 Abort.
|
adamc@31
|
584 Check even_list_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
585 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
586 even_list_ind
|
adamc@31
|
587 : forall P : even_list -> Prop,
|
adamc@31
|
588 P ENil ->
|
adamc@31
|
589 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P (ECons n o)) ->
|
adamc@31
|
590 forall e : even_list, P e
|
adamc@208
|
591
|
adamc@31
|
592 ]]
|
adamc@31
|
593
|
adam@316
|
594 We see that no inductive hypotheses are included anywhere in the type. To get them, we must ask for mutual principles as we need them, using the %\index{Vernacular commands!Scheme}%[Scheme] command. *)
|
adamc@31
|
595
|
adamc@31
|
596 Scheme even_list_mut := Induction for even_list Sort Prop
|
adamc@31
|
597 with odd_list_mut := Induction for odd_list Sort Prop.
|
adamc@31
|
598
|
adam@316
|
599 (** This invocation of [Scheme] asks for the creation of induction principles [even_list_mut] for the type [even_list] and [odd_list_mut] for the type [odd_list]. The [Induction] keyword says we want standard induction schemes, since [Scheme] supports more exotic choices. Finally, [Sort Prop] establishes that we really want induction schemes, not recursion schemes, which are the same according to Curry-Howard, save for the [Prop]/[Set] distinction. *)
|
adam@316
|
600
|
adamc@31
|
601 Check even_list_mut.
|
adamc@208
|
602 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
603 even_list_mut
|
adamc@31
|
604 : forall (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop),
|
adamc@31
|
605 P ENil ->
|
adamc@31
|
606 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) ->
|
adamc@31
|
607 (forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) ->
|
adamc@31
|
608 forall e : even_list, P e
|
adamc@208
|
609
|
adamc@31
|
610 ]]
|
adamc@31
|
611
|
adam@316
|
612 This is the principle we wanted in the first place. There is one more wrinkle left in using it: the [induction] tactic will not apply it for us automatically. It will be helpful to look at how to prove one of our past examples without using [induction], so that we can then generalize the technique to mutual inductive types.%\index{tactics!apply}% *)
|
adamc@31
|
613
|
adamc@31
|
614 Theorem n_plus_O' : forall n : nat, plus n O = n.
|
adamc@31
|
615 apply (nat_ind (fun n => plus n O = n)); crush.
|
adamc@31
|
616 Qed.
|
adamc@31
|
617
|
adamc@31
|
618 (** From this example, we can see that [induction] is not magic. It only does some bookkeeping for us to make it easy to apply a theorem, which we can do directly with the [apply] tactic. We apply not just an identifier but a partial application of it, specifying the predicate we mean to prove holds for all naturals.
|
adamc@31
|
619
|
adamc@31
|
620 This technique generalizes to our mutual example: *)
|
adamc@31
|
621
|
adamc@31
|
622 Theorem elength_eapp : forall el1 el2 : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
623 elength (eapp el1 el2) = plus (elength el1) (elength el2).
|
adamc@41
|
624
|
adamc@31
|
625 apply (even_list_mut
|
adamc@31
|
626 (fun el1 : even_list => forall el2 : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
627 elength (eapp el1 el2) = plus (elength el1) (elength el2))
|
adamc@31
|
628 (fun ol : odd_list => forall el : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
629 olength (oapp ol el) = plus (olength ol) (elength el))); crush.
|
adamc@31
|
630 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
631 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@31
|
632
|
adamc@31
|
633 (** We simply need to specify two predicates, one for each of the mutually inductive types. In general, it would not be a good idea to assume that a proof assistant could infer extra predicates, so this way of applying mutual induction is about as straightforward as we could hope for. *)
|
adamc@33
|
634
|
adamc@33
|
635
|
adamc@33
|
636 (** * Reflexive Types *)
|
adamc@33
|
637
|
adam@398
|
638 (** A kind of inductive type called a _reflexive type_ is defined in terms of functions that have the type being defined as their range. One very useful class of examples is in modeling variable binders. Our example will be an encoding of the syntax of first-order logic. Since the idea of syntactic encodings of logic may require a bit of acclimation, let us first consider a simpler formula type for a subset of propositional logic. *)
|
adam@316
|
639
|
adam@316
|
640 Inductive pformula : Set :=
|
adam@316
|
641 | Truth : pformula
|
adam@316
|
642 | Falsehood : pformula
|
adam@316
|
643 | Conjunction : pformula -> pformula -> pformula.
|
adam@316
|
644
|
adam@398
|
645 (** A key distinction here is between, for instance, the _syntax_ [Truth] and its _semantics_ [True]. We can make the semantics explicit with a recursive function. This function uses the infix operator %\index{Gallina operators!/\textbackslash}%[/\], which desugars to uses of the type family %\index{Gallina terms!and}%[and] from the standard library. The family [and] implements conjunction, the [Prop] Curry-Howard analogue of the usual pair type from functional programming (which is the type family %\index{Gallina terms!prod}%[prod] in Coq's standard library). *)
|
adam@316
|
646
|
adam@316
|
647 Fixpoint pformulaDenote (f : pformula) : Prop :=
|
adam@316
|
648 match f with
|
adam@316
|
649 | Truth => True
|
adam@316
|
650 | Falsehood => False
|
adam@316
|
651 | Conjunction f1 f2 => pformulaDenote f1 /\ pformulaDenote f2
|
adam@316
|
652 end.
|
adam@316
|
653
|
adam@392
|
654 (** This is just a warm-up that does not use reflexive types, the new feature we mean to introduce. When we set our sights on first-order logic instead, it becomes very handy to give constructors recursive arguments that are functions. *)
|
adamc@33
|
655
|
adamc@33
|
656 Inductive formula : Set :=
|
adamc@33
|
657 | Eq : nat -> nat -> formula
|
adamc@33
|
658 | And : formula -> formula -> formula
|
adamc@33
|
659 | Forall : (nat -> formula) -> formula.
|
adamc@33
|
660
|
adam@420
|
661 (** Our kinds of formulas are equalities between naturals, conjunction, and universal quantification over natural numbers. We avoid needing to include a notion of "variables" in our type, by using Coq functions to encode quantification. For instance, here is the encoding of [forall x : nat, x = x]:%\index{Vernacular commands!Example}% *)
|
adamc@33
|
662
|
adamc@33
|
663 Example forall_refl : formula := Forall (fun x => Eq x x).
|
adamc@33
|
664
|
adamc@33
|
665 (** We can write recursive functions over reflexive types quite naturally. Here is one translating our formulas into native Coq propositions. *)
|
adamc@33
|
666
|
adamc@33
|
667 Fixpoint formulaDenote (f : formula) : Prop :=
|
adamc@33
|
668 match f with
|
adamc@33
|
669 | Eq n1 n2 => n1 = n2
|
adamc@33
|
670 | And f1 f2 => formulaDenote f1 /\ formulaDenote f2
|
adamc@33
|
671 | Forall f' => forall n : nat, formulaDenote (f' n)
|
adamc@33
|
672 end.
|
adamc@33
|
673
|
adamc@33
|
674 (** We can also encode a trivial formula transformation that swaps the order of equality and conjunction operands. *)
|
adamc@33
|
675
|
adamc@33
|
676 Fixpoint swapper (f : formula) : formula :=
|
adamc@33
|
677 match f with
|
adamc@33
|
678 | Eq n1 n2 => Eq n2 n1
|
adamc@33
|
679 | And f1 f2 => And (swapper f2) (swapper f1)
|
adamc@33
|
680 | Forall f' => Forall (fun n => swapper (f' n))
|
adamc@33
|
681 end.
|
adamc@33
|
682
|
adamc@33
|
683 (** It is helpful to prove that this transformation does not make true formulas false. *)
|
adamc@33
|
684
|
adamc@33
|
685 Theorem swapper_preserves_truth : forall f, formulaDenote f -> formulaDenote (swapper f).
|
adamc@41
|
686 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@33
|
687 induction f; crush.
|
adamc@33
|
688 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
689 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@33
|
690
|
adamc@33
|
691 (** We can take a look at the induction principle behind this proof. *)
|
adamc@33
|
692
|
adamc@33
|
693 Check formula_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
694 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
695 formula_ind
|
adamc@33
|
696 : forall P : formula -> Prop,
|
adamc@33
|
697 (forall n n0 : nat, P (Eq n n0)) ->
|
adamc@33
|
698 (forall f0 : formula,
|
adamc@33
|
699 P f0 -> forall f1 : formula, P f1 -> P (And f0 f1)) ->
|
adamc@33
|
700 (forall f1 : nat -> formula,
|
adamc@33
|
701 (forall n : nat, P (f1 n)) -> P (Forall f1)) ->
|
adamc@33
|
702 forall f2 : formula, P f2
|
adamc@208
|
703
|
adamc@208
|
704 ]]
|
adamc@33
|
705
|
adam@398
|
706 Focusing on the [Forall] case, which comes third, we see that we are allowed to assume that the theorem holds _for any application of the argument function [f1]_. That is, Coq induction principles do not follow a simple rule that the textual representations of induction variables must get shorter in appeals to induction hypotheses. Luckily for us, the people behind the metatheory of Coq have verified that this flexibility does not introduce unsoundness.
|
adamc@33
|
707
|
adamc@33
|
708 %\medskip%
|
adamc@33
|
709
|
adam@316
|
710 Up to this point, we have seen how to encode in Coq more and more of what is possible with algebraic datatypes in %\index{Haskell}%Haskell and %\index{ML}%ML. This may have given the inaccurate impression that inductive types are a strict extension of algebraic datatypes. In fact, Coq must rule out some types allowed by Haskell and ML, for reasons of soundness. Reflexive types provide our first good example of such a case.
|
adamc@33
|
711
|
adam@400
|
712 Given our last example of an inductive type, many readers are probably eager to try encoding the syntax of %\index{lambda calculus}%lambda calculus. Indeed, the function-based representation technique that we just used, called%\index{higher-order abstract syntax}\index{HOAS|see{higher-order abstract syntax}}% _higher-order abstract syntax_ (HOAS)%~\cite{HOAS}%, is the representation of choice for lambda calculi in %\index{Twelf}%Twelf and in many applications implemented in Haskell and ML. Let us try to import that choice to Coq: *)
|
adam@400
|
713 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@437
|
714 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@400
|
715 Inductive term : Set := App | Abs.
|
adam@400
|
716 Reset term.
|
adam@420
|
717 Definition uhoh := O.
|
adam@437
|
718 (* end thide *)
|
adam@400
|
719 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@33
|
720 (** [[
|
adamc@33
|
721 Inductive term : Set :=
|
adamc@33
|
722 | App : term -> term -> term
|
adamc@33
|
723 | Abs : (term -> term) -> term.
|
adamc@33
|
724 ]]
|
adamc@33
|
725
|
adam@316
|
726 <<
|
adam@316
|
727 Error: Non strictly positive occurrence of "term" in "(term -> term) -> term"
|
adam@316
|
728 >>
|
adam@316
|
729
|
adam@400
|
730 We have run afoul of the%\index{strict positivity requirement}\index{positivity requirement}% _strict positivity requirement_ for inductive definitions, which says that the type being defined may not occur to the left of an arrow in the type of a constructor argument. It is important that the type of a constructor is viewed in terms of a series of arguments and a result, since obviously we need recursive occurrences to the lefts of the outermost arrows if we are to have recursive occurrences at all. Our candidate definition above violates the positivity requirement because it involves an argument of type [term -> term], where the type [term] that we are defining appears to the left of an arrow. The candidate type of [App] is fine, however, since every occurrence of [term] is either a constructor argument or the final result type.
|
adamc@33
|
731
|
adamc@33
|
732 Why must Coq enforce this restriction? Imagine that our last definition had been accepted, allowing us to write this function:
|
adamc@33
|
733
|
adamc@33
|
734 [[
|
adamc@33
|
735 Definition uhoh (t : term) : term :=
|
adamc@33
|
736 match t with
|
adamc@33
|
737 | Abs f => f t
|
adamc@33
|
738 | _ => t
|
adamc@33
|
739 end.
|
adamc@33
|
740
|
adamc@205
|
741 ]]
|
adamc@205
|
742
|
adamc@33
|
743 Using an informal idea of Coq's semantics, it is easy to verify that the application [uhoh (Abs uhoh)] will run forever. This would be a mere curiosity in OCaml and Haskell, where non-termination is commonplace, though the fact that we have a non-terminating program without explicit recursive function definitions is unusual.
|
adamc@33
|
744
|
adam@316
|
745 %\index{termination checking}%For Coq, however, this would be a disaster. The possibility of writing such a function would destroy all our confidence that proving a theorem means anything. Since Coq combines programs and proofs in one language, we would be able to prove every theorem with an infinite loop.
|
adamc@33
|
746
|
adamc@33
|
747 Nonetheless, the basic insight of HOAS is a very useful one, and there are ways to realize most benefits of HOAS in Coq. We will study a particular technique of this kind in the later chapters on programming language syntax and semantics. *)
|
adamc@34
|
748
|
adamc@34
|
749
|
adam@317
|
750 (** * An Interlude on Induction Principles *)
|
adamc@34
|
751
|
adam@317
|
752 (** As we have emphasized a few times already, Coq proofs are actually programs, written in the same language we have been using in our examples all along. We can get a first sense of what this means by taking a look at the definitions of some of the %\index{induction principles}%induction principles we have used. A close look at the details here will help us construct induction principles manually, which we will see is necessary for some more advanced inductive definitions. *)
|
adamc@34
|
753
|
adamc@34
|
754 Print unit_ind.
|
adam@437
|
755 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adamc@208
|
756 unit_ind =
|
adamc@208
|
757 fun P : unit -> Prop => unit_rect P
|
adamc@34
|
758 : forall P : unit -> Prop, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@208
|
759
|
adamc@34
|
760 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
761
|
adam@420
|
762 We see that this induction principle is defined in terms of a more general principle, [unit_rect]. The <<rec>> stands for "recursion principle," and the <<t>> at the end stands for [Type]. *)
|
adamc@34
|
763
|
adamc@34
|
764 Check unit_rect.
|
adamc@208
|
765 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
766 unit_rect
|
adamc@34
|
767 : forall P : unit -> Type, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@208
|
768
|
adamc@34
|
769 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
770
|
adam@400
|
771 The principle [unit_rect] gives [P] type [unit -> Type] instead of [unit -> Prop]. [Type] is another universe, like [Set] and [Prop]. In fact, it is a common supertype of both. Later on, we will discuss exactly what the significances of the different universes are. For now, it is just important that we can use [Type] as a sort of meta-universe that may turn out to be either [Set] or [Prop]. We can see the symmetry inherent in the subtyping relationship by printing the definition of another principle that was generated for [unit] automatically: *)
|
adamc@34
|
772
|
adamc@34
|
773 Print unit_rec.
|
adam@437
|
774 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adamc@208
|
775 unit_rec =
|
adamc@208
|
776 fun P : unit -> Set => unit_rect P
|
adamc@34
|
777 : forall P : unit -> Set, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@208
|
778
|
adamc@34
|
779 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
780
|
adam@317
|
781 This is identical to the definition for [unit_ind], except that we have substituted [Set] for [Prop]. For most inductive types [T], then, we get not just induction principles [T_ind], but also %\index{recursion principles}%recursion principles [T_rec]. We can use [T_rec] to write recursive definitions without explicit [Fixpoint] recursion. For instance, the following two definitions are equivalent: *)
|
adamc@34
|
782
|
adamc@34
|
783 Definition always_O (u : unit) : nat :=
|
adamc@34
|
784 match u with
|
adamc@34
|
785 | tt => O
|
adamc@34
|
786 end.
|
adamc@34
|
787
|
adamc@34
|
788 Definition always_O' (u : unit) : nat :=
|
adamc@34
|
789 unit_rec (fun _ : unit => nat) O u.
|
adamc@34
|
790
|
adamc@34
|
791 (** Going even further down the rabbit hole, [unit_rect] itself is not even a primitive. It is a functional program that we can write manually. *)
|
adamc@34
|
792
|
adamc@34
|
793 Print unit_rect.
|
adam@437
|
794 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adamc@208
|
795 unit_rect =
|
adamc@208
|
796 fun (P : unit -> Type) (f : P tt) (u : unit) =>
|
adamc@208
|
797 match u as u0 return (P u0) with
|
adamc@208
|
798 | tt => f
|
adamc@208
|
799 end
|
adamc@34
|
800 : forall P : unit -> Type, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@208
|
801
|
adamc@34
|
802 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
803
|
adam@400
|
804 The only new wrinkle here is the annotations on the [match] expression. This is a%\index{dependent pattern matching}% _dependently typed_ pattern match, because the _type_ of the expression depends on the _value_ being matched on. Of course, for this example, the dependency is degenerate; the value being matched on has type [unit], so it may only take on a single known value, [tt]. We will meet more involved examples later, especially in Part II of the book.
|
adam@317
|
805
|
adam@317
|
806 %\index{type inference}%Type inference for dependent pattern matching is undecidable, which can be proved by reduction from %\index{higher-order unification}%higher-order unification%~\cite{HOU}%. Thus, we often find ourselves needing to annotate our programs in a way that explains dependencies to the type checker. In the example of [unit_rect], we have an %\index{Gallina terms!as}%[as] clause, which binds a name for the discriminee; and a %\index{Gallina terms!return}%[return] clause, which gives a way to compute the [match] result type as a function of the discriminee.
|
adamc@34
|
807
|
adamc@34
|
808 To prove that [unit_rect] is nothing special, we can reimplement it manually. *)
|
adamc@34
|
809
|
adamc@34
|
810 Definition unit_rect' (P : unit -> Type) (f : P tt) (u : unit) :=
|
adamc@208
|
811 match u with
|
adamc@34
|
812 | tt => f
|
adamc@34
|
813 end.
|
adamc@34
|
814
|
adam@420
|
815 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@437
|
816 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@420
|
817 Definition foo := nat_rect.
|
adam@437
|
818 (* end thide *)
|
adam@420
|
819 (* end hide *)
|
adam@420
|
820
|
adam@317
|
821 (** We rely on Coq's heuristics for inferring [match] annotations, which are not consulted in the pretty-printing of terms.
|
adamc@34
|
822
|
adam@400
|
823 We can check the implementation [nat_rect] as well: *)
|
adamc@34
|
824
|
adamc@34
|
825 Print nat_rect.
|
adam@317
|
826
|
adam@317
|
827 (** %\vspace{-.05in}% [[
|
adam@400
|
828 nat_rect =
|
adamc@208
|
829 fun (P : nat -> Type) (f : P O) (f0 : forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) =>
|
adamc@208
|
830 fix F (n : nat) : P n :=
|
adamc@208
|
831 match n as n0 return (P n0) with
|
adamc@208
|
832 | O => f
|
adamc@208
|
833 | S n0 => f0 n0 (F n0)
|
adamc@208
|
834 end
|
adamc@208
|
835 : forall P : nat -> Type,
|
adamc@208
|
836 P O -> (forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) -> forall n : nat, P n
|
adamc@208
|
837 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
838
|
adam@400
|
839 Now we have an actual recursive definition. Expressions starting with %\index{Gallina terms!fix}%[fix] are anonymous forms of [Fixpoint], just as [fun] expressions stand for anonymous non-recursive functions. Beyond that, the syntax of [fix] mirrors that of [Fixpoint]. We can understand the definition of [nat_rect] better by reimplementing [nat_ind] using sections. *)
|
adamc@34
|
840
|
adam@317
|
841 Section nat_ind'.
|
adamc@208
|
842 (** First, we have the property of natural numbers that we aim to prove. *)
|
adamc@34
|
843
|
adam@317
|
844 Variable P : nat -> Prop.
|
adamc@34
|
845
|
adam@317
|
846 (** Then we require a proof of the [O] case, which we declare with the command %\index{Vernacular commands!Hypothesis}%[Hypothesis], which is a synonym for [Variable] that, by convention, is used for variables whose types are propositions. *)
|
adamc@34
|
847
|
adam@317
|
848 Hypothesis O_case : P O.
|
adamc@34
|
849
|
adamc@208
|
850 (** Next is a proof of the [S] case, which may assume an inductive hypothesis. *)
|
adamc@34
|
851
|
adam@317
|
852 Hypothesis S_case : forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n).
|
adamc@34
|
853
|
adamc@208
|
854 (** Finally, we define a recursive function to tie the pieces together. *)
|
adamc@34
|
855
|
adam@317
|
856 Fixpoint nat_ind' (n : nat) : P n :=
|
adam@317
|
857 match n with
|
adam@317
|
858 | O => O_case
|
adam@317
|
859 | S n' => S_case (nat_ind' n')
|
adam@317
|
860 end.
|
adam@317
|
861 End nat_ind'.
|
adamc@34
|
862
|
adam@400
|
863 (** Closing the section adds the [Variable]s and [Hypothesis]es as new [fun]-bound arguments to [nat_ind'], and, modulo the use of [Prop] instead of [Type], we end up with the exact same definition that was generated automatically for [nat_rect].
|
adamc@34
|
864
|
adam@317
|
865 %\medskip%
|
adamc@34
|
866
|
adam@317
|
867 We can also examine the definition of [even_list_mut], which we generated with [Scheme] for a mutually recursive type. *)
|
adamc@34
|
868
|
adam@317
|
869 Print even_list_mut.
|
adam@317
|
870 (** [[
|
adam@317
|
871 even_list_mut =
|
adam@317
|
872 fun (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop)
|
adam@317
|
873 (f : P ENil) (f0 : forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o))
|
adam@317
|
874 (f1 : forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) =>
|
adam@317
|
875 fix F (e : even_list) : P e :=
|
adam@317
|
876 match e as e0 return (P e0) with
|
adam@317
|
877 | ENil => f
|
adam@317
|
878 | ECons n o => f0 n o (F0 o)
|
adam@317
|
879 end
|
adam@317
|
880 with F0 (o : odd_list) : P0 o :=
|
adam@317
|
881 match o as o0 return (P0 o0) with
|
adam@317
|
882 | OCons n e => f1 n e (F e)
|
adam@317
|
883 end
|
adam@317
|
884 for F
|
adam@317
|
885 : forall (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop),
|
adam@317
|
886 P ENil ->
|
adam@317
|
887 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) ->
|
adam@317
|
888 (forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) ->
|
adam@317
|
889 forall e : even_list, P e
|
adamc@34
|
890
|
adam@317
|
891 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
892
|
adam@420
|
893 We see a mutually recursive [fix], with the different functions separated by %\index{Gallina terms!with}%[with] in the same way that they would be separated by <<and>> in ML. A final %\index{Gallina terms!for}%[for] clause identifies which of the mutually recursive functions should be the final value of the [fix] expression. Using this definition as a template, we can reimplement [even_list_mut] directly. *)
|
adamc@208
|
894
|
adam@317
|
895 Section even_list_mut'.
|
adam@317
|
896 (** First, we need the properties that we are proving. *)
|
adamc@208
|
897
|
adam@317
|
898 Variable Peven : even_list -> Prop.
|
adam@317
|
899 Variable Podd : odd_list -> Prop.
|
adamc@208
|
900
|
adam@317
|
901 (** Next, we need proofs of the three cases. *)
|
adamc@208
|
902
|
adam@317
|
903 Hypothesis ENil_case : Peven ENil.
|
adam@317
|
904 Hypothesis ECons_case : forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), Podd o -> Peven (ECons n o).
|
adam@317
|
905 Hypothesis OCons_case : forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), Peven e -> Podd (OCons n e).
|
adamc@208
|
906
|
adam@317
|
907 (** Finally, we define the recursive functions. *)
|
adamc@208
|
908
|
adam@317
|
909 Fixpoint even_list_mut' (e : even_list) : Peven e :=
|
adam@317
|
910 match e with
|
adam@317
|
911 | ENil => ENil_case
|
adam@317
|
912 | ECons n o => ECons_case n (odd_list_mut' o)
|
adam@317
|
913 end
|
adam@317
|
914 with odd_list_mut' (o : odd_list) : Podd o :=
|
adam@317
|
915 match o with
|
adam@317
|
916 | OCons n e => OCons_case n (even_list_mut' e)
|
adam@317
|
917 end.
|
adamc@34
|
918 End even_list_mut'.
|
adamc@34
|
919
|
adamc@34
|
920 (** Even induction principles for reflexive types are easy to implement directly. For our [formula] type, we can use a recursive definition much like those we wrote above. *)
|
adamc@34
|
921
|
adamc@34
|
922 Section formula_ind'.
|
adamc@34
|
923 Variable P : formula -> Prop.
|
adamc@38
|
924 Hypothesis Eq_case : forall n1 n2 : nat, P (Eq n1 n2).
|
adamc@38
|
925 Hypothesis And_case : forall f1 f2 : formula,
|
adamc@34
|
926 P f1 -> P f2 -> P (And f1 f2).
|
adamc@38
|
927 Hypothesis Forall_case : forall f : nat -> formula,
|
adamc@34
|
928 (forall n : nat, P (f n)) -> P (Forall f).
|
adamc@34
|
929
|
adamc@34
|
930 Fixpoint formula_ind' (f : formula) : P f :=
|
adamc@208
|
931 match f with
|
adamc@34
|
932 | Eq n1 n2 => Eq_case n1 n2
|
adamc@34
|
933 | And f1 f2 => And_case (formula_ind' f1) (formula_ind' f2)
|
adamc@34
|
934 | Forall f' => Forall_case f' (fun n => formula_ind' (f' n))
|
adamc@34
|
935 end.
|
adamc@34
|
936 End formula_ind'.
|
adamc@34
|
937
|
adam@317
|
938 (** It is apparent that induction principle implementations involve some tedium but not terribly much creativity. *)
|
adam@317
|
939
|
adamc@35
|
940
|
adamc@35
|
941 (** * Nested Inductive Types *)
|
adamc@35
|
942
|
adamc@35
|
943 (** Suppose we want to extend our earlier type of binary trees to trees with arbitrary finite branching. We can use lists to give a simple definition. *)
|
adamc@35
|
944
|
adamc@35
|
945 Inductive nat_tree : Set :=
|
adamc@35
|
946 | NLeaf' : nat_tree
|
adamc@35
|
947 | NNode' : nat -> list nat_tree -> nat_tree.
|
adamc@35
|
948
|
adam@420
|
949 (** This is an example of a%\index{nested inductive type}% _nested_ inductive type definition, because we use the type we are defining as an argument to a parametrized type family. Coq will not allow all such definitions; it effectively pretends that we are defining [nat_tree] mutually with a version of [list] specialized to [nat_tree], checking that the resulting expanded definition satisfies the usual rules. For instance, if we replaced [list] with a type family that used its parameter as a function argument, then the definition would be rejected as violating the positivity restriction.
|
adamc@35
|
950
|
adam@317
|
951 Like we encountered for mutual inductive types, we find that the automatically generated induction principle for [nat_tree] is too weak. *)
|
adamc@35
|
952
|
adamc@35
|
953 Check nat_tree_ind.
|
adamc@208
|
954 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@208
|
955 nat_tree_ind
|
adamc@35
|
956 : forall P : nat_tree -> Prop,
|
adamc@35
|
957 P NLeaf' ->
|
adamc@35
|
958 (forall (n : nat) (l : list nat_tree), P (NNode' n l)) ->
|
adamc@35
|
959 forall n : nat_tree, P n
|
adamc@208
|
960
|
adamc@35
|
961 ]]
|
adamc@35
|
962
|
adam@317
|
963 There is no command like [Scheme] that will implement an improved principle for us. In general, it takes creativity to figure out how to incorporate nested uses of different type families. This is roughly the same creativity employed in the traditional task of strengthening an induction hypothesis. Now that we know how to implement induction principles manually, we are in a position to apply just such creativity to this problem.
|
adamc@35
|
964
|
adamc@35
|
965 First, we will need an auxiliary definition, characterizing what it means for a property to hold of every element of a list. *)
|
adamc@35
|
966
|
adamc@35
|
967 Section All.
|
adamc@35
|
968 Variable T : Set.
|
adamc@35
|
969 Variable P : T -> Prop.
|
adamc@35
|
970
|
adamc@35
|
971 Fixpoint All (ls : list T) : Prop :=
|
adamc@35
|
972 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
973 | Nil => True
|
adamc@35
|
974 | Cons h t => P h /\ All t
|
adamc@35
|
975 end.
|
adamc@35
|
976 End All.
|
adamc@35
|
977
|
adam@317
|
978 (** It will be useful to review the definitions of [True] and [/\], since we will want to write manual proofs of them below. *)
|
adamc@35
|
979
|
adamc@35
|
980 Print True.
|
adam@317
|
981 (** [[
|
adamc@208
|
982 Inductive True : Prop := I : True
|
adamc@208
|
983 ]]
|
adamc@35
|
984
|
adamc@35
|
985 That is, [True] is a proposition with exactly one proof, [I], which we may always supply trivially.
|
adamc@35
|
986
|
adam@400
|
987 Finding the definition of [/\] takes a little more work. Coq supports user registration of arbitrary parsing rules, and it is such a rule that is letting us write [/\] instead of an application of some inductive type family. We can find the underlying inductive type with the %\index{Vernacular commands!Locate}%[Locate] command, whose argument may be a parsing token.%\index{Gallina terms!and}% *)
|
adamc@35
|
988
|
adamc@35
|
989 Locate "/\".
|
adam@317
|
990 (** [[
|
adam@317
|
991 "A /\ B" := and A B : type_scope (default interpretation)
|
adam@302
|
992 ]]
|
adam@302
|
993 *)
|
adamc@35
|
994
|
adamc@35
|
995 Print and.
|
adam@317
|
996 (** [[
|
adamc@208
|
997 Inductive and (A : Prop) (B : Prop) : Prop := conj : A -> B -> A /\ B
|
adam@317
|
998 ]]
|
adam@317
|
999 %\vspace{-.1in}%
|
adam@317
|
1000 <<
|
adamc@208
|
1001 For conj: Arguments A, B are implicit
|
adam@317
|
1002 >>
|
adamc@35
|
1003
|
adam@400
|
1004 In addition to the definition of [and] itself, we get information on %\index{implicit arguments}%implicit arguments (and some other information that we omit here). The implicit argument information tells us that we build a proof of a conjunction by calling the constructor [conj] on proofs of the conjuncts, with no need to include the types of those proofs as explicit arguments.
|
adamc@35
|
1005
|
adamc@35
|
1006 %\medskip%
|
adamc@35
|
1007
|
adamc@35
|
1008 Now we create a section for our induction principle, following the same basic plan as in the last section of this chapter. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1009
|
adamc@35
|
1010 Section nat_tree_ind'.
|
adamc@35
|
1011 Variable P : nat_tree -> Prop.
|
adamc@35
|
1012
|
adamc@38
|
1013 Hypothesis NLeaf'_case : P NLeaf'.
|
adamc@38
|
1014 Hypothesis NNode'_case : forall (n : nat) (ls : list nat_tree),
|
adamc@35
|
1015 All P ls -> P (NNode' n ls).
|
adamc@35
|
1016
|
adam@420
|
1017 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@437
|
1018 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@420
|
1019 Definition list_nat_tree_ind := O.
|
adam@437
|
1020 (* end thide *)
|
adam@420
|
1021 (* end hide *)
|
adam@420
|
1022
|
adamc@35
|
1023 (** A first attempt at writing the induction principle itself follows the intuition that nested inductive type definitions are expanded into mutual inductive definitions.
|
adamc@35
|
1024
|
adamc@35
|
1025 [[
|
adamc@35
|
1026 Fixpoint nat_tree_ind' (tr : nat_tree) : P tr :=
|
adamc@208
|
1027 match tr with
|
adamc@35
|
1028 | NLeaf' => NLeaf'_case
|
adamc@35
|
1029 | NNode' n ls => NNode'_case n ls (list_nat_tree_ind ls)
|
adamc@35
|
1030 end
|
adamc@35
|
1031
|
adamc@35
|
1032 with list_nat_tree_ind (ls : list nat_tree) : All P ls :=
|
adamc@208
|
1033 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
1034 | Nil => I
|
adamc@35
|
1035 | Cons tr rest => conj (nat_tree_ind' tr) (list_nat_tree_ind rest)
|
adamc@35
|
1036 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1037
|
adamc@205
|
1038 ]]
|
adamc@205
|
1039
|
adam@317
|
1040 Coq rejects this definition, saying
|
adam@317
|
1041 <<
|
adam@317
|
1042 Recursive call to nat_tree_ind' has principal argument equal to "tr"
|
adam@317
|
1043 instead of rest.
|
adam@317
|
1044 >>
|
adam@317
|
1045
|
adam@420
|
1046 There is no deep theoretical reason why this program should be rejected; Coq applies incomplete termination-checking heuristics, and it is necessary to learn a few of the most important rules. The term "nested inductive type" hints at the solution to this particular problem. Just like true mutually inductive types require mutually recursive induction principles, nested types require nested recursion. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1047
|
adamc@35
|
1048 Fixpoint nat_tree_ind' (tr : nat_tree) : P tr :=
|
adamc@208
|
1049 match tr with
|
adamc@35
|
1050 | NLeaf' => NLeaf'_case
|
adamc@35
|
1051 | NNode' n ls => NNode'_case n ls
|
adamc@35
|
1052 ((fix list_nat_tree_ind (ls : list nat_tree) : All P ls :=
|
adamc@208
|
1053 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
1054 | Nil => I
|
adamc@35
|
1055 | Cons tr rest => conj (nat_tree_ind' tr) (list_nat_tree_ind rest)
|
adamc@35
|
1056 end) ls)
|
adamc@35
|
1057 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1058
|
adam@398
|
1059 (** We include an anonymous [fix] version of [list_nat_tree_ind] that is literally _nested_ inside the definition of the recursive function corresponding to the inductive definition that had the nested use of [list]. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1060
|
adamc@35
|
1061 End nat_tree_ind'.
|
adamc@35
|
1062
|
adamc@35
|
1063 (** We can try our induction principle out by defining some recursive functions on [nat_tree]s and proving a theorem about them. First, we define some helper functions that operate on lists. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1064
|
adamc@35
|
1065 Section map.
|
adamc@35
|
1066 Variables T T' : Set.
|
adam@317
|
1067 Variable F : T -> T'.
|
adamc@35
|
1068
|
adamc@35
|
1069 Fixpoint map (ls : list T) : list T' :=
|
adamc@35
|
1070 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
1071 | Nil => Nil
|
adam@317
|
1072 | Cons h t => Cons (F h) (map t)
|
adamc@35
|
1073 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1074 End map.
|
adamc@35
|
1075
|
adamc@35
|
1076 Fixpoint sum (ls : list nat) : nat :=
|
adamc@35
|
1077 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
1078 | Nil => O
|
adamc@35
|
1079 | Cons h t => plus h (sum t)
|
adamc@35
|
1080 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1081
|
adamc@35
|
1082 (** Now we can define a size function over our trees. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1083
|
adamc@35
|
1084 Fixpoint ntsize (tr : nat_tree) : nat :=
|
adamc@35
|
1085 match tr with
|
adamc@35
|
1086 | NLeaf' => S O
|
adamc@35
|
1087 | NNode' _ trs => S (sum (map ntsize trs))
|
adamc@35
|
1088 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1089
|
adamc@35
|
1090 (** Notice that Coq was smart enough to expand the definition of [map] to verify that we are using proper nested recursion, even through a use of a higher-order function. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1091
|
adamc@208
|
1092 Fixpoint ntsplice (tr1 tr2 : nat_tree) : nat_tree :=
|
adamc@35
|
1093 match tr1 with
|
adamc@35
|
1094 | NLeaf' => NNode' O (Cons tr2 Nil)
|
adamc@35
|
1095 | NNode' n Nil => NNode' n (Cons tr2 Nil)
|
adamc@35
|
1096 | NNode' n (Cons tr trs) => NNode' n (Cons (ntsplice tr tr2) trs)
|
adamc@35
|
1097 end.
|
adamc@35
|
1098
|
adamc@35
|
1099 (** We have defined another arbitrary notion of tree splicing, similar to before, and we can prove an analogous theorem about its relationship with tree size. We start with a useful lemma about addition. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1100
|
adamc@41
|
1101 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@35
|
1102 Lemma plus_S : forall n1 n2 : nat,
|
adamc@35
|
1103 plus n1 (S n2) = S (plus n1 n2).
|
adamc@35
|
1104 induction n1; crush.
|
adamc@35
|
1105 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
1106 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@35
|
1107
|
adamc@35
|
1108 (** Now we begin the proof of the theorem, adding the lemma [plus_S] as a hint. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1109
|
adamc@35
|
1110 Theorem ntsize_ntsplice : forall tr1 tr2 : nat_tree, ntsize (ntsplice tr1 tr2)
|
adamc@35
|
1111 = plus (ntsize tr2) (ntsize tr1).
|
adamc@41
|
1112 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@375
|
1113 Hint Rewrite plus_S.
|
adamc@35
|
1114
|
adam@317
|
1115 (** We know that the standard induction principle is insufficient for the task, so we need to provide a %\index{tactics!using}%[using] clause for the [induction] tactic to specify our alternate principle. *)
|
adamc@208
|
1116
|
adamc@35
|
1117 induction tr1 using nat_tree_ind'; crush.
|
adamc@35
|
1118
|
adamc@35
|
1119 (** One subgoal remains: [[
|
adamc@35
|
1120 n : nat
|
adamc@35
|
1121 ls : list nat_tree
|
adamc@35
|
1122 H : All
|
adamc@35
|
1123 (fun tr1 : nat_tree =>
|
adamc@35
|
1124 forall tr2 : nat_tree,
|
adamc@35
|
1125 ntsize (ntsplice tr1 tr2) = plus (ntsize tr2) (ntsize tr1)) ls
|
adamc@35
|
1126 tr2 : nat_tree
|
adamc@35
|
1127 ============================
|
adamc@35
|
1128 ntsize
|
adamc@35
|
1129 match ls with
|
adamc@35
|
1130 | Nil => NNode' n (Cons tr2 Nil)
|
adamc@35
|
1131 | Cons tr trs => NNode' n (Cons (ntsplice tr tr2) trs)
|
adamc@35
|
1132 end = S (plus (ntsize tr2) (sum (map ntsize ls)))
|
adamc@208
|
1133
|
adamc@35
|
1134 ]]
|
adamc@35
|
1135
|
adamc@35
|
1136 After a few moments of squinting at this goal, it becomes apparent that we need to do a case analysis on the structure of [ls]. The rest is routine. *)
|
adamc@35
|
1137
|
adamc@35
|
1138 destruct ls; crush.
|
adamc@35
|
1139
|
adam@317
|
1140 (** We can go further in automating the proof by exploiting the hint mechanism.%\index{Vernacular commands!Hint Extern}% *)
|
adamc@35
|
1141
|
adamc@35
|
1142 Restart.
|
adam@317
|
1143
|
adamc@35
|
1144 Hint Extern 1 (ntsize (match ?LS with Nil => _ | Cons _ _ => _ end) = _) =>
|
adamc@35
|
1145 destruct LS; crush.
|
adamc@35
|
1146 induction tr1 using nat_tree_ind'; crush.
|
adamc@35
|
1147 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
1148 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@35
|
1149
|
adamc@35
|
1150 (** We will go into great detail on hints in a later chapter, but the only important thing to note here is that we register a pattern that describes a conclusion we expect to encounter during the proof. The pattern may contain unification variables, whose names are prefixed with question marks, and we may refer to those bound variables in a tactic that we ask to have run whenever the pattern matches.
|
adamc@35
|
1151
|
adam@317
|
1152 The advantage of using the hint is not very clear here, because the original proof was so short. However, the hint has fundamentally improved the readability of our proof. Before, the proof referred to the local variable [ls], which has an automatically generated name. To a human reading the proof script without stepping through it interactively, it was not clear where [ls] came from. The hint explains to the reader the process for choosing which variables to case analyze, and the hint can continue working even if the rest of the proof structure changes significantly. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1153
|
adamc@36
|
1154
|
adamc@36
|
1155 (** * Manual Proofs About Constructors *)
|
adamc@36
|
1156
|
adam@317
|
1157 (** It can be useful to understand how tactics like %\index{tactics!discriminate}%[discriminate] and %\index{tactics!injection}%[injection] work, so it is worth stepping through a manual proof of each kind. We will start with a proof fit for [discriminate]. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1158
|
adamc@36
|
1159 Theorem true_neq_false : true <> false.
|
adamc@208
|
1160
|
adamc@41
|
1161 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@420
|
1162 (** We begin with the tactic %\index{tactics!red}%[red], which is short for "one step of reduction," to unfold the definition of logical negation. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1163
|
adamc@36
|
1164 red.
|
adamc@36
|
1165 (** [[
|
adamc@36
|
1166 ============================
|
adamc@36
|
1167 true = false -> False
|
adamc@208
|
1168
|
adamc@36
|
1169 ]]
|
adamc@36
|
1170
|
adam@317
|
1171 The negation is replaced with an implication of falsehood. We use the tactic %\index{tactics!intro}%[intro H] to change the assumption of the implication into a hypothesis named [H]. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1172
|
adamc@36
|
1173 intro H.
|
adamc@36
|
1174 (** [[
|
adamc@36
|
1175 H : true = false
|
adamc@36
|
1176 ============================
|
adamc@36
|
1177 False
|
adamc@208
|
1178
|
adamc@36
|
1179 ]]
|
adamc@36
|
1180
|
adamc@36
|
1181 This is the point in the proof where we apply some creativity. We define a function whose utility will become clear soon. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1182
|
adam@317
|
1183 Definition toProp (b : bool) := if b then True else False.
|
adamc@36
|
1184
|
adam@400
|
1185 (** It is worth recalling the difference between the lowercase and uppercase versions of truth and falsehood: [True] and [False] are logical propositions, while [true] and [false] are boolean values that we can case-analyze. We have defined [toProp] such that our conclusion of [False] is computationally equivalent to [toProp false]. Thus, the %\index{tactics!change}%[change] tactic will let us change the conclusion to [toProp false]. The general form [change e] replaces the conclusion with [e], whenever Coq's built-in computation rules suffice to establish the equivalence of [e] with the original conclusion. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1186
|
adam@317
|
1187 change (toProp false).
|
adamc@36
|
1188 (** [[
|
adamc@36
|
1189 H : true = false
|
adamc@36
|
1190 ============================
|
adam@317
|
1191 toProp false
|
adamc@208
|
1192
|
adamc@36
|
1193 ]]
|
adamc@36
|
1194
|
adam@317
|
1195 Now the righthand side of [H]'s equality appears in the conclusion, so we can rewrite, using the notation [<-] to request to replace the righthand side the equality with the lefthand side.%\index{tactics!rewrite}% *)
|
adamc@36
|
1196
|
adamc@36
|
1197 rewrite <- H.
|
adamc@36
|
1198 (** [[
|
adamc@36
|
1199 H : true = false
|
adamc@36
|
1200 ============================
|
adam@317
|
1201 toProp true
|
adamc@208
|
1202
|
adamc@36
|
1203 ]]
|
adamc@36
|
1204
|
adamc@36
|
1205 We are almost done. Just how close we are to done is revealed by computational simplification. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1206
|
adamc@36
|
1207 simpl.
|
adamc@36
|
1208 (** [[
|
adamc@36
|
1209 H : true = false
|
adamc@36
|
1210 ============================
|
adamc@36
|
1211 True
|
adamc@208
|
1212
|
adam@302
|
1213 ]]
|
adam@302
|
1214 *)
|
adamc@36
|
1215
|
adamc@36
|
1216 trivial.
|
adamc@36
|
1217 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
1218 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@36
|
1219
|
adamc@36
|
1220 (** I have no trivial automated version of this proof to suggest, beyond using [discriminate] or [congruence] in the first place.
|
adamc@36
|
1221
|
adamc@36
|
1222 %\medskip%
|
adamc@36
|
1223
|
adamc@36
|
1224 We can perform a similar manual proof of injectivity of the constructor [S]. I leave a walk-through of the details to curious readers who want to run the proof script interactively. *)
|
adamc@36
|
1225
|
adamc@36
|
1226 Theorem S_inj' : forall n m : nat, S n = S m -> n = m.
|
adamc@41
|
1227 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@36
|
1228 intros n m H.
|
adamc@36
|
1229 change (pred (S n) = pred (S m)).
|
adamc@36
|
1230 rewrite H.
|
adamc@36
|
1231 reflexivity.
|
adamc@36
|
1232 Qed.
|
adamc@41
|
1233 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@36
|
1234
|
adam@400
|
1235 (** The key piece of creativity in this theorem comes in the use of the natural number predecessor function [pred]. Embodied in the implementation of [injection] is a generic recipe for writing such type-specific functions.
|
adam@317
|
1236
|
adam@317
|
1237 The examples in this section illustrate an important aspect of the design philosophy behind Coq. We could certainly design a Gallina replacement that built in rules for constructor discrimination and injectivity, but a simpler alternative is to include a few carefully chosen rules that enable the desired reasoning patterns and many others. A key benefit of this philosophy is that the complexity of proof checking is minimized, which bolsters our confidence that proved theorems are really true. *)
|