adamc@26
|
1 (* Copyright (c) 2008, Adam Chlipala
|
adamc@26
|
2 *
|
adamc@26
|
3 * This work is licensed under a
|
adamc@26
|
4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
|
adamc@26
|
5 * Unported License.
|
adamc@26
|
6 * The license text is available at:
|
adamc@26
|
7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
|
adamc@26
|
8 *)
|
adamc@26
|
9
|
adamc@26
|
10 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@26
|
11 Require Import List.
|
adamc@26
|
12
|
adamc@26
|
13 Require Import Tactics.
|
adamc@26
|
14
|
adamc@26
|
15 Set Implicit Arguments.
|
adamc@26
|
16 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@26
|
17
|
adamc@26
|
18
|
adamc@26
|
19 (** %\chapter{Inductive Types}% *)
|
adamc@26
|
20
|
adamc@26
|
21 (** In a sense, CIC is built from just two relatively straightforward features: function types and inductive types. From this modest foundation, we can prove effectively all of the theorems of math and carry out effectively all program verifications, with enough effort expended. This chapter introduces induction and recursion in Coq and shares some "design patterns" for overcoming common pitfalls with them. *)
|
adamc@26
|
22
|
adamc@26
|
23
|
adamc@26
|
24 (** * Enumerations *)
|
adamc@26
|
25
|
adamc@26
|
26 (** Coq inductive types generalize the algebraic datatypes found in Haskell and ML. Confusingly enough, inductive types also generalize generalized algebraic datatypes (GADTs), by adding the possibility for type dependency. Even so, it is worth backing up from the examples of the last chapter and going over basic, algebraic datatype uses of inductive datatypes, because the chance to prove things about the values of these types adds new wrinkles beyond usual practice in Haskell and ML.
|
adamc@26
|
27
|
adamc@26
|
28 The singleton type [unit] is an inductive type: *)
|
adamc@26
|
29
|
adamc@26
|
30 Inductive unit : Set :=
|
adamc@26
|
31 | tt.
|
adamc@26
|
32
|
adamc@26
|
33 (** This vernacular command defines a new inductive type [unit] whose only value is [tt], as we can see by checking the types of the two identifiers: *)
|
adamc@26
|
34
|
adamc@26
|
35 Check unit.
|
adamc@26
|
36 (** [[
|
adamc@26
|
37
|
adamc@26
|
38 unit : Set
|
adamc@26
|
39 ]] *)
|
adamc@26
|
40 Check tt.
|
adamc@26
|
41 (** [[
|
adamc@26
|
42
|
adamc@26
|
43 tt : unit
|
adamc@26
|
44 ]] *)
|
adamc@26
|
45
|
adamc@26
|
46 (** We can prove that [unit] is a genuine singleton type. *)
|
adamc@26
|
47
|
adamc@26
|
48 Theorem unit_singleton : forall x : unit, x = tt.
|
adamc@26
|
49 (** The important thing about an inductive type is, unsurprisingly, that you can do induction over its values, and induction is the key to proving this theorem. We ask to proceed by induction on the variable [x]. *)
|
adamc@26
|
50 induction x.
|
adamc@26
|
51 (** The goal changes to: [[
|
adamc@26
|
52
|
adamc@26
|
53 tt = tt
|
adamc@26
|
54 ]] *)
|
adamc@26
|
55 (** ...which we can discharge trivially. *)
|
adamc@26
|
56 reflexivity.
|
adamc@26
|
57 Qed.
|
adamc@26
|
58
|
adamc@26
|
59 (** It seems kind of odd to write a proof by induction with no inductive hypotheses. We could have arrived at the same result by beginning the proof with: [[
|
adamc@26
|
60
|
adamc@26
|
61 destruct x.
|
adamc@26
|
62 ...which corresponds to "proof by case analysis" in classical math. For non-recursive inductive types, the two tactics will always have identical behavior. Often case analysis is sufficient, even in proofs about recursive types, and it is nice to avoid introducing unneeded induction hypotheses.
|
adamc@26
|
63
|
adamc@26
|
64 What exactly %\textit{%#<i>#is#</i>#%}% the induction principle for [unit]? We can ask Coq: *)
|
adamc@26
|
65
|
adamc@26
|
66 Check unit_ind.
|
adamc@26
|
67 (** [[
|
adamc@26
|
68
|
adamc@26
|
69 unit_ind : forall P : unit -> Prop, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@26
|
70 ]]
|
adamc@26
|
71
|
adamc@26
|
72 Every [Inductive] command defining a type [T] also defines an induction principle named [T_ind]. Coq follows the Curry-Howard correspondence and includes the ingredients of programming and proving in the same single syntactic class. Thus, our type, operations over it, and principles for reasoning about it all live in the same language and are described by the same type system. The key to telling what is a program and what is a proof lies in the distinction between the type [Prop], which appears in our induction principle; and the type [Set], which we have seen a few times already.
|
adamc@26
|
73
|
adamc@26
|
74 The convention goes like this: [Set] is the type of normal types, and the values of such types are programs. [Prop] is the type of logical propositions, and the values of such types are proofs. Thus, an induction principle has a type that shows us that it is a function for building proofs.
|
adamc@26
|
75
|
adamc@26
|
76 Specifically, [unit_ind] quantifies over a predicate [P] over [unit] values. If we can present a proof that [P] holds of [tt], then we are rewarded with a proof that [P] holds for any value [u] of type [unit]. In our last proof, the predicate was [(fun u : unit => u = tt)].
|
adamc@26
|
77
|
adamc@26
|
78 %\medskip%
|
adamc@26
|
79
|
adamc@26
|
80 We can define an inductive type even simpler than [unit]: *)
|
adamc@26
|
81
|
adamc@26
|
82 Inductive Empty_set : Set := .
|
adamc@26
|
83
|
adamc@26
|
84 (** [Empty_set] has no elements. We can prove fun theorems about it: *)
|
adamc@26
|
85
|
adamc@26
|
86 Theorem the_sky_is_falling : forall x : Empty_set, 2 + 2 = 5.
|
adamc@26
|
87 destruct 1.
|
adamc@26
|
88 Qed.
|
adamc@26
|
89
|
adamc@32
|
90 (** Because [Empty_set] has no elements, the fact of having an element of this type implies anything. We use [destruct 1] instead of [destruct x] in the proof because unused quantified variables are relegated to being referred to by number. (There is a good reason for this, related to the unity of quantifiers and implication. An implication is just a quantification over a proof, where the quantified variable is never used. It generally makes more sense to refer to implication hypotheses by number than by name, and Coq treats our quantifier over an unused variable as an implication in determining the proper behavior.)
|
adamc@26
|
91
|
adamc@26
|
92 We can see the induction principle that made this proof so easy: *)
|
adamc@26
|
93
|
adamc@26
|
94 Check Empty_set_ind.
|
adamc@26
|
95 (** [[
|
adamc@26
|
96
|
adamc@26
|
97 Empty_set_ind : forall (P : Empty_set -> Prop) (e : Empty_set), P e
|
adamc@26
|
98 ]]
|
adamc@26
|
99
|
adamc@26
|
100 In other words, any predicate over values from the empty set holds vacuously of every such element. In the last proof, we chose the predicate [(fun _ : Empty_set => 2 + 2 = 5)].
|
adamc@26
|
101
|
adamc@26
|
102 We can also apply this get-out-of-jail-free card programmatically. Here is a lazy way of converting values of [Empty_set] to values of [unit]: *)
|
adamc@26
|
103
|
adamc@26
|
104 Definition e2u (e : Empty_set) : unit := match e with end.
|
adamc@26
|
105
|
adamc@26
|
106 (** We employ [match] pattern matching as in the last chapter. Since we match on a value whose type has no constructors, there is no need to provide any branches.
|
adamc@26
|
107
|
adamc@26
|
108 %\medskip%
|
adamc@26
|
109
|
adamc@26
|
110 Moving up the ladder of complexity, we can define the booleans: *)
|
adamc@26
|
111
|
adamc@26
|
112 Inductive bool : Set :=
|
adamc@26
|
113 | true
|
adamc@26
|
114 | false.
|
adamc@26
|
115
|
adamc@26
|
116 (** We can use less vacuous pattern matching to define boolean negation. *)
|
adamc@26
|
117
|
adamc@26
|
118 Definition not (b : bool) : bool :=
|
adamc@26
|
119 match b with
|
adamc@26
|
120 | true => false
|
adamc@26
|
121 | false => true
|
adamc@26
|
122 end.
|
adamc@26
|
123
|
adamc@27
|
124 (** An alternative definition desugars to the above: *)
|
adamc@27
|
125
|
adamc@27
|
126 Definition not' (b : bool) : bool :=
|
adamc@27
|
127 if b then false else true.
|
adamc@27
|
128
|
adamc@26
|
129 (** We might want to prove that [not] is its own inverse operation. *)
|
adamc@26
|
130
|
adamc@26
|
131 Theorem not_inverse : forall b : bool, not (not b) = b.
|
adamc@26
|
132 destruct b.
|
adamc@26
|
133
|
adamc@26
|
134 (** After we case analyze on [b], we are left with one subgoal for each constructor of [bool].
|
adamc@26
|
135
|
adamc@26
|
136 [[
|
adamc@26
|
137
|
adamc@26
|
138 2 subgoals
|
adamc@26
|
139
|
adamc@26
|
140 ============================
|
adamc@26
|
141 not (not true) = true
|
adamc@26
|
142 ]]
|
adamc@26
|
143
|
adamc@26
|
144 [[
|
adamc@26
|
145 subgoal 2 is:
|
adamc@26
|
146 not (not false) = false
|
adamc@26
|
147 ]]
|
adamc@26
|
148
|
adamc@26
|
149 The first subgoal follows by Coq's rules of computation, so we can dispatch it easily: *)
|
adamc@26
|
150
|
adamc@26
|
151 reflexivity.
|
adamc@26
|
152
|
adamc@26
|
153 (** Likewise for the second subgoal, so we can restart the proof and give a very compact justification. *)
|
adamc@26
|
154
|
adamc@26
|
155 Restart.
|
adamc@26
|
156 destruct b; reflexivity.
|
adamc@26
|
157 Qed.
|
adamc@27
|
158
|
adamc@27
|
159 (** Another theorem about booleans illustrates another useful tactic. *)
|
adamc@27
|
160
|
adamc@27
|
161 Theorem not_ineq : forall b : bool, not b <> b.
|
adamc@27
|
162 destruct b; discriminate.
|
adamc@27
|
163 Qed.
|
adamc@27
|
164
|
adamc@27
|
165 (** [discriminate] is used to prove that two values of an inductive type are not equal, whenever the values are formed with different constructors. In this case, the different constructors are [true] and [false].
|
adamc@27
|
166
|
adamc@27
|
167 At this point, it is probably not hard to guess what the underlying induction principle for [bool] is. *)
|
adamc@27
|
168
|
adamc@27
|
169 Check bool_ind.
|
adamc@27
|
170 (** [[
|
adamc@27
|
171
|
adamc@27
|
172 bool_ind : forall P : bool -> Prop, P true -> P false -> forall b : bool, P b
|
adamc@27
|
173 ]] *)
|
adamc@28
|
174
|
adamc@28
|
175
|
adamc@28
|
176 (** * Simple Recursive Types *)
|
adamc@28
|
177
|
adamc@28
|
178 (** The natural numbers are the simplest common example of an inductive type that actually deserves the name. *)
|
adamc@28
|
179
|
adamc@28
|
180 Inductive nat : Set :=
|
adamc@28
|
181 | O : nat
|
adamc@28
|
182 | S : nat -> nat.
|
adamc@28
|
183
|
adamc@28
|
184 (** [O] is zero, and [S] is the successor function, so that [0] is syntactic sugar for [O], [1] for [S O], [2] for [S (S O)], and so on.
|
adamc@28
|
185
|
adamc@28
|
186 Pattern matching works as we demonstrated in the last chapter: *)
|
adamc@28
|
187
|
adamc@28
|
188 Definition isZero (n : nat) : bool :=
|
adamc@28
|
189 match n with
|
adamc@28
|
190 | O => true
|
adamc@28
|
191 | S _ => false
|
adamc@28
|
192 end.
|
adamc@28
|
193
|
adamc@28
|
194 Definition pred (n : nat) : nat :=
|
adamc@28
|
195 match n with
|
adamc@28
|
196 | O => O
|
adamc@28
|
197 | S n' => n'
|
adamc@28
|
198 end.
|
adamc@28
|
199
|
adamc@28
|
200 (** We can prove theorems by case analysis: *)
|
adamc@28
|
201
|
adamc@28
|
202 Theorem S_isZero : forall n : nat, isZero (pred (S (S n))) = false.
|
adamc@28
|
203 destruct n; reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
204 Qed.
|
adamc@28
|
205
|
adamc@28
|
206 (** We can also now get into genuine inductive theorems. First, we will need a recursive function, to make things interesting. *)
|
adamc@28
|
207
|
adamc@28
|
208 Fixpoint plus (n m : nat) {struct n} : nat :=
|
adamc@28
|
209 match n with
|
adamc@28
|
210 | O => m
|
adamc@28
|
211 | S n' => S (plus n' m)
|
adamc@28
|
212 end.
|
adamc@28
|
213
|
adamc@28
|
214 (** Recall that [Fixpoint] is Coq's mechanism for recursive function definitions, and that the [{struct n}] annotation is noting which function argument decreases structurally at recursive calls.
|
adamc@28
|
215
|
adamc@28
|
216 Some theorems about [plus] can be proved without induction. *)
|
adamc@28
|
217
|
adamc@28
|
218 Theorem O_plus_n : forall n : nat, plus O n = n.
|
adamc@28
|
219 intro; reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
220 Qed.
|
adamc@28
|
221
|
adamc@28
|
222 (** Coq's computation rules automatically simplify the application of [plus]. If we just reverse the order of the arguments, though, this no longer works, and we need induction. *)
|
adamc@28
|
223
|
adamc@28
|
224 Theorem n_plus_O : forall n : nat, plus n O = n.
|
adamc@28
|
225 induction n.
|
adamc@28
|
226
|
adamc@28
|
227 (** Our first subgoal is [plus O O = O], which %\textit{%#<i>#is#</i>#%}% trivial by computation. *)
|
adamc@28
|
228
|
adamc@28
|
229 reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
230
|
adamc@28
|
231 (** Our second subgoal is more work and also demonstrates our first inductive hypothesis.
|
adamc@28
|
232
|
adamc@28
|
233 [[
|
adamc@28
|
234
|
adamc@28
|
235 n : nat
|
adamc@28
|
236 IHn : plus n O = n
|
adamc@28
|
237 ============================
|
adamc@28
|
238 plus (S n) O = S n
|
adamc@28
|
239 ]]
|
adamc@28
|
240
|
adamc@28
|
241 We can start out by using computation to simplify the goal as far as we can. *)
|
adamc@28
|
242
|
adamc@28
|
243 simpl.
|
adamc@28
|
244
|
adamc@28
|
245 (** Now the conclusion is [S (plus n O) = S n]. Using our inductive hypothesis: *)
|
adamc@28
|
246
|
adamc@28
|
247 rewrite IHn.
|
adamc@28
|
248
|
adamc@28
|
249 (** ...we get a trivial conclusion [S n = S n]. *)
|
adamc@28
|
250
|
adamc@28
|
251 reflexivity.
|
adamc@28
|
252
|
adamc@28
|
253 (** Not much really went on in this proof, so the [crush] tactic from the [Tactics] module can prove this theorem automatically. *)
|
adamc@28
|
254
|
adamc@28
|
255 Restart.
|
adamc@28
|
256 induction n; crush.
|
adamc@28
|
257 Qed.
|
adamc@28
|
258
|
adamc@28
|
259 (** We can check out the induction principle at work here: *)
|
adamc@28
|
260
|
adamc@28
|
261 Check nat_ind.
|
adamc@28
|
262 (** [[
|
adamc@28
|
263
|
adamc@28
|
264 nat_ind : forall P : nat -> Prop,
|
adamc@28
|
265 P O -> (forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) -> forall n : nat, P n
|
adamc@28
|
266 ]]
|
adamc@28
|
267
|
adamc@28
|
268 Each of the two cases of our last proof came from the type of one of the arguments to [nat_ind]. We chose [P] to be [(fun n : nat => plus n O = n)]. The first proof case corresponded to [P O], and the second case to [(forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n))]. The free variable [n] and inductive hypothesis [IHn] came from the argument types given here.
|
adamc@28
|
269
|
adamc@28
|
270 Since [nat] has a constructor that takes an argument, we may sometimes need to know that that constructor is injective. *)
|
adamc@28
|
271
|
adamc@28
|
272 Theorem S_inj : forall n m : nat, S n = S m -> n = m.
|
adamc@28
|
273 injection 1; trivial.
|
adamc@28
|
274 Qed.
|
adamc@28
|
275
|
adamc@28
|
276 (** [injection] refers to a premise by number, adding new equalities between the corresponding arguments of equated terms that are formed with the same constructor. We end up needing to prove [n = m -> n = m], so it is unsurprising that a tactic named [trivial] is able to finish the proof.
|
adamc@28
|
277
|
adamc@29
|
278 There is also a very useful tactic called [congruence] that can prove this theorem immediately. [congruence] generalizes [discriminate] and [injection], and it also adds reasoning about the general properties of equality, such as that a function returns equal results on equal arguments. That is, [congruence] is a %\textit{%#<i>#complete decision procedure for the theory of equality and uninterpreted functions#</i>#%}%, plus some smarts about inductive types.
|
adamc@29
|
279
|
adamc@29
|
280 %\medskip%
|
adamc@29
|
281
|
adamc@29
|
282 We can define a type of lists of natural numbers. *)
|
adamc@29
|
283
|
adamc@29
|
284 Inductive nat_list : Set :=
|
adamc@29
|
285 | NNil : nat_list
|
adamc@29
|
286 | NCons : nat -> nat_list -> nat_list.
|
adamc@29
|
287
|
adamc@29
|
288 (** Recursive definitions are straightforward extensions of what we have seen before. *)
|
adamc@29
|
289
|
adamc@29
|
290 Fixpoint nlength (ls : nat_list) : nat :=
|
adamc@29
|
291 match ls with
|
adamc@29
|
292 | NNil => O
|
adamc@29
|
293 | NCons _ ls' => S (nlength ls')
|
adamc@29
|
294 end.
|
adamc@29
|
295
|
adamc@29
|
296 Fixpoint napp (ls1 ls2 : nat_list) {struct ls1} : nat_list :=
|
adamc@29
|
297 match ls1 with
|
adamc@29
|
298 | NNil => ls2
|
adamc@29
|
299 | NCons n ls1' => NCons n (napp ls1' ls2)
|
adamc@29
|
300 end.
|
adamc@29
|
301
|
adamc@29
|
302 (** Inductive theorem proving can again be automated quite effectively. *)
|
adamc@29
|
303
|
adamc@29
|
304 Theorem nlength_napp : forall ls1 ls2 : nat_list, nlength (napp ls1 ls2)
|
adamc@29
|
305 = plus (nlength ls1) (nlength ls2).
|
adamc@29
|
306 induction ls1; crush.
|
adamc@29
|
307 Qed.
|
adamc@29
|
308
|
adamc@29
|
309 Check nat_list_ind.
|
adamc@29
|
310 (** [[
|
adamc@29
|
311
|
adamc@29
|
312 nat_list_ind
|
adamc@29
|
313 : forall P : nat_list -> Prop,
|
adamc@29
|
314 P NNil ->
|
adamc@29
|
315 (forall (n : nat) (n0 : nat_list), P n0 -> P (NCons n n0)) ->
|
adamc@29
|
316 forall n : nat_list, P n
|
adamc@29
|
317 ]]
|
adamc@29
|
318
|
adamc@29
|
319 %\medskip%
|
adamc@29
|
320
|
adamc@29
|
321 In general, we can implement any "tree" types as inductive types. For example, here are binary trees of naturals. *)
|
adamc@29
|
322
|
adamc@29
|
323 Inductive nat_btree : Set :=
|
adamc@29
|
324 | NLeaf : nat_btree
|
adamc@29
|
325 | NNode : nat_btree -> nat -> nat_btree -> nat_btree.
|
adamc@29
|
326
|
adamc@29
|
327 Fixpoint nsize (tr : nat_btree) : nat :=
|
adamc@29
|
328 match tr with
|
adamc@29
|
329 | NLeaf => O
|
adamc@29
|
330 | NNode tr1 _ tr2 => plus (nsize tr1) (nsize tr2)
|
adamc@29
|
331 end.
|
adamc@29
|
332
|
adamc@29
|
333 Fixpoint nsplice (tr1 tr2 : nat_btree) {struct tr1} : nat_btree :=
|
adamc@29
|
334 match tr1 with
|
adamc@29
|
335 | NLeaf => tr2
|
adamc@29
|
336 | NNode tr1' n tr2' => NNode (nsplice tr1' tr2) n tr2'
|
adamc@29
|
337 end.
|
adamc@29
|
338
|
adamc@29
|
339 Theorem plus_assoc : forall n1 n2 n3 : nat, plus (plus n1 n2) n3 = plus n1 (plus n2 n3).
|
adamc@29
|
340 induction n1; crush.
|
adamc@29
|
341 Qed.
|
adamc@29
|
342
|
adamc@29
|
343 Theorem nsize_nsplice : forall tr1 tr2 : nat_btree, nsize (nsplice tr1 tr2)
|
adamc@29
|
344 = plus (nsize tr2) (nsize tr1).
|
adamc@29
|
345 Hint Rewrite n_plus_O plus_assoc : cpdt.
|
adamc@29
|
346
|
adamc@29
|
347 induction tr1; crush.
|
adamc@29
|
348 Qed.
|
adamc@29
|
349
|
adamc@29
|
350 Check nat_btree_ind.
|
adamc@29
|
351 (** [[
|
adamc@29
|
352
|
adamc@29
|
353 nat_btree_ind
|
adamc@29
|
354 : forall P : nat_btree -> Prop,
|
adamc@29
|
355 P NLeaf ->
|
adamc@29
|
356 (forall n : nat_btree,
|
adamc@29
|
357 P n -> forall (n0 : nat) (n1 : nat_btree), P n1 -> P (NNode n n0 n1)) ->
|
adamc@29
|
358 forall n : nat_btree, P n
|
adamc@29
|
359 ]] *)
|
adamc@30
|
360
|
adamc@30
|
361
|
adamc@30
|
362 (** * Parameterized Types *)
|
adamc@30
|
363
|
adamc@30
|
364 (** We can also define polymorphic inductive types, as with algebraic datatypes in Haskell and ML. *)
|
adamc@30
|
365
|
adamc@30
|
366 Inductive list (T : Set) : Set :=
|
adamc@30
|
367 | Nil : list T
|
adamc@30
|
368 | Cons : T -> list T -> list T.
|
adamc@30
|
369
|
adamc@30
|
370 Fixpoint length T (ls : list T) : nat :=
|
adamc@30
|
371 match ls with
|
adamc@30
|
372 | Nil => O
|
adamc@30
|
373 | Cons _ ls' => S (length ls')
|
adamc@30
|
374 end.
|
adamc@30
|
375
|
adamc@30
|
376 Fixpoint app T (ls1 ls2 : list T) {struct ls1} : list T :=
|
adamc@30
|
377 match ls1 with
|
adamc@30
|
378 | Nil => ls2
|
adamc@30
|
379 | Cons x ls1' => Cons x (app ls1' ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
380 end.
|
adamc@30
|
381
|
adamc@30
|
382 Theorem length_app : forall T (ls1 ls2 : list T), length (app ls1 ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
383 = plus (length ls1) (length ls2).
|
adamc@30
|
384 induction ls1; crush.
|
adamc@30
|
385 Qed.
|
adamc@30
|
386
|
adamc@30
|
387 (** There is a useful shorthand for writing many definitions that share the same parameter, based on Coq's %\textit{%#<i>#section#</i>#%}% mechanism. The following block of code is equivalent to the above: *)
|
adamc@30
|
388
|
adamc@30
|
389 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@30
|
390 Reset list.
|
adamc@30
|
391 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@30
|
392
|
adamc@30
|
393 Section list.
|
adamc@30
|
394 Variable T : Set.
|
adamc@30
|
395
|
adamc@30
|
396 Inductive list : Set :=
|
adamc@30
|
397 | Nil : list
|
adamc@30
|
398 | Cons : T -> list -> list.
|
adamc@30
|
399
|
adamc@30
|
400 Fixpoint length (ls : list) : nat :=
|
adamc@30
|
401 match ls with
|
adamc@30
|
402 | Nil => O
|
adamc@30
|
403 | Cons _ ls' => S (length ls')
|
adamc@30
|
404 end.
|
adamc@30
|
405
|
adamc@30
|
406 Fixpoint app (ls1 ls2 : list) {struct ls1} : list :=
|
adamc@30
|
407 match ls1 with
|
adamc@30
|
408 | Nil => ls2
|
adamc@30
|
409 | Cons x ls1' => Cons x (app ls1' ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
410 end.
|
adamc@30
|
411
|
adamc@30
|
412 Theorem length_app : forall ls1 ls2 : list, length (app ls1 ls2)
|
adamc@30
|
413 = plus (length ls1) (length ls2).
|
adamc@30
|
414 induction ls1; crush.
|
adamc@30
|
415 Qed.
|
adamc@30
|
416 End list.
|
adamc@30
|
417
|
adamc@30
|
418 (** After we end the section, the [Variable]s we used are added as extra function parameters for each defined identifier, as needed. *)
|
adamc@30
|
419
|
adamc@30
|
420 Check list.
|
adamc@30
|
421 (** [[
|
adamc@30
|
422
|
adamc@30
|
423 list
|
adamc@30
|
424 : Set -> Set
|
adamc@30
|
425 ]] *)
|
adamc@30
|
426
|
adamc@30
|
427 Check Cons.
|
adamc@30
|
428 (** [[
|
adamc@30
|
429
|
adamc@30
|
430 Cons
|
adamc@30
|
431 : forall T : Set, T -> list T -> list T
|
adamc@30
|
432 ]] *)
|
adamc@30
|
433
|
adamc@30
|
434 Check length.
|
adamc@30
|
435 (** [[
|
adamc@30
|
436
|
adamc@30
|
437 length
|
adamc@30
|
438 : forall T : Set, list T -> nat
|
adamc@30
|
439 ]]
|
adamc@30
|
440
|
adamc@30
|
441 The extra parameter [T] is treated as a new argument to the induction principle, too. *)
|
adamc@30
|
442
|
adamc@30
|
443 Check list_ind.
|
adamc@30
|
444 (** [[
|
adamc@30
|
445
|
adamc@30
|
446 list_ind
|
adamc@30
|
447 : forall (T : Set) (P : list T -> Prop),
|
adamc@30
|
448 P (Nil T) ->
|
adamc@30
|
449 (forall (t : T) (l : list T), P l -> P (Cons t l)) ->
|
adamc@30
|
450 forall l : list T, P l
|
adamc@30
|
451 ]]
|
adamc@30
|
452
|
adamc@30
|
453 Thus, even though we just saw that [T] is added as an extra argument to the constructor [Cons], there is no quantifier for [T] in the type of the inductive case like there is for each of the other arguments. *)
|
adamc@31
|
454
|
adamc@31
|
455
|
adamc@31
|
456 (** * Mutually Inductive Types *)
|
adamc@31
|
457
|
adamc@31
|
458 (** We can define inductive types that refer to each other: *)
|
adamc@31
|
459
|
adamc@31
|
460 Inductive even_list : Set :=
|
adamc@31
|
461 | ENil : even_list
|
adamc@31
|
462 | ECons : nat -> odd_list -> even_list
|
adamc@31
|
463
|
adamc@31
|
464 with odd_list : Set :=
|
adamc@31
|
465 | OCons : nat -> even_list -> odd_list.
|
adamc@31
|
466
|
adamc@31
|
467 Fixpoint elength (el : even_list) : nat :=
|
adamc@31
|
468 match el with
|
adamc@31
|
469 | ENil => O
|
adamc@31
|
470 | ECons _ ol => S (olength ol)
|
adamc@31
|
471 end
|
adamc@31
|
472
|
adamc@31
|
473 with olength (ol : odd_list) : nat :=
|
adamc@31
|
474 match ol with
|
adamc@31
|
475 | OCons _ el => S (elength el)
|
adamc@31
|
476 end.
|
adamc@31
|
477
|
adamc@31
|
478 Fixpoint eapp (el1 el2 : even_list) {struct el1} : even_list :=
|
adamc@31
|
479 match el1 with
|
adamc@31
|
480 | ENil => el2
|
adamc@31
|
481 | ECons n ol => ECons n (oapp ol el2)
|
adamc@31
|
482 end
|
adamc@31
|
483
|
adamc@31
|
484 with oapp (ol : odd_list) (el : even_list) {struct ol} : odd_list :=
|
adamc@31
|
485 match ol with
|
adamc@31
|
486 | OCons n el' => OCons n (eapp el' el)
|
adamc@31
|
487 end.
|
adamc@31
|
488
|
adamc@31
|
489 (** Everything is going roughly the same as in past examples, until we try to prove a theorem similar to those that came before. *)
|
adamc@31
|
490
|
adamc@31
|
491 Theorem elength_eapp : forall el1 el2 : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
492 elength (eapp el1 el2) = plus (elength el1) (elength el2).
|
adamc@31
|
493 induction el1; crush.
|
adamc@31
|
494
|
adamc@31
|
495 (** One goal remains: [[
|
adamc@31
|
496
|
adamc@31
|
497 n : nat
|
adamc@31
|
498 o : odd_list
|
adamc@31
|
499 el2 : even_list
|
adamc@31
|
500 ============================
|
adamc@31
|
501 S (olength (oapp o el2)) = S (plus (olength o) (elength el2))
|
adamc@31
|
502 ]]
|
adamc@31
|
503
|
adamc@31
|
504 We have no induction hypothesis, so we cannot prove this goal without starting another induction, which would reach a similar point, sending us into a futile infinite chain of inductions. The problem is that Coq's generation of [T_ind] principles is incomplete. We only get non-mutual induction principles generated by default. *)
|
adamc@31
|
505
|
adamc@31
|
506 Abort.
|
adamc@31
|
507 Check even_list_ind.
|
adamc@31
|
508 (** [[
|
adamc@31
|
509
|
adamc@31
|
510 even_list_ind
|
adamc@31
|
511 : forall P : even_list -> Prop,
|
adamc@31
|
512 P ENil ->
|
adamc@31
|
513 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P (ECons n o)) ->
|
adamc@31
|
514 forall e : even_list, P e
|
adamc@31
|
515 ]]
|
adamc@31
|
516
|
adamc@31
|
517 We see that no inductive hypotheses are included anywhere in the type. To get them, we must ask for mutual principles as we need them, using the [Scheme] command. *)
|
adamc@31
|
518
|
adamc@31
|
519 Scheme even_list_mut := Induction for even_list Sort Prop
|
adamc@31
|
520 with odd_list_mut := Induction for odd_list Sort Prop.
|
adamc@31
|
521
|
adamc@31
|
522 Check even_list_mut.
|
adamc@31
|
523 (** [[
|
adamc@31
|
524
|
adamc@31
|
525 even_list_mut
|
adamc@31
|
526 : forall (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop),
|
adamc@31
|
527 P ENil ->
|
adamc@31
|
528 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) ->
|
adamc@31
|
529 (forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) ->
|
adamc@31
|
530 forall e : even_list, P e
|
adamc@31
|
531 ]]
|
adamc@31
|
532
|
adamc@31
|
533 This is the principle we wanted in the first place. There is one more wrinkle left in using it: the [induction] tactic will not apply it for us automatically. It will be helpful to look at how to prove one of our past examples without using [induction], so that we can then generalize the technique to mutual inductive types. *)
|
adamc@31
|
534
|
adamc@31
|
535 Theorem n_plus_O' : forall n : nat, plus n O = n.
|
adamc@31
|
536 apply (nat_ind (fun n => plus n O = n)); crush.
|
adamc@31
|
537 Qed.
|
adamc@31
|
538
|
adamc@31
|
539 (** From this example, we can see that [induction] is not magic. It only does some bookkeeping for us to make it easy to apply a theorem, which we can do directly with the [apply] tactic. We apply not just an identifier but a partial application of it, specifying the predicate we mean to prove holds for all naturals.
|
adamc@31
|
540
|
adamc@31
|
541 This technique generalizes to our mutual example: *)
|
adamc@31
|
542
|
adamc@31
|
543 Theorem elength_eapp : forall el1 el2 : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
544 elength (eapp el1 el2) = plus (elength el1) (elength el2).
|
adamc@31
|
545 apply (even_list_mut
|
adamc@31
|
546 (fun el1 : even_list => forall el2 : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
547 elength (eapp el1 el2) = plus (elength el1) (elength el2))
|
adamc@31
|
548 (fun ol : odd_list => forall el : even_list,
|
adamc@31
|
549 olength (oapp ol el) = plus (olength ol) (elength el))); crush.
|
adamc@31
|
550 Qed.
|
adamc@31
|
551
|
adamc@31
|
552 (** We simply need to specify two predicates, one for each of the mutually inductive types. In general, it would not be a good idea to assume that a proof assistant could infer extra predicates, so this way of applying mutual induction is about as straightforward as we could hope for. *)
|
adamc@33
|
553
|
adamc@33
|
554
|
adamc@33
|
555 (** * Reflexive Types *)
|
adamc@33
|
556
|
adamc@33
|
557 (** A kind of inductive type called a %\textit{%#<i>#reflexive type#</i>#%}% is defined in terms of functions that have the type being defined as their range. One very useful class of examples is in modeling variable binders. For instance, here is a type for encoding the syntax of a subset of first-order logic: *)
|
adamc@33
|
558
|
adamc@33
|
559 Inductive formula : Set :=
|
adamc@33
|
560 | Eq : nat -> nat -> formula
|
adamc@33
|
561 | And : formula -> formula -> formula
|
adamc@33
|
562 | Forall : (nat -> formula) -> formula.
|
adamc@33
|
563
|
adamc@33
|
564 (** Our kinds of formulas are equalities between naturals, conjunction, and universal quantification over natural numbers. We avoid needing to include a notion of "variables" in our type, by using Coq functions to encode quantification. For instance, here is the encoding of [forall x : nat, x = x]: *)
|
adamc@33
|
565
|
adamc@33
|
566 Example forall_refl : formula := Forall (fun x => Eq x x).
|
adamc@33
|
567
|
adamc@33
|
568 (** We can write recursive functions over reflexive types quite naturally. Here is one translating our formulas into native Coq propositions. *)
|
adamc@33
|
569
|
adamc@33
|
570 Fixpoint formulaDenote (f : formula) : Prop :=
|
adamc@33
|
571 match f with
|
adamc@33
|
572 | Eq n1 n2 => n1 = n2
|
adamc@33
|
573 | And f1 f2 => formulaDenote f1 /\ formulaDenote f2
|
adamc@33
|
574 | Forall f' => forall n : nat, formulaDenote (f' n)
|
adamc@33
|
575 end.
|
adamc@33
|
576
|
adamc@33
|
577 (** We can also encode a trivial formula transformation that swaps the order of equality and conjunction operands. *)
|
adamc@33
|
578
|
adamc@33
|
579 Fixpoint swapper (f : formula) : formula :=
|
adamc@33
|
580 match f with
|
adamc@33
|
581 | Eq n1 n2 => Eq n2 n1
|
adamc@33
|
582 | And f1 f2 => And (swapper f2) (swapper f1)
|
adamc@33
|
583 | Forall f' => Forall (fun n => swapper (f' n))
|
adamc@33
|
584 end.
|
adamc@33
|
585
|
adamc@33
|
586 (** It is helpful to prove that this transformation does not make true formulas false. *)
|
adamc@33
|
587
|
adamc@33
|
588 Theorem swapper_preserves_truth : forall f, formulaDenote f -> formulaDenote (swapper f).
|
adamc@33
|
589 induction f; crush.
|
adamc@33
|
590 Qed.
|
adamc@33
|
591
|
adamc@33
|
592 (** We can take a look at the induction principle behind this proof. *)
|
adamc@33
|
593
|
adamc@33
|
594 Check formula_ind.
|
adamc@33
|
595 (** [[
|
adamc@33
|
596
|
adamc@33
|
597 formula_ind
|
adamc@33
|
598 : forall P : formula -> Prop,
|
adamc@33
|
599 (forall n n0 : nat, P (Eq n n0)) ->
|
adamc@33
|
600 (forall f0 : formula,
|
adamc@33
|
601 P f0 -> forall f1 : formula, P f1 -> P (And f0 f1)) ->
|
adamc@33
|
602 (forall f1 : nat -> formula,
|
adamc@33
|
603 (forall n : nat, P (f1 n)) -> P (Forall f1)) ->
|
adamc@33
|
604 forall f2 : formula, P f2
|
adamc@33
|
605 ]] *)
|
adamc@33
|
606
|
adamc@33
|
607 (** Focusing on the [Forall] case, which comes third, we see that we are allowed to assume that the theorem holds %\textit{%#<i>#for any application of the argument function [f1]#</i>#%}%. That is, Coq induction principles do not follow a simple rule that the textual representations of induction variables must get shorter in appeals to induction hypotheses. Luckily for us, the people behind the metatheory of Coq have verified that this flexibility does not introduce unsoundness.
|
adamc@33
|
608
|
adamc@33
|
609 %\medskip%
|
adamc@33
|
610
|
adamc@33
|
611 Up to this point, we have seen how to encode in Coq more and more of what is possible with algebraic datatypes in Haskell and ML. This may have given the inaccurate impression that inductive types are a strict extension of algebraic datatypes. In fact, Coq must rule out some types allowed by Haskell and ML, for reasons of soundness. Reflexive types provide our first good example of such a case.
|
adamc@33
|
612
|
adamc@33
|
613 Given our last example of an inductive type, many readers are probably eager to try encoding the syntax of lambda calculus. Indeed, the function-based representation technique that we just used, called %\textit{%#<i>#higher-order abstract syntax (HOAS)#</i>#%}%, is the representation of choice for lambda calculi in Twelf and in many applications implemented in Haskell and ML. Let us try to import that choice to Coq: *)
|
adamc@33
|
614
|
adamc@33
|
615 (** [[
|
adamc@33
|
616
|
adamc@33
|
617 Inductive term : Set :=
|
adamc@33
|
618 | App : term -> term -> term
|
adamc@33
|
619 | Abs : (term -> term) -> term.
|
adamc@33
|
620
|
adamc@33
|
621 [[
|
adamc@33
|
622 Error: Non strictly positive occurrence of "term" in "(term -> term) -> term"
|
adamc@33
|
623 ]]
|
adamc@33
|
624
|
adamc@33
|
625 We have run afoul of the %\textit{%#<i>#strict positivity requirement#</i>#%}% for inductive definitions, which says that the type being defined may not occur to the left of an arrow in the type of a constructor argument. It is important that the type of a constructor is viewed in terms of a series of arguments and a result, since obviously we need recursive occurrences to the lefts of the outermost arrows if we are to have recursive occurrences at all.
|
adamc@33
|
626
|
adamc@33
|
627 Why must Coq enforce this restriction? Imagine that our last definition had been accepted, allowing us to write this function:
|
adamc@33
|
628
|
adamc@33
|
629 [[
|
adamc@33
|
630 Definition uhoh (t : term) : term :=
|
adamc@33
|
631 match t with
|
adamc@33
|
632 | Abs f => f t
|
adamc@33
|
633 | _ => t
|
adamc@33
|
634 end.
|
adamc@33
|
635
|
adamc@33
|
636 Using an informal idea of Coq's semantics, it is easy to verify that the application [uhoh (Abs uhoh)] will run forever. This would be a mere curiosity in OCaml and Haskell, where non-termination is commonplace, though the fact that we have a non-terminating program without explicit recursive function definitions is unusual.
|
adamc@33
|
637
|
adamc@33
|
638 For Coq, however, this would be a disaster. The possibility of writing such a function would destroy all our confidence that proving a theorem means anything. Since Coq combines programs and proofs in one language, we would be able to prove every theorem with an infinite loop.
|
adamc@33
|
639
|
adamc@33
|
640 Nonetheless, the basic insight of HOAS is a very useful one, and there are ways to realize most benefits of HOAS in Coq. We will study a particular technique of this kind in the later chapters on programming language syntax and semantics. *)
|
adamc@34
|
641
|
adamc@34
|
642
|
adamc@34
|
643 (** * An Interlude on Proof Terms *)
|
adamc@34
|
644
|
adamc@34
|
645 (** As we have emphasized a few times already, Coq proofs are actually programs, written in the same language we have been using in our examples all along. We can get a first sense of what this means by taking a look at the definitions of some of the induction principles we have used. *)
|
adamc@34
|
646
|
adamc@34
|
647 Print unit_ind.
|
adamc@34
|
648 (** [[
|
adamc@34
|
649
|
adamc@34
|
650 unit_ind =
|
adamc@34
|
651 fun P : unit -> Prop => unit_rect P
|
adamc@34
|
652 : forall P : unit -> Prop, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@34
|
653 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
654
|
adamc@34
|
655 We see that this induction principle is defined in terms of a more general principle, [unit_rect]. *)
|
adamc@34
|
656
|
adamc@34
|
657 Check unit_rect.
|
adamc@34
|
658 (** [[
|
adamc@34
|
659
|
adamc@34
|
660 unit_rect
|
adamc@34
|
661 : forall P : unit -> Type, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@34
|
662 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
663
|
adamc@34
|
664 [unit_rect] gives [P] type [unit -> Type] instead of [unit -> Prop]. [Type] is another universe, like [Set] and [Prop]. In fact, it is a common supertype of both. Later on, we will discuss exactly what the significances of the different universes are. For now, it is just important that we can use [Type] as a sort of meta-universe that may turn out to be either [Set] or [Prop]. We can see the symmetry inherent in the subtyping relationship by printing the definition of another principle that was generated for [unit] automatically: *)
|
adamc@34
|
665
|
adamc@34
|
666 Print unit_rec.
|
adamc@34
|
667 (** [[
|
adamc@34
|
668
|
adamc@34
|
669 unit_rec =
|
adamc@34
|
670 fun P : unit -> Set => unit_rect P
|
adamc@34
|
671 : forall P : unit -> Set, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@34
|
672 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
673
|
adamc@34
|
674 This is identical to the definition for [unit_ind], except that we have substituted [Set] for [Prop]. For most inductive types [T], then, we get not just induction principles [T_ind], but also recursion principles [T_rec]. We can use [T_rec] to write recursive definitions without explicit [Fixpoint] recursion. For instance, the following two definitions are equivalent: *)
|
adamc@34
|
675
|
adamc@34
|
676 Definition always_O (u : unit) : nat :=
|
adamc@34
|
677 match u with
|
adamc@34
|
678 | tt => O
|
adamc@34
|
679 end.
|
adamc@34
|
680
|
adamc@34
|
681 Definition always_O' (u : unit) : nat :=
|
adamc@34
|
682 unit_rec (fun _ : unit => nat) O u.
|
adamc@34
|
683
|
adamc@34
|
684 (** Going even further down the rabbit hole, [unit_rect] itself is not even a primitive. It is a functional program that we can write manually. *)
|
adamc@34
|
685
|
adamc@34
|
686 Print unit_rect.
|
adamc@34
|
687
|
adamc@34
|
688 (** [[
|
adamc@34
|
689
|
adamc@34
|
690 unit_rect =
|
adamc@34
|
691 fun (P : unit -> Type) (f : P tt) (u : unit) =>
|
adamc@34
|
692 match u as u0 return (P u0) with
|
adamc@34
|
693 | tt => f
|
adamc@34
|
694 end
|
adamc@34
|
695 : forall P : unit -> Type, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u
|
adamc@34
|
696 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
697
|
adamc@34
|
698 The only new feature we see is an [as] clause for a [match], which is used in concert with the [return] clause that we saw in the introduction. Since the type of the [match] is dependent on the value of the object being analyzed, we must give that object a name so that we can refer to it in the [return] clause.
|
adamc@34
|
699
|
adamc@34
|
700 To prove that [unit_rect] is nothing special, we can reimplement it manually. *)
|
adamc@34
|
701
|
adamc@34
|
702 Definition unit_rect' (P : unit -> Type) (f : P tt) (u : unit) :=
|
adamc@34
|
703 match u return (P u) with
|
adamc@34
|
704 | tt => f
|
adamc@34
|
705 end.
|
adamc@34
|
706
|
adamc@34
|
707 (** We use the handy shorthand that lets us omit an [as] annotation when matching on a variable, simply using that variable directly in the [return] clause.
|
adamc@34
|
708
|
adamc@34
|
709 We can check the implement of [nat_rect] as well: *)
|
adamc@34
|
710
|
adamc@34
|
711 Print nat_rect.
|
adamc@34
|
712 (** [[
|
adamc@34
|
713
|
adamc@34
|
714 nat_rect =
|
adamc@34
|
715 fun (P : nat -> Type) (f : P O) (f0 : forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) =>
|
adamc@34
|
716 fix F (n : nat) : P n :=
|
adamc@34
|
717 match n as n0 return (P n0) with
|
adamc@34
|
718 | O => f
|
adamc@34
|
719 | S n0 => f0 n0 (F n0)
|
adamc@34
|
720 end
|
adamc@34
|
721 : forall P : nat -> Type,
|
adamc@34
|
722 P O -> (forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) -> forall n : nat, P n
|
adamc@34
|
723 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
724
|
adamc@34
|
725 Now we have an actual recursive definition. [fix] expressions are an anonymous form of [Fixpoint], just as [fun] expressions stand for anonymous non-recursive functions. Beyond that, the syntax of [fix] mirrors that of [Fixpoint]. We can understand the definition of [nat_rect] better by reimplementing [nat_ind] using sections. *)
|
adamc@34
|
726
|
adamc@34
|
727 Section nat_ind'.
|
adamc@34
|
728 (** First, we have the property of natural numbers that we aim to prove. *)
|
adamc@34
|
729 Variable P : nat -> Prop.
|
adamc@34
|
730
|
adamc@34
|
731 (** Then we require a proof of the [O] case. *)
|
adamc@34
|
732 Variable O_case : P O.
|
adamc@34
|
733
|
adamc@34
|
734 (** Next is a proof of the [S] case, which may assume an inductive hypothesis. *)
|
adamc@34
|
735 Variable S_case : forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n).
|
adamc@34
|
736
|
adamc@34
|
737 (** Finally, we define a recursive function to tie the pieces together. *)
|
adamc@34
|
738 Fixpoint nat_ind' (n : nat) : P n :=
|
adamc@34
|
739 match n return (P n) with
|
adamc@34
|
740 | O => O_case
|
adamc@34
|
741 | S n' => S_case (nat_ind' n')
|
adamc@34
|
742 end.
|
adamc@34
|
743 End nat_ind'.
|
adamc@34
|
744
|
adamc@34
|
745 (** Closing the section adds the [Variable]s as new [fun]-bound arguments to [nat_ind'], and, modulo the use of [Prop] instead of [Type], we end up with the exact same definition that was generated automatically for [nat_rect].
|
adamc@34
|
746
|
adamc@34
|
747 %\medskip%
|
adamc@34
|
748
|
adamc@34
|
749 We can also examine the definition of [even_list_mut], which we generated with [Scheme] for a mutually-recursive type. *)
|
adamc@34
|
750
|
adamc@34
|
751 Print even_list_mut.
|
adamc@34
|
752 (** [[
|
adamc@34
|
753
|
adamc@34
|
754 even_list_mut =
|
adamc@34
|
755 fun (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop)
|
adamc@34
|
756 (f : P ENil) (f0 : forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o))
|
adamc@34
|
757 (f1 : forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) =>
|
adamc@34
|
758 fix F (e : even_list) : P e :=
|
adamc@34
|
759 match e as e0 return (P e0) with
|
adamc@34
|
760 | ENil => f
|
adamc@34
|
761 | ECons n o => f0 n o (F0 o)
|
adamc@34
|
762 end
|
adamc@34
|
763 with F0 (o : odd_list) : P0 o :=
|
adamc@34
|
764 match o as o0 return (P0 o0) with
|
adamc@34
|
765 | OCons n e => f1 n e (F e)
|
adamc@34
|
766 end
|
adamc@34
|
767 for F
|
adamc@34
|
768 : forall (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop),
|
adamc@34
|
769 P ENil ->
|
adamc@34
|
770 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) ->
|
adamc@34
|
771 (forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) ->
|
adamc@34
|
772 forall e : even_list, P e
|
adamc@34
|
773 ]]
|
adamc@34
|
774
|
adamc@34
|
775 We see a mutually-recursive [fix], with the different functions separated by [with] in the same way that they would be separated by [and] in ML. A final [for] clause identifies which of the mutually-recursive functions should be the final value of the [fix] expression. Using this definition as a template, we can reimplement [even_list_mut] directly. *)
|
adamc@34
|
776
|
adamc@34
|
777 Section even_list_mut'.
|
adamc@34
|
778 (** First, we need the properties that we are proving. *)
|
adamc@34
|
779 Variable Peven : even_list -> Prop.
|
adamc@34
|
780 Variable Podd : odd_list -> Prop.
|
adamc@34
|
781
|
adamc@34
|
782 (** Next, we need proofs of the three cases. *)
|
adamc@34
|
783 Variable ENil_case : Peven ENil.
|
adamc@34
|
784 Variable ECons_case : forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), Podd o -> Peven (ECons n o).
|
adamc@34
|
785 Variable OCons_case : forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), Peven e -> Podd (OCons n e).
|
adamc@34
|
786
|
adamc@34
|
787 (** Finally, we define the recursive functions. *)
|
adamc@34
|
788 Fixpoint even_list_mut' (e : even_list) : Peven e :=
|
adamc@34
|
789 match e return (Peven e) with
|
adamc@34
|
790 | ENil => ENil_case
|
adamc@34
|
791 | ECons n o => ECons_case n (odd_list_mut' o)
|
adamc@34
|
792 end
|
adamc@34
|
793 with odd_list_mut' (o : odd_list) : Podd o :=
|
adamc@34
|
794 match o return (Podd o) with
|
adamc@34
|
795 | OCons n e => OCons_case n (even_list_mut' e)
|
adamc@34
|
796 end.
|
adamc@34
|
797 End even_list_mut'.
|
adamc@34
|
798
|
adamc@34
|
799 (** Even induction principles for reflexive types are easy to implement directly. For our [formula] type, we can use a recursive definition much like those we wrote above. *)
|
adamc@34
|
800
|
adamc@34
|
801 Section formula_ind'.
|
adamc@34
|
802 Variable P : formula -> Prop.
|
adamc@34
|
803 Variable Eq_case : forall n1 n2 : nat, P (Eq n1 n2).
|
adamc@34
|
804 Variable And_case : forall f1 f2 : formula,
|
adamc@34
|
805 P f1 -> P f2 -> P (And f1 f2).
|
adamc@34
|
806 Variable Forall_case : forall f : nat -> formula,
|
adamc@34
|
807 (forall n : nat, P (f n)) -> P (Forall f).
|
adamc@34
|
808
|
adamc@34
|
809 Fixpoint formula_ind' (f : formula) : P f :=
|
adamc@34
|
810 match f return (P f) with
|
adamc@34
|
811 | Eq n1 n2 => Eq_case n1 n2
|
adamc@34
|
812 | And f1 f2 => And_case (formula_ind' f1) (formula_ind' f2)
|
adamc@34
|
813 | Forall f' => Forall_case f' (fun n => formula_ind' (f' n))
|
adamc@34
|
814 end.
|
adamc@34
|
815 End formula_ind'.
|
adamc@34
|
816
|