adam@534
|
1 (* Copyright (c) 2006, 2011-2012, 2015, Adam Chlipala
|
adam@350
|
2 *
|
adam@350
|
3 * This work is licensed under a
|
adam@350
|
4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
|
adam@350
|
5 * Unported License.
|
adam@350
|
6 * The license text is available at:
|
adam@350
|
7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
|
adam@350
|
8 *)
|
adam@350
|
9
|
adam@350
|
10 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@534
|
11 Require Import Arith List Omega.
|
adam@350
|
12
|
adam@534
|
13 Require Import Cpdt.CpdtTactics Cpdt.Coinductive.
|
adam@350
|
14
|
adam@563
|
15 Require Extraction.
|
adam@563
|
16
|
adam@350
|
17 Set Implicit Arguments.
|
adam@534
|
18 Set Asymmetric Patterns.
|
adam@350
|
19 (* end hide *)
|
adam@350
|
20
|
adam@350
|
21
|
adam@350
|
22 (** %\chapter{General Recursion}% *)
|
adam@350
|
23
|
adam@353
|
24 (** Termination of all programs is a crucial property of Gallina. Non-terminating programs introduce logical inconsistency, where any theorem can be proved with an infinite loop. Coq uses a small set of conservative, syntactic criteria to check termination of all recursive definitions. These criteria are insufficient to support the natural encodings of a variety of important programming idioms. Further, since Coq makes it so convenient to encode mathematics computationally, with functional programs, we may find ourselves wanting to employ more complicated recursion in mathematical definitions.
|
adam@351
|
25
|
adam@424
|
26 What exactly are the conservative criteria that we run up against? For _recursive_ definitions, recursive calls are only allowed on _syntactic subterms_ of the original primary argument, a restriction known as%\index{primitive recursion}% _primitive recursion_. In fact, Coq's handling of reflexive inductive types (those defined in terms of functions returning the same type) gives a bit more flexibility than in traditional primitive recursion, but the term is still applied commonly. In Chapter 5, we saw how _co-recursive_ definitions are checked against a syntactic guardedness condition that guarantees productivity.
|
adam@351
|
27
|
adam@353
|
28 Many natural recursion patterns satisfy neither condition. For instance, there is our simple running example in this chapter, merge sort. We will study three different approaches to more flexible recursion, and the latter two of the approaches will even support definitions that may fail to terminate on certain inputs, without any up-front characterization of which inputs those may be.
|
adam@351
|
29
|
adam@404
|
30 Before proceeding, it is important to note that the problem here is not as fundamental as it may appear. The final example of Chapter 5 demonstrated what is called a%\index{deep embedding}% _deep embedding_ of the syntax and semantics of a programming language. That is, we gave a mathematical definition of a language of programs and their meanings. This language clearly admitted non-termination, and we could think of writing all our sophisticated recursive functions with such explicit syntax types. However, in doing so, we forfeit our chance to take advantage of Coq's very good built-in support for reasoning about Gallina programs. We would rather use a%\index{shallow embedding}% _shallow embedding_, where we model informal constructs by encoding them as normal Gallina programs. Each of the three techniques of this chapter follows that style. *)
|
adam@351
|
31
|
adam@351
|
32
|
adam@351
|
33 (** * Well-Founded Recursion *)
|
adam@351
|
34
|
adam@404
|
35 (** The essence of terminating recursion is that there are no infinite chains of nested recursive calls. This intuition is commonly mapped to the mathematical idea of a%\index{well-founded relation}% _well-founded relation_, and the associated standard technique in Coq is%\index{well-founded recursion}% _well-founded recursion_. The syntactic-subterm relation that Coq applies by default is well-founded, but many cases demand alternate well-founded relations. To demonstrate, let us see where we get stuck on attempting a standard merge sort implementation. *)
|
adam@351
|
36
|
adam@351
|
37 Section mergeSort.
|
adam@351
|
38 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@351
|
39 Variable le : A -> A -> bool.
|
adam@475
|
40
|
adam@424
|
41 (** We have a set equipped with some "less-than-or-equal-to" test. *)
|
adam@351
|
42
|
adam@351
|
43 (** A standard function inserts an element into a sorted list, preserving sortedness. *)
|
adam@351
|
44
|
adam@351
|
45 Fixpoint insert (x : A) (ls : list A) : list A :=
|
adam@351
|
46 match ls with
|
adam@351
|
47 | nil => x :: nil
|
adam@351
|
48 | h :: ls' =>
|
adam@351
|
49 if le x h
|
adam@351
|
50 then x :: ls
|
adam@351
|
51 else h :: insert x ls'
|
adam@351
|
52 end.
|
adam@351
|
53
|
adam@351
|
54 (** We will also need a function to merge two sorted lists. (We use a less efficient implementation than usual, because the more efficient implementation already forces us to think about well-founded recursion, while here we are only interested in setting up the example of merge sort.) *)
|
adam@351
|
55
|
adam@351
|
56 Fixpoint merge (ls1 ls2 : list A) : list A :=
|
adam@351
|
57 match ls1 with
|
adam@351
|
58 | nil => ls2
|
adam@351
|
59 | h :: ls' => insert h (merge ls' ls2)
|
adam@351
|
60 end.
|
adam@351
|
61
|
adam@480
|
62 (** The last helper function for classic merge sort is the one that follows, to split a list arbitrarily into two pieces of approximately equal length. *)
|
adam@351
|
63
|
adam@480
|
64 Fixpoint split (ls : list A) : list A * list A :=
|
adam@351
|
65 match ls with
|
adam@351
|
66 | nil => (nil, nil)
|
adam@351
|
67 | h :: nil => (h :: nil, nil)
|
adam@351
|
68 | h1 :: h2 :: ls' =>
|
adam@480
|
69 let (ls1, ls2) := split ls' in
|
adam@351
|
70 (h1 :: ls1, h2 :: ls2)
|
adam@351
|
71 end.
|
adam@351
|
72
|
adam@424
|
73 (** Now, let us try to write the final sorting function, using a natural number "[<=]" test [leb] from the standard library.
|
adam@351
|
74 [[
|
adam@351
|
75 Fixpoint mergeSort (ls : list A) : list A :=
|
adam@453
|
76 if leb (length ls) 1
|
adam@351
|
77 then ls
|
adam@480
|
78 else let lss := split ls in
|
adam@351
|
79 merge (mergeSort (fst lss)) (mergeSort (snd lss)).
|
adam@351
|
80 ]]
|
adam@351
|
81
|
adam@351
|
82 <<
|
adam@351
|
83 Recursive call to mergeSort has principal argument equal to
|
adam@480
|
84 "fst (split ls)" instead of a subterm of "ls".
|
adam@351
|
85 >>
|
adam@351
|
86
|
adam@351
|
87 The definition is rejected for not following the simple primitive recursion criterion. In particular, it is not apparent that recursive calls to [mergeSort] are syntactic subterms of the original argument [ls]; indeed, they are not, yet we know this is a well-founded recursive definition.
|
adam@351
|
88
|
adam@351
|
89 To produce an acceptable definition, we need to choose a well-founded relation and prove that [mergeSort] respects it. A good starting point is an examination of how well-foundedness is formalized in the Coq standard library. *)
|
adam@351
|
90
|
adam@351
|
91 Print well_founded.
|
adam@351
|
92 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adam@351
|
93 well_founded =
|
adam@351
|
94 fun (A : Type) (R : A -> A -> Prop) => forall a : A, Acc R a
|
adam@351
|
95 ]]
|
adam@351
|
96
|
adam@404
|
97 The bulk of the definitional work devolves to the%\index{accessibility relation}\index{Gallina terms!Acc}% _accessibility_ relation [Acc], whose definition we may also examine. *)
|
adam@351
|
98
|
adam@424
|
99 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@437
|
100 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@424
|
101 Definition Acc_intro' := Acc_intro.
|
adam@437
|
102 (* end thide *)
|
adam@424
|
103 (* end hide *)
|
adam@424
|
104
|
adam@351
|
105 Print Acc.
|
adam@351
|
106 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adam@351
|
107 Inductive Acc (A : Type) (R : A -> A -> Prop) (x : A) : Prop :=
|
adam@351
|
108 Acc_intro : (forall y : A, R y x -> Acc R y) -> Acc R x
|
adam@351
|
109 ]]
|
adam@351
|
110
|
adam@424
|
111 In prose, an element [x] is accessible for a relation [R] if every element "less than" [x] according to [R] is also accessible. Since [Acc] is defined inductively, we know that any accessibility proof involves a finite chain of invocations, in a certain sense that we can make formal. Building on Chapter 5's examples, let us define a co-inductive relation that is closer to the usual informal notion of "absence of infinite decreasing chains." *)
|
adam@351
|
112
|
adam@474
|
113 CoInductive infiniteDecreasingChain A (R : A -> A -> Prop) : stream A -> Prop :=
|
adam@474
|
114 | ChainCons : forall x y s, infiniteDecreasingChain R (Cons y s)
|
adam@351
|
115 -> R y x
|
adam@474
|
116 -> infiniteDecreasingChain R (Cons x (Cons y s)).
|
adam@351
|
117
|
adam@351
|
118 (** We can now prove that any accessible element cannot be the beginning of any infinite decreasing chain. *)
|
adam@351
|
119
|
adam@351
|
120 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@474
|
121 Lemma noBadChains' : forall A (R : A -> A -> Prop) x, Acc R x
|
adam@474
|
122 -> forall s, ~infiniteDecreasingChain R (Cons x s).
|
adam@351
|
123 induction 1; crush;
|
adam@351
|
124 match goal with
|
adam@474
|
125 | [ H : infiniteDecreasingChain _ _ |- _ ] => inversion H; eauto
|
adam@351
|
126 end.
|
adam@351
|
127 Qed.
|
adam@351
|
128
|
adam@351
|
129 (** From here, the absence of infinite decreasing chains in well-founded sets is immediate. *)
|
adam@351
|
130
|
adam@474
|
131 Theorem noBadChains : forall A (R : A -> A -> Prop), well_founded R
|
adam@474
|
132 -> forall s, ~infiniteDecreasingChain R s.
|
adam@474
|
133 destruct s; apply noBadChains'; auto.
|
adam@351
|
134 Qed.
|
adam@351
|
135 (* end thide *)
|
adam@351
|
136
|
adam@351
|
137 (** Absence of infinite decreasing chains implies absence of infinitely nested recursive calls, for any recursive definition that respects the well-founded relation. The [Fix] combinator from the standard library formalizes that intuition: *)
|
adam@351
|
138
|
adam@351
|
139 Check Fix.
|
adam@351
|
140 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@351
|
141 Fix
|
adam@351
|
142 : forall (A : Type) (R : A -> A -> Prop),
|
adam@351
|
143 well_founded R ->
|
adam@351
|
144 forall P : A -> Type,
|
adam@351
|
145 (forall x : A, (forall y : A, R y x -> P y) -> P x) ->
|
adam@351
|
146 forall x : A, P x
|
adam@351
|
147 ]]
|
adam@351
|
148
|
adam@351
|
149 A call to %\index{Gallina terms!Fix}%[Fix] must present a relation [R] and a proof of its well-foundedness. The next argument, [P], is the possibly dependent range type of the function we build; the domain [A] of [R] is the function's domain. The following argument has this type:
|
adam@351
|
150 [[
|
adam@351
|
151 forall x : A, (forall y : A, R y x -> P y) -> P x
|
adam@351
|
152 ]]
|
adam@351
|
153
|
adam@424
|
154 This is an encoding of the function body. The input [x] stands for the function argument, and the next input stands for the function we are defining. Recursive calls are encoded as calls to the second argument, whose type tells us it expects a value [y] and a proof that [y] is "less than" [x], according to [R]. In this way, we enforce the well-foundedness restriction on recursive calls.
|
adam@351
|
155
|
adam@353
|
156 The rest of [Fix]'s type tells us that it returns a function of exactly the type we expect, so we are now ready to use it to implement [mergeSort]. Careful readers may have noticed that [Fix] has a dependent type of the sort we met in the previous chapter.
|
adam@351
|
157
|
adam@351
|
158 Before writing [mergeSort], we need to settle on a well-founded relation. The right one for this example is based on lengths of lists. *)
|
adam@351
|
159
|
adam@351
|
160 Definition lengthOrder (ls1 ls2 : list A) :=
|
adam@351
|
161 length ls1 < length ls2.
|
adam@351
|
162
|
adam@353
|
163 (** We must prove that the relation is truly well-founded. To save some space in the rest of this chapter, we skip right to nice, automated proof scripts, though we postpone introducing the principles behind such scripts to Part III of the book. Curious readers may still replace semicolons with periods and newlines to step through these scripts interactively. *)
|
adam@351
|
164
|
adam@351
|
165 Hint Constructors Acc.
|
adam@351
|
166
|
adam@351
|
167 Lemma lengthOrder_wf' : forall len, forall ls, length ls <= len -> Acc lengthOrder ls.
|
adam@351
|
168 unfold lengthOrder; induction len; crush.
|
adam@351
|
169 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
170
|
adam@351
|
171 Theorem lengthOrder_wf : well_founded lengthOrder.
|
adam@351
|
172 red; intro; eapply lengthOrder_wf'; eauto.
|
adam@351
|
173 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
174
|
adam@514
|
175 (** Notice that we end these proofs with %\index{Vernacular commands!Defined}%[Defined], not [Qed]. Recall that [Defined] marks the theorems as %\emph{%#<i>#transparent#</i>#%}%, so that the details of their proofs may be used during program execution. Why could such details possibly matter for computation? It turns out that [Fix] satisfies the primitive recursion restriction by declaring itself as _recursive in the structure of [Acc] proofs_. This is possible because [Acc] proofs follow a predictable inductive structure. We must do work, as in the last theorem's proof, to establish that all elements of a type belong to [Acc], but the automatic unwinding of those proofs during recursion is straightforward. If we ended the proof with [Qed], the proof details would be hidden from computation, in which case the unwinding process would get stuck.
|
adam@351
|
176
|
adam@480
|
177 To justify our two recursive [mergeSort] calls, we will also need to prove that [split] respects the [lengthOrder] relation. These proofs, too, must be kept transparent, to avoid stuckness of [Fix] evaluation. We use the syntax [@foo] to reference identifier [foo] with its implicit argument behavior turned off. (The proof details below use Ltac features not introduced yet, and they are safe to skip for now.) *)
|
adam@351
|
178
|
adam@480
|
179 Lemma split_wf : forall len ls, 2 <= length ls <= len
|
adam@480
|
180 -> let (ls1, ls2) := split ls in
|
adam@351
|
181 lengthOrder ls1 ls /\ lengthOrder ls2 ls.
|
adam@351
|
182 unfold lengthOrder; induction len; crush; do 2 (destruct ls; crush);
|
adam@351
|
183 destruct (le_lt_dec 2 (length ls));
|
adam@351
|
184 repeat (match goal with
|
adam@351
|
185 | [ _ : length ?E < 2 |- _ ] => destruct E
|
adam@351
|
186 | [ _ : S (length ?E) < 2 |- _ ] => destruct E
|
adam@480
|
187 | [ IH : _ |- context[split ?L] ] =>
|
adam@480
|
188 specialize (IH L); destruct (split L); destruct IH
|
adam@351
|
189 end; crush).
|
adam@351
|
190 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
191
|
adam@480
|
192 Ltac split_wf := intros ls ?; intros; generalize (@split_wf (length ls) ls);
|
adam@480
|
193 destruct (split ls); destruct 1; crush.
|
adam@351
|
194
|
adam@480
|
195 Lemma split_wf1 : forall ls, 2 <= length ls
|
adam@480
|
196 -> lengthOrder (fst (split ls)) ls.
|
adam@480
|
197 split_wf.
|
adam@351
|
198 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
199
|
adam@480
|
200 Lemma split_wf2 : forall ls, 2 <= length ls
|
adam@480
|
201 -> lengthOrder (snd (split ls)) ls.
|
adam@480
|
202 split_wf.
|
adam@351
|
203 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
204
|
adam@480
|
205 Hint Resolve split_wf1 split_wf2.
|
adam@351
|
206
|
adam@453
|
207 (** To write the function definition itself, we use the %\index{tactics!refine}%[refine] tactic as a convenient way to write a program that needs to manipulate proofs, without writing out those proofs manually. We also use a replacement [le_lt_dec] for [leb] that has a more interesting dependent type. (Note that we would not be able to complete the definition without this change, since [refine] will generate subgoals for the [if] branches based only on the _type_ of the test expression, not its _value_.) *)
|
adam@351
|
208
|
adam@351
|
209 Definition mergeSort : list A -> list A.
|
adam@351
|
210 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@351
|
211 refine (Fix lengthOrder_wf (fun _ => list A)
|
adam@351
|
212 (fun (ls : list A)
|
adam@351
|
213 (mergeSort : forall ls' : list A, lengthOrder ls' ls -> list A) =>
|
adam@351
|
214 if le_lt_dec 2 (length ls)
|
adam@480
|
215 then let lss := split ls in
|
adam@351
|
216 merge (mergeSort (fst lss) _) (mergeSort (snd lss) _)
|
adam@351
|
217 else ls)); subst lss; eauto.
|
adam@351
|
218 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
219 (* end thide *)
|
adam@351
|
220 End mergeSort.
|
adam@351
|
221
|
adam@351
|
222 (** The important thing is that it is now easy to evaluate calls to [mergeSort]. *)
|
adam@351
|
223
|
adam@351
|
224 Eval compute in mergeSort leb (1 :: 2 :: 36 :: 8 :: 19 :: nil).
|
adam@351
|
225 (** [= 1 :: 2 :: 8 :: 19 :: 36 :: nil] *)
|
adam@351
|
226
|
adam@441
|
227 (** %\smallskip{}%Since the subject of this chapter is merely how to define functions with unusual recursion structure, we will not prove any further correctness theorems about [mergeSort]. Instead, we stop at proving that [mergeSort] has the expected computational behavior, for all inputs, not merely the one we just tested. *)
|
adam@351
|
228
|
adam@351
|
229 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@351
|
230 Theorem mergeSort_eq : forall A (le : A -> A -> bool) ls,
|
adam@351
|
231 mergeSort le ls = if le_lt_dec 2 (length ls)
|
adam@480
|
232 then let lss := split ls in
|
adam@351
|
233 merge le (mergeSort le (fst lss)) (mergeSort le (snd lss))
|
adam@351
|
234 else ls.
|
adam@351
|
235 intros; apply (Fix_eq (@lengthOrder_wf A) (fun _ => list A)); intros.
|
adam@351
|
236
|
adam@424
|
237 (** The library theorem [Fix_eq] imposes one more strange subgoal upon us. We must prove that the function body is unable to distinguish between "self" arguments that map equal inputs to equal outputs. One might think this should be true of any Gallina code, but in fact this general%\index{extensionality}% _function extensionality_ property is neither provable nor disprovable within Coq. The type of [Fix_eq] makes clear what we must show manually: *)
|
adam@351
|
238
|
adam@351
|
239 Check Fix_eq.
|
adam@351
|
240 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@351
|
241 Fix_eq
|
adam@351
|
242 : forall (A : Type) (R : A -> A -> Prop) (Rwf : well_founded R)
|
adam@351
|
243 (P : A -> Type)
|
adam@351
|
244 (F : forall x : A, (forall y : A, R y x -> P y) -> P x),
|
adam@351
|
245 (forall (x : A) (f g : forall y : A, R y x -> P y),
|
adam@351
|
246 (forall (y : A) (p : R y x), f y p = g y p) -> F x f = F x g) ->
|
adam@351
|
247 forall x : A,
|
adam@351
|
248 Fix Rwf P F x = F x (fun (y : A) (_ : R y x) => Fix Rwf P F y)
|
adam@351
|
249 ]]
|
adam@351
|
250
|
adam@465
|
251 Most such obligations are dischargeable with straightforward proof automation, and this example is no exception. *)
|
adam@351
|
252
|
adam@351
|
253 match goal with
|
adam@351
|
254 | [ |- context[match ?E with left _ => _ | right _ => _ end] ] => destruct E
|
adam@351
|
255 end; simpl; f_equal; auto.
|
adam@351
|
256 Qed.
|
adam@351
|
257 (* end thide *)
|
adam@351
|
258
|
adam@351
|
259 (** As a final test of our definition's suitability, we can extract to OCaml. *)
|
adam@351
|
260
|
adam@351
|
261 Extraction mergeSort.
|
adam@351
|
262
|
adam@351
|
263 (** <<
|
adam@351
|
264 let rec mergeSort le x =
|
adam@351
|
265 match le_lt_dec (S (S O)) (length x) with
|
adam@351
|
266 | Left ->
|
adam@480
|
267 let lss = split x in
|
adam@351
|
268 merge le (mergeSort le (fst lss)) (mergeSort le (snd lss))
|
adam@351
|
269 | Right -> x
|
adam@351
|
270 >>
|
adam@351
|
271
|
adam@353
|
272 We see almost precisely the same definition we would have written manually in OCaml! It might be a good exercise for the reader to use the commands we saw in the previous chapter to clean up some remaining differences from idiomatic OCaml.
|
adam@351
|
273
|
adam@351
|
274 One more piece of the full picture is missing. To go on and prove correctness of [mergeSort], we would need more than a way of unfolding its definition. We also need an appropriate induction principle matched to the well-founded relation. Such a principle is available in the standard library, though we will say no more about its details here. *)
|
adam@351
|
275
|
adam@351
|
276 Check well_founded_induction.
|
adam@351
|
277 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@351
|
278 well_founded_induction
|
adam@351
|
279 : forall (A : Type) (R : A -> A -> Prop),
|
adam@351
|
280 well_founded R ->
|
adam@351
|
281 forall P : A -> Set,
|
adam@351
|
282 (forall x : A, (forall y : A, R y x -> P y) -> P x) ->
|
adam@351
|
283 forall a : A, P a
|
adam@351
|
284 ]]
|
adam@351
|
285
|
adam@351
|
286 Some more recent Coq features provide more convenient syntax for defining recursive functions. Interested readers can consult the Coq manual about the commands %\index{Function}%[Function] and %\index{Program Fixpoint}%[Program Fixpoint]. *)
|
adam@352
|
287
|
adam@352
|
288
|
adam@354
|
289 (** * A Non-Termination Monad Inspired by Domain Theory *)
|
adam@352
|
290
|
adam@424
|
291 (** The key insights of %\index{domain theory}%domain theory%~\cite{WinskelDomains}% inspire the next approach to modeling non-termination. Domain theory is based on _information orders_ that relate values representing computation results, according to how much information these values convey. For instance, a simple domain might include values "the program does not terminate" and "the program terminates with the answer 5." The former is considered to be an _approximation_ of the latter, while the latter is _not_ an approximation of "the program terminates with the answer 6." The details of domain theory will not be important in what follows; we merely borrow the notion of an approximation ordering on computation results.
|
adam@355
|
292
|
adam@355
|
293 Consider this definition of a type of computations. *)
|
adam@355
|
294
|
adam@352
|
295 Section computation.
|
adam@352
|
296 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@355
|
297 (** The type [A] describes the result a computation will yield, if it terminates.
|
adam@355
|
298
|
adam@355
|
299 We give a rich dependent type to computations themselves: *)
|
adam@352
|
300
|
adam@352
|
301 Definition computation :=
|
adam@352
|
302 {f : nat -> option A
|
adam@352
|
303 | forall (n : nat) (v : A),
|
adam@352
|
304 f n = Some v
|
adam@352
|
305 -> forall (n' : nat), n' >= n
|
adam@352
|
306 -> f n' = Some v}.
|
adam@352
|
307
|
adam@474
|
308 (** A computation is fundamentally a function [f] from an _approximation level_ [n] to an optional result. Intuitively, higher [n] values enable termination in more cases than lower values. A call to [f] may return [None] to indicate that [n] was not high enough to run the computation to completion; higher [n] values may yield [Some]. Further, the proof obligation within the subset type asserts that [f] is _monotone_ in an appropriate sense: when some [n] is sufficient to produce termination, so are all higher [n] values, and they all yield the same program result [v].
|
adam@355
|
309
|
adam@355
|
310 It is easy to define a relation characterizing when a computation runs to a particular result at a particular approximation level. *)
|
adam@355
|
311
|
adam@352
|
312 Definition runTo (m : computation) (n : nat) (v : A) :=
|
adam@352
|
313 proj1_sig m n = Some v.
|
adam@352
|
314
|
adam@355
|
315 (** On top of [runTo], we also define [run], which is the most abstract notion of when a computation runs to a value. *)
|
adam@355
|
316
|
adam@352
|
317 Definition run (m : computation) (v : A) :=
|
adam@352
|
318 exists n, runTo m n v.
|
adam@352
|
319 End computation.
|
adam@352
|
320
|
adam@355
|
321 (** The book source code contains at this point some tactics, lemma proofs, and hint commands, to be used in proving facts about computations. Since their details are orthogonal to the message of this chapter, I have omitted them in the rendered version. *)
|
adam@355
|
322 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@355
|
323
|
adam@352
|
324 Hint Unfold runTo.
|
adam@352
|
325
|
adam@352
|
326 Ltac run' := unfold run, runTo in *; try red; crush;
|
adam@352
|
327 repeat (match goal with
|
adam@352
|
328 | [ _ : proj1_sig ?E _ = _ |- _ ] =>
|
adam@352
|
329 match goal with
|
adam@352
|
330 | [ x : _ |- _ ] =>
|
adam@352
|
331 match x with
|
adam@352
|
332 | E => destruct E
|
adam@352
|
333 end
|
adam@352
|
334 end
|
adam@352
|
335 | [ |- context[match ?M with exist _ _ => _ end] ] => let Heq := fresh "Heq" in
|
adam@352
|
336 case_eq M; intros ? ? Heq; try rewrite Heq in *; try subst
|
adam@352
|
337 | [ _ : context[match ?M with exist _ _ => _ end] |- _ ] => let Heq := fresh "Heq" in
|
adam@352
|
338 case_eq M; intros ? ? Heq; try rewrite Heq in *; subst
|
adam@352
|
339 | [ H : forall n v, ?E n = Some v -> _,
|
adam@352
|
340 _ : context[match ?E ?N with Some _ => _ | None => _ end] |- _ ] =>
|
adam@426
|
341 specialize (H N); destruct (E N); try rewrite (H _ (eq_refl _)) by auto; try discriminate
|
adam@352
|
342 | [ H : forall n v, ?E n = Some v -> _, H' : ?E _ = Some _ |- _ ] => rewrite (H _ _ H') by auto
|
adam@352
|
343 end; simpl in *); eauto 7.
|
adam@352
|
344
|
adam@352
|
345 Ltac run := run'; repeat (match goal with
|
adam@352
|
346 | [ H : forall n v, ?E n = Some v -> _
|
adam@352
|
347 |- context[match ?E ?N with Some _ => _ | None => _ end] ] =>
|
adam@426
|
348 specialize (H N); destruct (E N); try rewrite (H _ (eq_refl _)) by auto; try discriminate
|
adam@352
|
349 end; run').
|
adam@352
|
350
|
adam@352
|
351 Lemma ex_irrelevant : forall P : Prop, P -> exists n : nat, P.
|
adam@352
|
352 exists 0; auto.
|
adam@352
|
353 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
354
|
adam@352
|
355 Hint Resolve ex_irrelevant.
|
adam@352
|
356
|
adam@352
|
357 Require Import Max.
|
adam@352
|
358
|
adam@380
|
359 Theorem max_spec_le : forall n m, n <= m /\ max n m = m \/ m <= n /\ max n m = n.
|
adam@380
|
360 induction n; destruct m; simpl; intuition;
|
adam@380
|
361 specialize (IHn m); intuition.
|
adam@380
|
362 Qed.
|
adam@380
|
363
|
adam@352
|
364 Ltac max := intros n m; generalize (max_spec_le n m); crush.
|
adam@352
|
365
|
adam@352
|
366 Lemma max_1 : forall n m, max n m >= n.
|
adam@352
|
367 max.
|
adam@352
|
368 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
369
|
adam@352
|
370 Lemma max_2 : forall n m, max n m >= m.
|
adam@352
|
371 max.
|
adam@352
|
372 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
373
|
adam@352
|
374 Hint Resolve max_1 max_2.
|
adam@352
|
375
|
adam@352
|
376 Lemma ge_refl : forall n, n >= n.
|
adam@352
|
377 crush.
|
adam@352
|
378 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
379
|
adam@352
|
380 Hint Resolve ge_refl.
|
adam@352
|
381
|
adam@352
|
382 Hint Extern 1 => match goal with
|
adam@352
|
383 | [ H : _ = exist _ _ _ |- _ ] => rewrite H
|
adam@352
|
384 end.
|
adam@355
|
385 (* end hide *)
|
adam@355
|
386 (** remove printing exists *)
|
adam@355
|
387
|
adam@480
|
388 (** Now, as a simple first example of a computation, we can define [Bottom], which corresponds to an infinite loop. For any approximation level, it fails to terminate (returns [None]). Note the use of [abstract] to create a new opaque lemma for the proof found by the #<tt>#%\coqdocvar{%run%}%#</tt># tactic. In contrast to the previous section, opaque proofs are fine here, since the proof components of computations do not influence evaluation behavior. It is generally preferable to make proofs opaque when possible, as this enforces a kind of modularity in the code to follow, preventing it from depending on any details of the proof. *)
|
adam@352
|
389
|
adam@352
|
390 Section Bottom.
|
adam@352
|
391 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@352
|
392
|
adam@352
|
393 Definition Bottom : computation A.
|
adam@352
|
394 exists (fun _ : nat => @None A); abstract run.
|
adam@352
|
395 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
396
|
adam@352
|
397 Theorem run_Bottom : forall v, ~run Bottom v.
|
adam@352
|
398 run.
|
adam@352
|
399 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
400 End Bottom.
|
adam@352
|
401
|
adam@355
|
402 (** A slightly more complicated example is [Return], which gives the same terminating answer at every approximation level. *)
|
adam@355
|
403
|
adam@352
|
404 Section Return.
|
adam@352
|
405 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@352
|
406 Variable v : A.
|
adam@352
|
407
|
adam@352
|
408 Definition Return : computation A.
|
adam@352
|
409 intros; exists (fun _ : nat => Some v); abstract run.
|
adam@352
|
410 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
411
|
adam@352
|
412 Theorem run_Return : run Return v.
|
adam@352
|
413 run.
|
adam@352
|
414 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
415 End Return.
|
adam@352
|
416
|
adam@474
|
417 (** The name [Return] was meant to be suggestive of the standard operations of %\index{monad}%monads%~\cite{Monads}%. The other standard operation is [Bind], which lets us run one computation and, if it terminates, pass its result off to another computation. We implement bind using the notation [let (x, y) := e1 in e2], for pulling apart the value [e1] which may be thought of as a pair. The second component of a [computation] is a proof, which we do not need to mention directly in the definition of [Bind]. *)
|
adam@352
|
418
|
adam@352
|
419 Section Bind.
|
adam@352
|
420 Variables A B : Type.
|
adam@352
|
421 Variable m1 : computation A.
|
adam@352
|
422 Variable m2 : A -> computation B.
|
adam@352
|
423
|
adam@352
|
424 Definition Bind : computation B.
|
adam@352
|
425 exists (fun n =>
|
adam@357
|
426 let (f1, _) := m1 in
|
adam@352
|
427 match f1 n with
|
adam@352
|
428 | None => None
|
adam@352
|
429 | Some v =>
|
adam@357
|
430 let (f2, _) := m2 v in
|
adam@352
|
431 f2 n
|
adam@352
|
432 end); abstract run.
|
adam@352
|
433 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
434
|
adam@352
|
435 Theorem run_Bind : forall (v1 : A) (v2 : B),
|
adam@352
|
436 run m1 v1
|
adam@352
|
437 -> run (m2 v1) v2
|
adam@352
|
438 -> run Bind v2.
|
adam@352
|
439 run; match goal with
|
adam@352
|
440 | [ x : nat, y : nat |- _ ] => exists (max x y)
|
adam@352
|
441 end; run.
|
adam@352
|
442 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
443 End Bind.
|
adam@352
|
444
|
adam@355
|
445 (** A simple notation lets us write [Bind] calls the way they appear in Haskell. *)
|
adam@352
|
446
|
adam@352
|
447 Notation "x <- m1 ; m2" :=
|
adam@352
|
448 (Bind m1 (fun x => m2)) (right associativity, at level 70).
|
adam@352
|
449
|
adam@424
|
450 (** We can verify that we have indeed defined a monad, by proving the standard monad laws. Part of the exercise is choosing an appropriate notion of equality between computations. We use "equality at all approximation levels." *)
|
adam@355
|
451
|
adam@352
|
452 Definition meq A (m1 m2 : computation A) := forall n, proj1_sig m1 n = proj1_sig m2 n.
|
adam@352
|
453
|
adam@352
|
454 Theorem left_identity : forall A B (a : A) (f : A -> computation B),
|
adam@352
|
455 meq (Bind (Return a) f) (f a).
|
adam@352
|
456 run.
|
adam@352
|
457 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
458
|
adam@352
|
459 Theorem right_identity : forall A (m : computation A),
|
adam@352
|
460 meq (Bind m (@Return _)) m.
|
adam@352
|
461 run.
|
adam@352
|
462 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
463
|
adam@357
|
464 Theorem associativity : forall A B C (m : computation A)
|
adam@357
|
465 (f : A -> computation B) (g : B -> computation C),
|
adam@352
|
466 meq (Bind (Bind m f) g) (Bind m (fun x => Bind (f x) g)).
|
adam@352
|
467 run.
|
adam@352
|
468 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
469
|
adam@398
|
470 (** Now we come to the piece most directly inspired by domain theory. We want to support general recursive function definitions, but domain theory tells us that not all definitions are reasonable; some fail to be _continuous_ and thus represent unrealizable computations. To formalize an analogous notion of continuity for our non-termination monad, we write down the approximation relation on computation results that we have had in mind all along. *)
|
adam@352
|
471
|
adam@352
|
472 Section lattice.
|
adam@352
|
473 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@352
|
474
|
adam@352
|
475 Definition leq (x y : option A) :=
|
adam@352
|
476 forall v, x = Some v -> y = Some v.
|
adam@352
|
477 End lattice.
|
adam@352
|
478
|
adam@355
|
479 (** We now have the tools we need to define a new [Fix] combinator that, unlike the one we saw in the prior section, does not require a termination proof, and in fact admits recursive definition of functions that fail to terminate on some or all inputs. *)
|
adam@352
|
480
|
adam@352
|
481 Section Fix.
|
adam@475
|
482
|
adam@355
|
483 (** First, we have the function domain and range types. *)
|
adam@355
|
484
|
adam@352
|
485 Variables A B : Type.
|
adam@355
|
486
|
adam@355
|
487 (** Next comes the function body, which is written as though it can be parameterized over itself, for recursive calls. *)
|
adam@355
|
488
|
adam@352
|
489 Variable f : (A -> computation B) -> (A -> computation B).
|
adam@352
|
490
|
adam@355
|
491 (** Finally, we impose an obligation to prove that the body [f] is continuous. That is, when [f] terminates according to one recursive version of itself, it also terminates with the same result at the same approximation level when passed a recursive version that refines the original, according to [leq]. *)
|
adam@355
|
492
|
adam@352
|
493 Hypothesis f_continuous : forall n v v1 x,
|
adam@352
|
494 runTo (f v1 x) n v
|
adam@352
|
495 -> forall (v2 : A -> computation B),
|
adam@352
|
496 (forall x, leq (proj1_sig (v1 x) n) (proj1_sig (v2 x) n))
|
adam@352
|
497 -> runTo (f v2 x) n v.
|
adam@352
|
498
|
adam@355
|
499 (** The computational part of the [Fix] combinator is easy to define. At approximation level 0, we diverge; at higher levels, we run the body with a functional argument drawn from the next lower level. *)
|
adam@355
|
500
|
adam@352
|
501 Fixpoint Fix' (n : nat) (x : A) : computation B :=
|
adam@352
|
502 match n with
|
adam@352
|
503 | O => Bottom _
|
adam@352
|
504 | S n' => f (Fix' n') x
|
adam@352
|
505 end.
|
adam@352
|
506
|
adam@355
|
507 (** Now it is straightforward to package [Fix'] as a computation combinator [Fix]. *)
|
adam@355
|
508
|
adam@352
|
509 Hint Extern 1 (_ >= _) => omega.
|
adam@352
|
510 Hint Unfold leq.
|
adam@352
|
511
|
adam@352
|
512 Lemma Fix'_ok : forall steps n x v, proj1_sig (Fix' n x) steps = Some v
|
adam@352
|
513 -> forall n', n' >= n
|
adam@352
|
514 -> proj1_sig (Fix' n' x) steps = Some v.
|
adam@352
|
515 unfold runTo in *; induction n; crush;
|
adam@352
|
516 match goal with
|
adam@352
|
517 | [ H : _ >= _ |- _ ] => inversion H; crush; eauto
|
adam@352
|
518 end.
|
adam@352
|
519 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
520
|
adam@352
|
521 Hint Resolve Fix'_ok.
|
adam@352
|
522
|
adam@352
|
523 Hint Extern 1 (proj1_sig _ _ = _) => simpl;
|
adam@352
|
524 match goal with
|
adam@352
|
525 | [ |- proj1_sig ?E _ = _ ] => eapply (proj2_sig E)
|
adam@352
|
526 end.
|
adam@352
|
527
|
adam@352
|
528 Definition Fix : A -> computation B.
|
adam@352
|
529 intro x; exists (fun n => proj1_sig (Fix' n x) n); abstract run.
|
adam@352
|
530 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
531
|
adam@355
|
532 (** Finally, we can prove that [Fix] obeys the expected computation rule. *)
|
adam@352
|
533
|
adam@352
|
534 Theorem run_Fix : forall x v,
|
adam@352
|
535 run (f Fix x) v
|
adam@352
|
536 -> run (Fix x) v.
|
adam@352
|
537 run; match goal with
|
adam@352
|
538 | [ n : nat |- _ ] => exists (S n); eauto
|
adam@352
|
539 end.
|
adam@352
|
540 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
541 End Fix.
|
adam@352
|
542
|
adam@355
|
543 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@352
|
544 Lemma leq_Some : forall A (x y : A), leq (Some x) (Some y)
|
adam@352
|
545 -> x = y.
|
adam@426
|
546 intros ? ? ? H; generalize (H _ (eq_refl _)); crush.
|
adam@352
|
547 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
548
|
adam@352
|
549 Lemma leq_None : forall A (x y : A), leq (Some x) None
|
adam@352
|
550 -> False.
|
adam@426
|
551 intros ? ? ? H; generalize (H _ (eq_refl _)); crush.
|
adam@352
|
552 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
553
|
adam@355
|
554 Ltac mergeSort' := run;
|
adam@355
|
555 repeat (match goal with
|
adam@355
|
556 | [ |- context[match ?E with O => _ | S _ => _ end] ] => destruct E
|
adam@355
|
557 end; run);
|
adam@355
|
558 repeat match goal with
|
adam@355
|
559 | [ H : forall x, leq (proj1_sig (?f x) _) (proj1_sig (?g x) _) |- _ ] =>
|
adam@355
|
560 match goal with
|
adam@355
|
561 | [ H1 : f ?arg = _, H2 : g ?arg = _ |- _ ] =>
|
adam@355
|
562 generalize (H arg); rewrite H1; rewrite H2; clear H1 H2; simpl; intro
|
adam@355
|
563 end
|
adam@355
|
564 end; run; repeat match goal with
|
adam@355
|
565 | [ H : _ |- _ ] => (apply leq_None in H; tauto) || (apply leq_Some in H; subst)
|
adam@355
|
566 end; auto.
|
adam@355
|
567 (* end hide *)
|
adam@355
|
568
|
adam@355
|
569 (** After all that work, it is now fairly painless to define a version of [mergeSort] that requires no proof of termination. We appeal to a program-specific tactic whose definition is hidden here but present in the book source. *)
|
adam@355
|
570
|
adam@352
|
571 Definition mergeSort' : forall A, (A -> A -> bool) -> list A -> computation (list A).
|
adam@352
|
572 refine (fun A le => Fix
|
adam@352
|
573 (fun (mergeSort : list A -> computation (list A))
|
adam@352
|
574 (ls : list A) =>
|
adam@352
|
575 if le_lt_dec 2 (length ls)
|
adam@480
|
576 then let lss := split ls in
|
adam@352
|
577 ls1 <- mergeSort (fst lss);
|
adam@352
|
578 ls2 <- mergeSort (snd lss);
|
adam@352
|
579 Return (merge le ls1 ls2)
|
adam@355
|
580 else Return ls) _); abstract mergeSort'.
|
adam@352
|
581 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
582
|
adam@424
|
583 (** Furthermore, "running" [mergeSort'] on concrete inputs is as easy as choosing a sufficiently high approximation level and letting Coq's computation rules do the rest. Contrast this with the proof work that goes into deriving an evaluation fact for a deeply embedded language, with one explicit proof rule application per execution step. *)
|
adam@352
|
584
|
adam@352
|
585 Lemma test_mergeSort' : run (mergeSort' leb (1 :: 2 :: 36 :: 8 :: 19 :: nil))
|
adam@352
|
586 (1 :: 2 :: 8 :: 19 :: 36 :: nil).
|
adam@352
|
587 exists 4; reflexivity.
|
adam@352
|
588 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
589
|
adam@453
|
590 (** There is another benefit of our new [Fix] compared with the one we used in the previous section: we can now write recursive functions that sometimes fail to terminate, without losing easy reasoning principles for the terminating cases. Consider this simple example, which appeals to another tactic whose definition we elide here. *)
|
adam@355
|
591
|
adam@355
|
592 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@355
|
593 Ltac looper := unfold leq in *; run;
|
adam@355
|
594 repeat match goal with
|
adam@355
|
595 | [ x : unit |- _ ] => destruct x
|
adam@355
|
596 | [ x : bool |- _ ] => destruct x
|
adam@355
|
597 end; auto.
|
adam@355
|
598 (* end hide *)
|
adam@355
|
599
|
adam@352
|
600 Definition looper : bool -> computation unit.
|
adam@352
|
601 refine (Fix (fun looper (b : bool) =>
|
adam@355
|
602 if b then Return tt else looper b) _); abstract looper.
|
adam@352
|
603 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
604
|
adam@352
|
605 Lemma test_looper : run (looper true) tt.
|
adam@352
|
606 exists 1; reflexivity.
|
adam@352
|
607 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
608
|
adam@355
|
609 (** As before, proving outputs for specific inputs is as easy as demonstrating a high enough approximation level.
|
adam@355
|
610
|
adam@480
|
611 There are other theorems that are important to prove about combinators like [Return], [Bind], and [Fix]. In general, for a computation [c], we sometimes have a hypothesis proving [run c v] for some [v], and we want to perform inversion to deduce what [v] must be. Each combinator should ideally have a theorem of that kind, for [c] built directly from that combinator. We have omitted such theorems here, but they are not hard to prove. In general, the domain theory-inspired approach avoids the type-theoretic "gotchas" that tend to show up in approaches that try to mix normal Coq computation with explicit syntax types. The next section of this chapter demonstrates two alternate approaches of that sort. In the final section of the chapter, we review the pros and cons of the different choices, coming to the conclusion that none of them is obviously better than any one of the others for all situations. *)
|
adam@355
|
612
|
adam@354
|
613
|
adam@354
|
614 (** * Co-Inductive Non-Termination Monads *)
|
adam@354
|
615
|
adam@356
|
616 (** There are two key downsides to both of the previous approaches: both require unusual syntax based on explicit calls to fixpoint combinators, and both generate immediate proof obligations about the bodies of recursive definitions. In Chapter 5, we have already seen how co-inductive types support recursive definitions that exhibit certain well-behaved varieties of non-termination. It turns out that we can leverage that co-induction support for encoding of general recursive definitions, by adding layers of co-inductive syntax. In effect, we mix elements of shallow and deep embeddings.
|
adam@356
|
617
|
adam@356
|
618 Our first example of this kind, proposed by Capretta%~\cite{Capretta}%, defines a silly-looking type of thunks; that is, computations that may be forced to yield results, if they terminate. *)
|
adam@356
|
619
|
adam@354
|
620 CoInductive thunk (A : Type) : Type :=
|
adam@354
|
621 | Answer : A -> thunk A
|
adam@354
|
622 | Think : thunk A -> thunk A.
|
adam@354
|
623
|
adam@356
|
624 (** A computation is either an immediate [Answer] or another computation wrapped inside [Think]. Since [thunk] is co-inductive, every [thunk] type is inhabited by an infinite nesting of [Think]s, standing for non-termination. Terminating results are [Answer] wrapped inside some finite number of [Think]s.
|
adam@356
|
625
|
adam@424
|
626 Why bother to write such a strange definition? The definition of [thunk] is motivated by the ability it gives us to define a "bind" operation, similar to the one we defined in the previous section. *)
|
adam@356
|
627
|
adam@356
|
628 CoFixpoint TBind A B (m1 : thunk A) (m2 : A -> thunk B) : thunk B :=
|
adam@354
|
629 match m1 with
|
adam@354
|
630 | Answer x => m2 x
|
adam@354
|
631 | Think m1' => Think (TBind m1' m2)
|
adam@354
|
632 end.
|
adam@354
|
633
|
adam@356
|
634 (** Note that the definition would violate the co-recursion guardedness restriction if we left out the seemingly superfluous [Think] on the righthand side of the second [match] branch.
|
adam@356
|
635
|
adam@356
|
636 We can prove that [Answer] and [TBind] form a monad for [thunk]. The proof is omitted here but present in the book source. As usual for this sort of proof, a key element is choosing an appropriate notion of equality for [thunk]s. *)
|
adam@356
|
637
|
adam@356
|
638 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@354
|
639 CoInductive thunk_eq A : thunk A -> thunk A -> Prop :=
|
adam@354
|
640 | EqAnswer : forall x, thunk_eq (Answer x) (Answer x)
|
adam@354
|
641 | EqThinkL : forall m1 m2, thunk_eq m1 m2 -> thunk_eq (Think m1) m2
|
adam@354
|
642 | EqThinkR : forall m1 m2, thunk_eq m1 m2 -> thunk_eq m1 (Think m2).
|
adam@354
|
643
|
adam@354
|
644 Section thunk_eq_coind.
|
adam@354
|
645 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@354
|
646 Variable P : thunk A -> thunk A -> Prop.
|
adam@354
|
647
|
adam@354
|
648 Hypothesis H : forall m1 m2, P m1 m2
|
adam@354
|
649 -> match m1, m2 with
|
adam@354
|
650 | Answer x1, Answer x2 => x1 = x2
|
adam@354
|
651 | Think m1', Think m2' => P m1' m2'
|
adam@354
|
652 | Think m1', _ => P m1' m2
|
adam@354
|
653 | _, Think m2' => P m1 m2'
|
adam@354
|
654 end.
|
adam@354
|
655
|
adam@354
|
656 Theorem thunk_eq_coind : forall m1 m2, P m1 m2 -> thunk_eq m1 m2.
|
adam@568
|
657 cofix thunk_eq_coind; intros;
|
adam@354
|
658 match goal with
|
adam@354
|
659 | [ H' : P _ _ |- _ ] => specialize (H H'); clear H'
|
adam@354
|
660 end; destruct m1; destruct m2; subst; repeat constructor; auto.
|
adam@354
|
661 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
662 End thunk_eq_coind.
|
adam@356
|
663 (* end hide *)
|
adam@356
|
664
|
adam@356
|
665 (** In the proofs to follow, we will need a function similar to one we saw in Chapter 5, to pull apart and reassemble a [thunk] in a way that provokes reduction of co-recursive calls. *)
|
adam@354
|
666
|
adam@354
|
667 Definition frob A (m : thunk A) : thunk A :=
|
adam@354
|
668 match m with
|
adam@354
|
669 | Answer x => Answer x
|
adam@354
|
670 | Think m' => Think m'
|
adam@354
|
671 end.
|
adam@354
|
672
|
adam@354
|
673 Theorem frob_eq : forall A (m : thunk A), frob m = m.
|
adam@354
|
674 destruct m; reflexivity.
|
adam@354
|
675 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
676
|
adam@356
|
677 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@354
|
678 Theorem thunk_eq_frob : forall A (m1 m2 : thunk A),
|
adam@354
|
679 thunk_eq (frob m1) (frob m2)
|
adam@354
|
680 -> thunk_eq m1 m2.
|
adam@354
|
681 intros; repeat rewrite frob_eq in *; auto.
|
adam@354
|
682 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
683
|
adam@354
|
684 Ltac findDestr := match goal with
|
adam@354
|
685 | [ |- context[match ?E with Answer _ => _ | Think _ => _ end] ] =>
|
adam@354
|
686 match E with
|
adam@354
|
687 | context[match _ with Answer _ => _ | Think _ => _ end] => fail 1
|
adam@354
|
688 | _ => destruct E
|
adam@354
|
689 end
|
adam@354
|
690 end.
|
adam@354
|
691
|
adam@354
|
692 Theorem thunk_eq_refl : forall A (m : thunk A), thunk_eq m m.
|
adam@354
|
693 intros; apply (thunk_eq_coind (fun m1 m2 => m1 = m2)); crush; findDestr; reflexivity.
|
adam@354
|
694 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
695
|
adam@354
|
696 Hint Resolve thunk_eq_refl.
|
adam@354
|
697
|
adam@354
|
698 Theorem tleft_identity : forall A B (a : A) (f : A -> thunk B),
|
adam@354
|
699 thunk_eq (TBind (Answer a) f) (f a).
|
adam@354
|
700 intros; apply thunk_eq_frob; crush.
|
adam@354
|
701 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
702
|
adam@354
|
703 Theorem tright_identity : forall A (m : thunk A),
|
adam@354
|
704 thunk_eq (TBind m (@Answer _)) m.
|
adam@354
|
705 intros; apply (thunk_eq_coind (fun m1 m2 => m1 = TBind m2 (@Answer _))); crush;
|
adam@354
|
706 findDestr; reflexivity.
|
adam@354
|
707 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
708
|
adam@354
|
709 Lemma TBind_Answer : forall (A B : Type) (v : A) (m2 : A -> thunk B),
|
adam@354
|
710 TBind (Answer v) m2 = m2 v.
|
adam@354
|
711 intros; rewrite <- (frob_eq (TBind (Answer v) m2));
|
adam@354
|
712 simpl; findDestr; reflexivity.
|
adam@354
|
713 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
714
|
adam@375
|
715 Hint Rewrite TBind_Answer.
|
adam@354
|
716
|
adam@355
|
717 (** printing exists $\exists$ *)
|
adam@355
|
718
|
adam@354
|
719 Theorem tassociativity : forall A B C (m : thunk A) (f : A -> thunk B) (g : B -> thunk C),
|
adam@354
|
720 thunk_eq (TBind (TBind m f) g) (TBind m (fun x => TBind (f x) g)).
|
adam@354
|
721 intros; apply (thunk_eq_coind (fun m1 m2 => (exists m,
|
adam@354
|
722 m1 = TBind (TBind m f) g
|
adam@354
|
723 /\ m2 = TBind m (fun x => TBind (f x) g))
|
adam@354
|
724 \/ m1 = m2)); crush; eauto; repeat (findDestr; crush; eauto).
|
adam@354
|
725 Qed.
|
adam@356
|
726 (* end hide *)
|
adam@356
|
727
|
adam@356
|
728 (** As a simple example, here is how we might define a tail-recursive factorial function. *)
|
adam@354
|
729
|
adam@354
|
730 CoFixpoint fact (n acc : nat) : thunk nat :=
|
adam@354
|
731 match n with
|
adam@354
|
732 | O => Answer acc
|
adam@354
|
733 | S n' => Think (fact n' (S n' * acc))
|
adam@354
|
734 end.
|
adam@354
|
735
|
adam@356
|
736 (** To test our definition, we need an evaluation relation that characterizes results of evaluating [thunk]s. *)
|
adam@356
|
737
|
adam@354
|
738 Inductive eval A : thunk A -> A -> Prop :=
|
adam@354
|
739 | EvalAnswer : forall x, eval (Answer x) x
|
adam@354
|
740 | EvalThink : forall m x, eval m x -> eval (Think m) x.
|
adam@354
|
741
|
adam@375
|
742 Hint Rewrite frob_eq.
|
adam@354
|
743
|
adam@354
|
744 Lemma eval_frob : forall A (c : thunk A) x,
|
adam@354
|
745 eval (frob c) x
|
adam@354
|
746 -> eval c x.
|
adam@354
|
747 crush.
|
adam@354
|
748 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
749
|
adam@354
|
750 Theorem eval_fact : eval (fact 5 1) 120.
|
adam@354
|
751 repeat (apply eval_frob; simpl; constructor).
|
adam@354
|
752 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
753
|
adam@356
|
754 (** We need to apply constructors of [eval] explicitly, but the process is easy to automate completely for concrete input programs.
|
adam@356
|
755
|
adam@465
|
756 Now consider another very similar definition, this time of a Fibonacci number function. *)
|
adam@357
|
757
|
adam@357
|
758 Notation "x <- m1 ; m2" :=
|
adam@357
|
759 (TBind m1 (fun x => m2)) (right associativity, at level 70).
|
adam@357
|
760
|
adam@404
|
761 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@437
|
762 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@424
|
763 Definition fib := pred.
|
adam@437
|
764 (* end thide *)
|
adam@404
|
765 (* end hide *)
|
adam@404
|
766
|
adam@453
|
767 (** %\vspace{-.3in}%[[
|
adam@354
|
768 CoFixpoint fib (n : nat) : thunk nat :=
|
adam@354
|
769 match n with
|
adam@354
|
770 | 0 => Answer 1
|
adam@354
|
771 | 1 => Answer 1
|
adam@357
|
772 | _ => n1 <- fib (pred n);
|
adam@357
|
773 n2 <- fib (pred (pred n));
|
adam@357
|
774 Answer (n1 + n2)
|
adam@354
|
775 end.
|
adam@354
|
776 ]]
|
adam@354
|
777
|
adam@356
|
778 Coq complains that the guardedness condition is violated. The two recursive calls are immediate arguments to [TBind], but [TBind] is not a constructor of [thunk]. Rather, it is a defined function. This example shows a very serious limitation of [thunk] for traditional functional programming: it is not, in general, possible to make recursive calls and then make further recursive calls, depending on the first call's result. The [fact] example succeeded because it was already tail recursive, meaning no further computation is needed after a recursive call.
|
adam@356
|
779
|
adam@356
|
780 %\medskip%
|
adam@356
|
781
|
adam@424
|
782 I know no easy fix for this problem of [thunk], but we can define an alternate co-inductive monad that avoids the problem, based on a proposal by Megacz%~\cite{Megacz}%. We ran into trouble because [TBind] was not a constructor of [thunk], so let us define a new type family where "bind" is a constructor. *)
|
adam@354
|
783
|
adam@354
|
784 CoInductive comp (A : Type) : Type :=
|
adam@354
|
785 | Ret : A -> comp A
|
adam@354
|
786 | Bnd : forall B, comp B -> (B -> comp A) -> comp A.
|
adam@354
|
787
|
adam@404
|
788 (** This example shows off Coq's support for%\index{recursively non-uniform parameters}% _recursively non-uniform parameters_, as in the case of the parameter [A] declared above, where each constructor's type ends in [comp A], but there is a recursive use of [comp] with a different parameter [B]. Beside that technical wrinkle, we see the simplest possible definition of a monad, via a type whose two constructors are precisely the monad operators.
|
adam@356
|
789
|
adam@356
|
790 It is easy to define the semantics of terminating [comp] computations. *)
|
adam@356
|
791
|
adam@354
|
792 Inductive exec A : comp A -> A -> Prop :=
|
adam@354
|
793 | ExecRet : forall x, exec (Ret x) x
|
adam@354
|
794 | ExecBnd : forall B (c : comp B) (f : B -> comp A) x1 x2, exec (A := B) c x1
|
adam@354
|
795 -> exec (f x1) x2
|
adam@354
|
796 -> exec (Bnd c f) x2.
|
adam@354
|
797
|
adam@356
|
798 (** We can also prove that [Ret] and [Bnd] form a monad according to a notion of [comp] equality based on [exec], but we omit details here; they are in the book source at this point. *)
|
adam@356
|
799
|
adam@356
|
800 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@354
|
801 Hint Constructors exec.
|
adam@354
|
802
|
adam@354
|
803 Definition comp_eq A (c1 c2 : comp A) := forall r, exec c1 r <-> exec c2 r.
|
adam@354
|
804
|
adam@354
|
805 Ltac inverter := repeat match goal with
|
adam@354
|
806 | [ H : exec _ _ |- _ ] => inversion H; []; crush
|
adam@354
|
807 end.
|
adam@354
|
808
|
adam@354
|
809 Theorem cleft_identity : forall A B (a : A) (f : A -> comp B),
|
adam@354
|
810 comp_eq (Bnd (Ret a) f) (f a).
|
adam@354
|
811 red; crush; inverter; eauto.
|
adam@354
|
812 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
813
|
adam@354
|
814 Theorem cright_identity : forall A (m : comp A),
|
adam@354
|
815 comp_eq (Bnd m (@Ret _)) m.
|
adam@354
|
816 red; crush; inverter; eauto.
|
adam@354
|
817 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
818
|
adam@354
|
819 Lemma cassociativity1 : forall A B C (f : A -> comp B) (g : B -> comp C) r c,
|
adam@354
|
820 exec c r
|
adam@354
|
821 -> forall m, c = Bnd (Bnd m f) g
|
adam@354
|
822 -> exec (Bnd m (fun x => Bnd (f x) g)) r.
|
adam@354
|
823 induction 1; crush.
|
adam@354
|
824 match goal with
|
adam@354
|
825 | [ H : Bnd _ _ = Bnd _ _ |- _ ] => injection H; clear H; intros; try subst
|
adam@354
|
826 end.
|
adam@549
|
827 try subst B. (* This line expected to fail in Coq 8.4 and succeed in Coq 8.6. *)
|
adam@354
|
828 crush.
|
adam@354
|
829 inversion H; clear H; crush.
|
adam@354
|
830 eauto.
|
adam@354
|
831 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
832
|
adam@354
|
833 Lemma cassociativity2 : forall A B C (f : A -> comp B) (g : B -> comp C) r c,
|
adam@354
|
834 exec c r
|
adam@354
|
835 -> forall m, c = Bnd m (fun x => Bnd (f x) g)
|
adam@354
|
836 -> exec (Bnd (Bnd m f) g) r.
|
adam@354
|
837 induction 1; crush.
|
adam@354
|
838 match goal with
|
adam@354
|
839 | [ H : Bnd _ _ = Bnd _ _ |- _ ] => injection H; clear H; intros; try subst
|
adam@354
|
840 end.
|
adam@549
|
841 try subst A. (* Same as above *)
|
adam@354
|
842 crush.
|
adam@354
|
843 inversion H0; clear H0; crush.
|
adam@354
|
844 eauto.
|
adam@354
|
845 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
846
|
adam@354
|
847 Hint Resolve cassociativity1 cassociativity2.
|
adam@354
|
848
|
adam@354
|
849 Theorem cassociativity : forall A B C (m : comp A) (f : A -> comp B) (g : B -> comp C),
|
adam@354
|
850 comp_eq (Bnd (Bnd m f) g) (Bnd m (fun x => Bnd (f x) g)).
|
adam@354
|
851 red; crush; eauto.
|
adam@354
|
852 Qed.
|
adam@356
|
853 (* end hide *)
|
adam@356
|
854
|
adam@469
|
855 (** Not only can we define the Fibonacci function with the new monad, but even our running example of merge sort becomes definable. By shadowing our previous notation for "bind," we can write almost exactly the same code as in our previous [mergeSort'] definition, but with less syntactic clutter. *)
|
adam@356
|
856
|
adam@356
|
857 Notation "x <- m1 ; m2" := (Bnd m1 (fun x => m2)).
|
adam@354
|
858
|
adam@354
|
859 CoFixpoint mergeSort'' A (le : A -> A -> bool) (ls : list A) : comp (list A) :=
|
adam@354
|
860 if le_lt_dec 2 (length ls)
|
adam@480
|
861 then let lss := split ls in
|
adam@356
|
862 ls1 <- mergeSort'' le (fst lss);
|
adam@356
|
863 ls2 <- mergeSort'' le (snd lss);
|
adam@356
|
864 Ret (merge le ls1 ls2)
|
adam@354
|
865 else Ret ls.
|
adam@354
|
866
|
adam@356
|
867 (** To execute this function, we go through the usual exercise of writing a function to catalyze evaluation of co-recursive calls. *)
|
adam@356
|
868
|
adam@354
|
869 Definition frob' A (c : comp A) :=
|
adam@354
|
870 match c with
|
adam@354
|
871 | Ret x => Ret x
|
adam@354
|
872 | Bnd _ c' f => Bnd c' f
|
adam@354
|
873 end.
|
adam@354
|
874
|
adam@354
|
875 Lemma exec_frob : forall A (c : comp A) x,
|
adam@354
|
876 exec (frob' c) x
|
adam@354
|
877 -> exec c x.
|
adam@356
|
878 destruct c; crush.
|
adam@354
|
879 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
880
|
adam@356
|
881 (** Now the same sort of proof script that we applied for testing [thunk]s will get the job done. *)
|
adam@356
|
882
|
adam@354
|
883 Lemma test_mergeSort'' : exec (mergeSort'' leb (1 :: 2 :: 36 :: 8 :: 19 :: nil))
|
adam@354
|
884 (1 :: 2 :: 8 :: 19 :: 36 :: nil).
|
adam@354
|
885 repeat (apply exec_frob; simpl; econstructor).
|
adam@354
|
886 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
887
|
adam@356
|
888 (** Have we finally reached the ideal solution for encoding general recursive definitions, with minimal hassle in syntax and proof obligations? Unfortunately, we have not, as [comp] has a serious expressivity weakness. Consider the following definition of a curried addition function: *)
|
adam@356
|
889
|
adam@354
|
890 Definition curriedAdd (n : nat) := Ret (fun m : nat => Ret (n + m)).
|
adam@354
|
891
|
adam@356
|
892 (** This definition works fine, but we run into trouble when we try to apply it in a trivial way.
|
adam@356
|
893 [[
|
adam@356
|
894 Definition testCurriedAdd := Bnd (curriedAdd 2) (fun f => f 3).
|
adam@354
|
895 ]]
|
adam@354
|
896
|
adam@354
|
897 <<
|
adam@354
|
898 Error: Universe inconsistency.
|
adam@354
|
899 >>
|
adam@356
|
900
|
adam@496
|
901 The problem has to do with rules for inductive definitions that we will study in more detail in Chapter 12. Briefly, recall that the type of the constructor [Bnd] quantifies over a type [B]. To make [testCurriedAdd] work, we would need to instantiate [B] as [nat -> comp nat]. However, Coq enforces a %\emph{predicativity restriction}% that (roughly) no quantifier in an inductive or co-inductive type's definition may ever be instantiated with a term that contains the type being defined. Chapter 12 presents the exact mechanism by which this restriction is enforced, but for now our conclusion is that [comp] is fatally flawed as a way of encoding interesting higher-order functional programs that use general recursion. *)
|
adam@354
|
902
|
adam@354
|
903
|
adam@357
|
904 (** * Comparing the Alternatives *)
|
adam@354
|
905
|
adam@453
|
906 (** We have seen four different approaches to encoding general recursive definitions in Coq. Among them there is no clear champion that dominates the others in every important way. Instead, we close the chapter by comparing the techniques along a number of dimensions. Every technique allows recursive definitions with termination arguments that go beyond Coq's built-in termination checking, so we must turn to subtler points to highlight differences.
|
adam@356
|
907
|
adam@356
|
908 One useful property is automatic integration with normal Coq programming. That is, we would like the type of a function to be the same, whether or not that function is defined using an interesting recursion pattern. Only the first of the four techniques, well-founded recursion, meets this criterion. It is also the only one of the four to meet the related criterion that evaluation of function calls can take place entirely inside Coq's built-in computation machinery. The monad inspired by domain theory occupies some middle ground in this dimension, since generally standard computation is enough to evaluate a term once a high enough approximation level is provided.
|
adam@356
|
909
|
adam@356
|
910 Another useful property is that a function and its termination argument may be developed separately. We may even want to define functions that fail to terminate on some or all inputs. The well-founded recursion technique does not have this property, but the other three do.
|
adam@356
|
911
|
adam@480
|
912 One minor plus is the ability to write recursive definitions in natural syntax, rather than with calls to higher-order combinators. This downside of the first two techniques is actually rather easy to get around using Coq's notation mechanism, though we leave the details as an exercise for the reader. (For this and other details of notations, see Chapter 12 of the Coq 8.4 manual.)
|
adam@356
|
913
|
adam@465
|
914 The first two techniques impose proof obligations that are more basic than termination arguments, where well-founded recursion requires a proof of extensionality and domain-theoretic recursion requires a proof of continuity. A function may not be defined, and thus may not be computed with, until these obligations are proved. The co-inductive techniques avoid this problem, as recursive definitions may be made without any proof obligations.
|
adam@356
|
915
|
adam@356
|
916 We can also consider support for common idioms in functional programming. For instance, the [thunk] monad effectively only supports recursion that is tail recursion, while the others allow arbitrary recursion schemes.
|
adam@356
|
917
|
adam@356
|
918 On the other hand, the [comp] monad does not support the effective mixing of higher-order functions and general recursion, while all the other techniques do. For instance, we can finish the failed [curriedAdd] example in the domain-theoretic monad. *)
|
adam@356
|
919
|
adam@354
|
920 Definition curriedAdd' (n : nat) := Return (fun m : nat => Return (n + m)).
|
adam@354
|
921
|
adam@356
|
922 Definition testCurriedAdd := Bind (curriedAdd' 2) (fun f => f 3).
|
adam@356
|
923
|
adam@357
|
924 (** The same techniques also apply to more interesting higher-order functions like list map, and, as in all four techniques, we can mix primitive and general recursion, preferring the former when possible to avoid proof obligations. *)
|
adam@354
|
925
|
adam@354
|
926 Fixpoint map A B (f : A -> computation B) (ls : list A) : computation (list B) :=
|
adam@354
|
927 match ls with
|
adam@354
|
928 | nil => Return nil
|
adam@354
|
929 | x :: ls' => Bind (f x) (fun x' =>
|
adam@354
|
930 Bind (map f ls') (fun ls'' =>
|
adam@354
|
931 Return (x' :: ls'')))
|
adam@354
|
932 end.
|
adam@354
|
933
|
adam@355
|
934 (** remove printing exists *)
|
adam@356
|
935 Theorem test_map : run (map (fun x => Return (S x)) (1 :: 2 :: 3 :: nil))
|
adam@356
|
936 (2 :: 3 :: 4 :: nil).
|
adam@354
|
937 exists 1; reflexivity.
|
adam@354
|
938 Qed.
|
adam@356
|
939
|
adam@524
|
940 (** One further disadvantage of [comp] is that we cannot prove an inversion lemma for executions of [Bind] without appealing to an _axiom_, a logical complication that we discuss at more length in Chapter 12. The other three techniques allow proof of all the important theorems within the normal logic of Coq.
|
adam@356
|
941
|
adam@357
|
942 Perhaps one theme of our comparison is that one must trade off between, on one hand, functional programming expressiveness and compatibility with normal Coq types and computation; and, on the other hand, the level of proof obligations one is willing to handle at function definition time. *)
|