adam@534
|
1 (* Copyright (c) 2006, 2011-2012, 2015, Adam Chlipala
|
adam@350
|
2 *
|
adam@350
|
3 * This work is licensed under a
|
adam@350
|
4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
|
adam@350
|
5 * Unported License.
|
adam@350
|
6 * The license text is available at:
|
adam@350
|
7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
|
adam@350
|
8 *)
|
adam@350
|
9
|
adam@350
|
10 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@534
|
11 Require Import Arith List Omega.
|
adam@350
|
12
|
adam@534
|
13 Require Import Cpdt.CpdtTactics Cpdt.Coinductive.
|
adam@350
|
14
|
adam@350
|
15 Set Implicit Arguments.
|
adam@534
|
16 Set Asymmetric Patterns.
|
adam@350
|
17 (* end hide *)
|
adam@350
|
18
|
adam@350
|
19
|
adam@350
|
20 (** %\chapter{General Recursion}% *)
|
adam@350
|
21
|
adam@353
|
22 (** Termination of all programs is a crucial property of Gallina. Non-terminating programs introduce logical inconsistency, where any theorem can be proved with an infinite loop. Coq uses a small set of conservative, syntactic criteria to check termination of all recursive definitions. These criteria are insufficient to support the natural encodings of a variety of important programming idioms. Further, since Coq makes it so convenient to encode mathematics computationally, with functional programs, we may find ourselves wanting to employ more complicated recursion in mathematical definitions.
|
adam@351
|
23
|
adam@424
|
24 What exactly are the conservative criteria that we run up against? For _recursive_ definitions, recursive calls are only allowed on _syntactic subterms_ of the original primary argument, a restriction known as%\index{primitive recursion}% _primitive recursion_. In fact, Coq's handling of reflexive inductive types (those defined in terms of functions returning the same type) gives a bit more flexibility than in traditional primitive recursion, but the term is still applied commonly. In Chapter 5, we saw how _co-recursive_ definitions are checked against a syntactic guardedness condition that guarantees productivity.
|
adam@351
|
25
|
adam@353
|
26 Many natural recursion patterns satisfy neither condition. For instance, there is our simple running example in this chapter, merge sort. We will study three different approaches to more flexible recursion, and the latter two of the approaches will even support definitions that may fail to terminate on certain inputs, without any up-front characterization of which inputs those may be.
|
adam@351
|
27
|
adam@404
|
28 Before proceeding, it is important to note that the problem here is not as fundamental as it may appear. The final example of Chapter 5 demonstrated what is called a%\index{deep embedding}% _deep embedding_ of the syntax and semantics of a programming language. That is, we gave a mathematical definition of a language of programs and their meanings. This language clearly admitted non-termination, and we could think of writing all our sophisticated recursive functions with such explicit syntax types. However, in doing so, we forfeit our chance to take advantage of Coq's very good built-in support for reasoning about Gallina programs. We would rather use a%\index{shallow embedding}% _shallow embedding_, where we model informal constructs by encoding them as normal Gallina programs. Each of the three techniques of this chapter follows that style. *)
|
adam@351
|
29
|
adam@351
|
30
|
adam@351
|
31 (** * Well-Founded Recursion *)
|
adam@351
|
32
|
adam@404
|
33 (** The essence of terminating recursion is that there are no infinite chains of nested recursive calls. This intuition is commonly mapped to the mathematical idea of a%\index{well-founded relation}% _well-founded relation_, and the associated standard technique in Coq is%\index{well-founded recursion}% _well-founded recursion_. The syntactic-subterm relation that Coq applies by default is well-founded, but many cases demand alternate well-founded relations. To demonstrate, let us see where we get stuck on attempting a standard merge sort implementation. *)
|
adam@351
|
34
|
adam@351
|
35 Section mergeSort.
|
adam@351
|
36 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@351
|
37 Variable le : A -> A -> bool.
|
adam@475
|
38
|
adam@424
|
39 (** We have a set equipped with some "less-than-or-equal-to" test. *)
|
adam@351
|
40
|
adam@351
|
41 (** A standard function inserts an element into a sorted list, preserving sortedness. *)
|
adam@351
|
42
|
adam@351
|
43 Fixpoint insert (x : A) (ls : list A) : list A :=
|
adam@351
|
44 match ls with
|
adam@351
|
45 | nil => x :: nil
|
adam@351
|
46 | h :: ls' =>
|
adam@351
|
47 if le x h
|
adam@351
|
48 then x :: ls
|
adam@351
|
49 else h :: insert x ls'
|
adam@351
|
50 end.
|
adam@351
|
51
|
adam@351
|
52 (** We will also need a function to merge two sorted lists. (We use a less efficient implementation than usual, because the more efficient implementation already forces us to think about well-founded recursion, while here we are only interested in setting up the example of merge sort.) *)
|
adam@351
|
53
|
adam@351
|
54 Fixpoint merge (ls1 ls2 : list A) : list A :=
|
adam@351
|
55 match ls1 with
|
adam@351
|
56 | nil => ls2
|
adam@351
|
57 | h :: ls' => insert h (merge ls' ls2)
|
adam@351
|
58 end.
|
adam@351
|
59
|
adam@480
|
60 (** The last helper function for classic merge sort is the one that follows, to split a list arbitrarily into two pieces of approximately equal length. *)
|
adam@351
|
61
|
adam@480
|
62 Fixpoint split (ls : list A) : list A * list A :=
|
adam@351
|
63 match ls with
|
adam@351
|
64 | nil => (nil, nil)
|
adam@351
|
65 | h :: nil => (h :: nil, nil)
|
adam@351
|
66 | h1 :: h2 :: ls' =>
|
adam@480
|
67 let (ls1, ls2) := split ls' in
|
adam@351
|
68 (h1 :: ls1, h2 :: ls2)
|
adam@351
|
69 end.
|
adam@351
|
70
|
adam@424
|
71 (** Now, let us try to write the final sorting function, using a natural number "[<=]" test [leb] from the standard library.
|
adam@351
|
72 [[
|
adam@351
|
73 Fixpoint mergeSort (ls : list A) : list A :=
|
adam@453
|
74 if leb (length ls) 1
|
adam@351
|
75 then ls
|
adam@480
|
76 else let lss := split ls in
|
adam@351
|
77 merge (mergeSort (fst lss)) (mergeSort (snd lss)).
|
adam@351
|
78 ]]
|
adam@351
|
79
|
adam@351
|
80 <<
|
adam@351
|
81 Recursive call to mergeSort has principal argument equal to
|
adam@480
|
82 "fst (split ls)" instead of a subterm of "ls".
|
adam@351
|
83 >>
|
adam@351
|
84
|
adam@351
|
85 The definition is rejected for not following the simple primitive recursion criterion. In particular, it is not apparent that recursive calls to [mergeSort] are syntactic subterms of the original argument [ls]; indeed, they are not, yet we know this is a well-founded recursive definition.
|
adam@351
|
86
|
adam@351
|
87 To produce an acceptable definition, we need to choose a well-founded relation and prove that [mergeSort] respects it. A good starting point is an examination of how well-foundedness is formalized in the Coq standard library. *)
|
adam@351
|
88
|
adam@351
|
89 Print well_founded.
|
adam@351
|
90 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adam@351
|
91 well_founded =
|
adam@351
|
92 fun (A : Type) (R : A -> A -> Prop) => forall a : A, Acc R a
|
adam@351
|
93 ]]
|
adam@351
|
94
|
adam@404
|
95 The bulk of the definitional work devolves to the%\index{accessibility relation}\index{Gallina terms!Acc}% _accessibility_ relation [Acc], whose definition we may also examine. *)
|
adam@351
|
96
|
adam@424
|
97 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@437
|
98 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@424
|
99 Definition Acc_intro' := Acc_intro.
|
adam@437
|
100 (* end thide *)
|
adam@424
|
101 (* end hide *)
|
adam@424
|
102
|
adam@351
|
103 Print Acc.
|
adam@351
|
104 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adam@351
|
105 Inductive Acc (A : Type) (R : A -> A -> Prop) (x : A) : Prop :=
|
adam@351
|
106 Acc_intro : (forall y : A, R y x -> Acc R y) -> Acc R x
|
adam@351
|
107 ]]
|
adam@351
|
108
|
adam@424
|
109 In prose, an element [x] is accessible for a relation [R] if every element "less than" [x] according to [R] is also accessible. Since [Acc] is defined inductively, we know that any accessibility proof involves a finite chain of invocations, in a certain sense that we can make formal. Building on Chapter 5's examples, let us define a co-inductive relation that is closer to the usual informal notion of "absence of infinite decreasing chains." *)
|
adam@351
|
110
|
adam@474
|
111 CoInductive infiniteDecreasingChain A (R : A -> A -> Prop) : stream A -> Prop :=
|
adam@474
|
112 | ChainCons : forall x y s, infiniteDecreasingChain R (Cons y s)
|
adam@351
|
113 -> R y x
|
adam@474
|
114 -> infiniteDecreasingChain R (Cons x (Cons y s)).
|
adam@351
|
115
|
adam@351
|
116 (** We can now prove that any accessible element cannot be the beginning of any infinite decreasing chain. *)
|
adam@351
|
117
|
adam@351
|
118 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@474
|
119 Lemma noBadChains' : forall A (R : A -> A -> Prop) x, Acc R x
|
adam@474
|
120 -> forall s, ~infiniteDecreasingChain R (Cons x s).
|
adam@351
|
121 induction 1; crush;
|
adam@351
|
122 match goal with
|
adam@474
|
123 | [ H : infiniteDecreasingChain _ _ |- _ ] => inversion H; eauto
|
adam@351
|
124 end.
|
adam@351
|
125 Qed.
|
adam@351
|
126
|
adam@351
|
127 (** From here, the absence of infinite decreasing chains in well-founded sets is immediate. *)
|
adam@351
|
128
|
adam@474
|
129 Theorem noBadChains : forall A (R : A -> A -> Prop), well_founded R
|
adam@474
|
130 -> forall s, ~infiniteDecreasingChain R s.
|
adam@474
|
131 destruct s; apply noBadChains'; auto.
|
adam@351
|
132 Qed.
|
adam@351
|
133 (* end thide *)
|
adam@351
|
134
|
adam@351
|
135 (** Absence of infinite decreasing chains implies absence of infinitely nested recursive calls, for any recursive definition that respects the well-founded relation. The [Fix] combinator from the standard library formalizes that intuition: *)
|
adam@351
|
136
|
adam@351
|
137 Check Fix.
|
adam@351
|
138 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@351
|
139 Fix
|
adam@351
|
140 : forall (A : Type) (R : A -> A -> Prop),
|
adam@351
|
141 well_founded R ->
|
adam@351
|
142 forall P : A -> Type,
|
adam@351
|
143 (forall x : A, (forall y : A, R y x -> P y) -> P x) ->
|
adam@351
|
144 forall x : A, P x
|
adam@351
|
145 ]]
|
adam@351
|
146
|
adam@351
|
147 A call to %\index{Gallina terms!Fix}%[Fix] must present a relation [R] and a proof of its well-foundedness. The next argument, [P], is the possibly dependent range type of the function we build; the domain [A] of [R] is the function's domain. The following argument has this type:
|
adam@351
|
148 [[
|
adam@351
|
149 forall x : A, (forall y : A, R y x -> P y) -> P x
|
adam@351
|
150 ]]
|
adam@351
|
151
|
adam@424
|
152 This is an encoding of the function body. The input [x] stands for the function argument, and the next input stands for the function we are defining. Recursive calls are encoded as calls to the second argument, whose type tells us it expects a value [y] and a proof that [y] is "less than" [x], according to [R]. In this way, we enforce the well-foundedness restriction on recursive calls.
|
adam@351
|
153
|
adam@353
|
154 The rest of [Fix]'s type tells us that it returns a function of exactly the type we expect, so we are now ready to use it to implement [mergeSort]. Careful readers may have noticed that [Fix] has a dependent type of the sort we met in the previous chapter.
|
adam@351
|
155
|
adam@351
|
156 Before writing [mergeSort], we need to settle on a well-founded relation. The right one for this example is based on lengths of lists. *)
|
adam@351
|
157
|
adam@351
|
158 Definition lengthOrder (ls1 ls2 : list A) :=
|
adam@351
|
159 length ls1 < length ls2.
|
adam@351
|
160
|
adam@353
|
161 (** We must prove that the relation is truly well-founded. To save some space in the rest of this chapter, we skip right to nice, automated proof scripts, though we postpone introducing the principles behind such scripts to Part III of the book. Curious readers may still replace semicolons with periods and newlines to step through these scripts interactively. *)
|
adam@351
|
162
|
adam@351
|
163 Hint Constructors Acc.
|
adam@351
|
164
|
adam@351
|
165 Lemma lengthOrder_wf' : forall len, forall ls, length ls <= len -> Acc lengthOrder ls.
|
adam@351
|
166 unfold lengthOrder; induction len; crush.
|
adam@351
|
167 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
168
|
adam@351
|
169 Theorem lengthOrder_wf : well_founded lengthOrder.
|
adam@351
|
170 red; intro; eapply lengthOrder_wf'; eauto.
|
adam@351
|
171 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
172
|
adam@514
|
173 (** Notice that we end these proofs with %\index{Vernacular commands!Defined}%[Defined], not [Qed]. Recall that [Defined] marks the theorems as %\emph{%#<i>#transparent#</i>#%}%, so that the details of their proofs may be used during program execution. Why could such details possibly matter for computation? It turns out that [Fix] satisfies the primitive recursion restriction by declaring itself as _recursive in the structure of [Acc] proofs_. This is possible because [Acc] proofs follow a predictable inductive structure. We must do work, as in the last theorem's proof, to establish that all elements of a type belong to [Acc], but the automatic unwinding of those proofs during recursion is straightforward. If we ended the proof with [Qed], the proof details would be hidden from computation, in which case the unwinding process would get stuck.
|
adam@351
|
174
|
adam@480
|
175 To justify our two recursive [mergeSort] calls, we will also need to prove that [split] respects the [lengthOrder] relation. These proofs, too, must be kept transparent, to avoid stuckness of [Fix] evaluation. We use the syntax [@foo] to reference identifier [foo] with its implicit argument behavior turned off. (The proof details below use Ltac features not introduced yet, and they are safe to skip for now.) *)
|
adam@351
|
176
|
adam@480
|
177 Lemma split_wf : forall len ls, 2 <= length ls <= len
|
adam@480
|
178 -> let (ls1, ls2) := split ls in
|
adam@351
|
179 lengthOrder ls1 ls /\ lengthOrder ls2 ls.
|
adam@351
|
180 unfold lengthOrder; induction len; crush; do 2 (destruct ls; crush);
|
adam@351
|
181 destruct (le_lt_dec 2 (length ls));
|
adam@351
|
182 repeat (match goal with
|
adam@351
|
183 | [ _ : length ?E < 2 |- _ ] => destruct E
|
adam@351
|
184 | [ _ : S (length ?E) < 2 |- _ ] => destruct E
|
adam@480
|
185 | [ IH : _ |- context[split ?L] ] =>
|
adam@480
|
186 specialize (IH L); destruct (split L); destruct IH
|
adam@351
|
187 end; crush).
|
adam@351
|
188 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
189
|
adam@480
|
190 Ltac split_wf := intros ls ?; intros; generalize (@split_wf (length ls) ls);
|
adam@480
|
191 destruct (split ls); destruct 1; crush.
|
adam@351
|
192
|
adam@480
|
193 Lemma split_wf1 : forall ls, 2 <= length ls
|
adam@480
|
194 -> lengthOrder (fst (split ls)) ls.
|
adam@480
|
195 split_wf.
|
adam@351
|
196 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
197
|
adam@480
|
198 Lemma split_wf2 : forall ls, 2 <= length ls
|
adam@480
|
199 -> lengthOrder (snd (split ls)) ls.
|
adam@480
|
200 split_wf.
|
adam@351
|
201 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
202
|
adam@480
|
203 Hint Resolve split_wf1 split_wf2.
|
adam@351
|
204
|
adam@453
|
205 (** To write the function definition itself, we use the %\index{tactics!refine}%[refine] tactic as a convenient way to write a program that needs to manipulate proofs, without writing out those proofs manually. We also use a replacement [le_lt_dec] for [leb] that has a more interesting dependent type. (Note that we would not be able to complete the definition without this change, since [refine] will generate subgoals for the [if] branches based only on the _type_ of the test expression, not its _value_.) *)
|
adam@351
|
206
|
adam@351
|
207 Definition mergeSort : list A -> list A.
|
adam@351
|
208 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@351
|
209 refine (Fix lengthOrder_wf (fun _ => list A)
|
adam@351
|
210 (fun (ls : list A)
|
adam@351
|
211 (mergeSort : forall ls' : list A, lengthOrder ls' ls -> list A) =>
|
adam@351
|
212 if le_lt_dec 2 (length ls)
|
adam@480
|
213 then let lss := split ls in
|
adam@351
|
214 merge (mergeSort (fst lss) _) (mergeSort (snd lss) _)
|
adam@351
|
215 else ls)); subst lss; eauto.
|
adam@351
|
216 Defined.
|
adam@351
|
217 (* end thide *)
|
adam@351
|
218 End mergeSort.
|
adam@351
|
219
|
adam@351
|
220 (** The important thing is that it is now easy to evaluate calls to [mergeSort]. *)
|
adam@351
|
221
|
adam@351
|
222 Eval compute in mergeSort leb (1 :: 2 :: 36 :: 8 :: 19 :: nil).
|
adam@351
|
223 (** [= 1 :: 2 :: 8 :: 19 :: 36 :: nil] *)
|
adam@351
|
224
|
adam@441
|
225 (** %\smallskip{}%Since the subject of this chapter is merely how to define functions with unusual recursion structure, we will not prove any further correctness theorems about [mergeSort]. Instead, we stop at proving that [mergeSort] has the expected computational behavior, for all inputs, not merely the one we just tested. *)
|
adam@351
|
226
|
adam@351
|
227 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@351
|
228 Theorem mergeSort_eq : forall A (le : A -> A -> bool) ls,
|
adam@351
|
229 mergeSort le ls = if le_lt_dec 2 (length ls)
|
adam@480
|
230 then let lss := split ls in
|
adam@351
|
231 merge le (mergeSort le (fst lss)) (mergeSort le (snd lss))
|
adam@351
|
232 else ls.
|
adam@351
|
233 intros; apply (Fix_eq (@lengthOrder_wf A) (fun _ => list A)); intros.
|
adam@351
|
234
|
adam@424
|
235 (** The library theorem [Fix_eq] imposes one more strange subgoal upon us. We must prove that the function body is unable to distinguish between "self" arguments that map equal inputs to equal outputs. One might think this should be true of any Gallina code, but in fact this general%\index{extensionality}% _function extensionality_ property is neither provable nor disprovable within Coq. The type of [Fix_eq] makes clear what we must show manually: *)
|
adam@351
|
236
|
adam@351
|
237 Check Fix_eq.
|
adam@351
|
238 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@351
|
239 Fix_eq
|
adam@351
|
240 : forall (A : Type) (R : A -> A -> Prop) (Rwf : well_founded R)
|
adam@351
|
241 (P : A -> Type)
|
adam@351
|
242 (F : forall x : A, (forall y : A, R y x -> P y) -> P x),
|
adam@351
|
243 (forall (x : A) (f g : forall y : A, R y x -> P y),
|
adam@351
|
244 (forall (y : A) (p : R y x), f y p = g y p) -> F x f = F x g) ->
|
adam@351
|
245 forall x : A,
|
adam@351
|
246 Fix Rwf P F x = F x (fun (y : A) (_ : R y x) => Fix Rwf P F y)
|
adam@351
|
247 ]]
|
adam@351
|
248
|
adam@465
|
249 Most such obligations are dischargeable with straightforward proof automation, and this example is no exception. *)
|
adam@351
|
250
|
adam@351
|
251 match goal with
|
adam@351
|
252 | [ |- context[match ?E with left _ => _ | right _ => _ end] ] => destruct E
|
adam@351
|
253 end; simpl; f_equal; auto.
|
adam@351
|
254 Qed.
|
adam@351
|
255 (* end thide *)
|
adam@351
|
256
|
adam@351
|
257 (** As a final test of our definition's suitability, we can extract to OCaml. *)
|
adam@351
|
258
|
adam@351
|
259 Extraction mergeSort.
|
adam@351
|
260
|
adam@351
|
261 (** <<
|
adam@351
|
262 let rec mergeSort le x =
|
adam@351
|
263 match le_lt_dec (S (S O)) (length x) with
|
adam@351
|
264 | Left ->
|
adam@480
|
265 let lss = split x in
|
adam@351
|
266 merge le (mergeSort le (fst lss)) (mergeSort le (snd lss))
|
adam@351
|
267 | Right -> x
|
adam@351
|
268 >>
|
adam@351
|
269
|
adam@353
|
270 We see almost precisely the same definition we would have written manually in OCaml! It might be a good exercise for the reader to use the commands we saw in the previous chapter to clean up some remaining differences from idiomatic OCaml.
|
adam@351
|
271
|
adam@351
|
272 One more piece of the full picture is missing. To go on and prove correctness of [mergeSort], we would need more than a way of unfolding its definition. We also need an appropriate induction principle matched to the well-founded relation. Such a principle is available in the standard library, though we will say no more about its details here. *)
|
adam@351
|
273
|
adam@351
|
274 Check well_founded_induction.
|
adam@351
|
275 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@351
|
276 well_founded_induction
|
adam@351
|
277 : forall (A : Type) (R : A -> A -> Prop),
|
adam@351
|
278 well_founded R ->
|
adam@351
|
279 forall P : A -> Set,
|
adam@351
|
280 (forall x : A, (forall y : A, R y x -> P y) -> P x) ->
|
adam@351
|
281 forall a : A, P a
|
adam@351
|
282 ]]
|
adam@351
|
283
|
adam@351
|
284 Some more recent Coq features provide more convenient syntax for defining recursive functions. Interested readers can consult the Coq manual about the commands %\index{Function}%[Function] and %\index{Program Fixpoint}%[Program Fixpoint]. *)
|
adam@352
|
285
|
adam@352
|
286
|
adam@354
|
287 (** * A Non-Termination Monad Inspired by Domain Theory *)
|
adam@352
|
288
|
adam@424
|
289 (** The key insights of %\index{domain theory}%domain theory%~\cite{WinskelDomains}% inspire the next approach to modeling non-termination. Domain theory is based on _information orders_ that relate values representing computation results, according to how much information these values convey. For instance, a simple domain might include values "the program does not terminate" and "the program terminates with the answer 5." The former is considered to be an _approximation_ of the latter, while the latter is _not_ an approximation of "the program terminates with the answer 6." The details of domain theory will not be important in what follows; we merely borrow the notion of an approximation ordering on computation results.
|
adam@355
|
290
|
adam@355
|
291 Consider this definition of a type of computations. *)
|
adam@355
|
292
|
adam@352
|
293 Section computation.
|
adam@352
|
294 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@355
|
295 (** The type [A] describes the result a computation will yield, if it terminates.
|
adam@355
|
296
|
adam@355
|
297 We give a rich dependent type to computations themselves: *)
|
adam@352
|
298
|
adam@352
|
299 Definition computation :=
|
adam@352
|
300 {f : nat -> option A
|
adam@352
|
301 | forall (n : nat) (v : A),
|
adam@352
|
302 f n = Some v
|
adam@352
|
303 -> forall (n' : nat), n' >= n
|
adam@352
|
304 -> f n' = Some v}.
|
adam@352
|
305
|
adam@474
|
306 (** A computation is fundamentally a function [f] from an _approximation level_ [n] to an optional result. Intuitively, higher [n] values enable termination in more cases than lower values. A call to [f] may return [None] to indicate that [n] was not high enough to run the computation to completion; higher [n] values may yield [Some]. Further, the proof obligation within the subset type asserts that [f] is _monotone_ in an appropriate sense: when some [n] is sufficient to produce termination, so are all higher [n] values, and they all yield the same program result [v].
|
adam@355
|
307
|
adam@355
|
308 It is easy to define a relation characterizing when a computation runs to a particular result at a particular approximation level. *)
|
adam@355
|
309
|
adam@352
|
310 Definition runTo (m : computation) (n : nat) (v : A) :=
|
adam@352
|
311 proj1_sig m n = Some v.
|
adam@352
|
312
|
adam@355
|
313 (** On top of [runTo], we also define [run], which is the most abstract notion of when a computation runs to a value. *)
|
adam@355
|
314
|
adam@352
|
315 Definition run (m : computation) (v : A) :=
|
adam@352
|
316 exists n, runTo m n v.
|
adam@352
|
317 End computation.
|
adam@352
|
318
|
adam@355
|
319 (** The book source code contains at this point some tactics, lemma proofs, and hint commands, to be used in proving facts about computations. Since their details are orthogonal to the message of this chapter, I have omitted them in the rendered version. *)
|
adam@355
|
320 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@355
|
321
|
adam@352
|
322 Hint Unfold runTo.
|
adam@352
|
323
|
adam@352
|
324 Ltac run' := unfold run, runTo in *; try red; crush;
|
adam@352
|
325 repeat (match goal with
|
adam@352
|
326 | [ _ : proj1_sig ?E _ = _ |- _ ] =>
|
adam@352
|
327 match goal with
|
adam@352
|
328 | [ x : _ |- _ ] =>
|
adam@352
|
329 match x with
|
adam@352
|
330 | E => destruct E
|
adam@352
|
331 end
|
adam@352
|
332 end
|
adam@352
|
333 | [ |- context[match ?M with exist _ _ => _ end] ] => let Heq := fresh "Heq" in
|
adam@352
|
334 case_eq M; intros ? ? Heq; try rewrite Heq in *; try subst
|
adam@352
|
335 | [ _ : context[match ?M with exist _ _ => _ end] |- _ ] => let Heq := fresh "Heq" in
|
adam@352
|
336 case_eq M; intros ? ? Heq; try rewrite Heq in *; subst
|
adam@352
|
337 | [ H : forall n v, ?E n = Some v -> _,
|
adam@352
|
338 _ : context[match ?E ?N with Some _ => _ | None => _ end] |- _ ] =>
|
adam@426
|
339 specialize (H N); destruct (E N); try rewrite (H _ (eq_refl _)) by auto; try discriminate
|
adam@352
|
340 | [ H : forall n v, ?E n = Some v -> _, H' : ?E _ = Some _ |- _ ] => rewrite (H _ _ H') by auto
|
adam@352
|
341 end; simpl in *); eauto 7.
|
adam@352
|
342
|
adam@352
|
343 Ltac run := run'; repeat (match goal with
|
adam@352
|
344 | [ H : forall n v, ?E n = Some v -> _
|
adam@352
|
345 |- context[match ?E ?N with Some _ => _ | None => _ end] ] =>
|
adam@426
|
346 specialize (H N); destruct (E N); try rewrite (H _ (eq_refl _)) by auto; try discriminate
|
adam@352
|
347 end; run').
|
adam@352
|
348
|
adam@352
|
349 Lemma ex_irrelevant : forall P : Prop, P -> exists n : nat, P.
|
adam@352
|
350 exists 0; auto.
|
adam@352
|
351 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
352
|
adam@352
|
353 Hint Resolve ex_irrelevant.
|
adam@352
|
354
|
adam@352
|
355 Require Import Max.
|
adam@352
|
356
|
adam@380
|
357 Theorem max_spec_le : forall n m, n <= m /\ max n m = m \/ m <= n /\ max n m = n.
|
adam@380
|
358 induction n; destruct m; simpl; intuition;
|
adam@380
|
359 specialize (IHn m); intuition.
|
adam@380
|
360 Qed.
|
adam@380
|
361
|
adam@352
|
362 Ltac max := intros n m; generalize (max_spec_le n m); crush.
|
adam@352
|
363
|
adam@352
|
364 Lemma max_1 : forall n m, max n m >= n.
|
adam@352
|
365 max.
|
adam@352
|
366 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
367
|
adam@352
|
368 Lemma max_2 : forall n m, max n m >= m.
|
adam@352
|
369 max.
|
adam@352
|
370 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
371
|
adam@352
|
372 Hint Resolve max_1 max_2.
|
adam@352
|
373
|
adam@352
|
374 Lemma ge_refl : forall n, n >= n.
|
adam@352
|
375 crush.
|
adam@352
|
376 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
377
|
adam@352
|
378 Hint Resolve ge_refl.
|
adam@352
|
379
|
adam@352
|
380 Hint Extern 1 => match goal with
|
adam@352
|
381 | [ H : _ = exist _ _ _ |- _ ] => rewrite H
|
adam@352
|
382 end.
|
adam@355
|
383 (* end hide *)
|
adam@355
|
384 (** remove printing exists *)
|
adam@355
|
385
|
adam@480
|
386 (** Now, as a simple first example of a computation, we can define [Bottom], which corresponds to an infinite loop. For any approximation level, it fails to terminate (returns [None]). Note the use of [abstract] to create a new opaque lemma for the proof found by the #<tt>#%\coqdocvar{%run%}%#</tt># tactic. In contrast to the previous section, opaque proofs are fine here, since the proof components of computations do not influence evaluation behavior. It is generally preferable to make proofs opaque when possible, as this enforces a kind of modularity in the code to follow, preventing it from depending on any details of the proof. *)
|
adam@352
|
387
|
adam@352
|
388 Section Bottom.
|
adam@352
|
389 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@352
|
390
|
adam@352
|
391 Definition Bottom : computation A.
|
adam@352
|
392 exists (fun _ : nat => @None A); abstract run.
|
adam@352
|
393 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
394
|
adam@352
|
395 Theorem run_Bottom : forall v, ~run Bottom v.
|
adam@352
|
396 run.
|
adam@352
|
397 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
398 End Bottom.
|
adam@352
|
399
|
adam@355
|
400 (** A slightly more complicated example is [Return], which gives the same terminating answer at every approximation level. *)
|
adam@355
|
401
|
adam@352
|
402 Section Return.
|
adam@352
|
403 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@352
|
404 Variable v : A.
|
adam@352
|
405
|
adam@352
|
406 Definition Return : computation A.
|
adam@352
|
407 intros; exists (fun _ : nat => Some v); abstract run.
|
adam@352
|
408 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
409
|
adam@352
|
410 Theorem run_Return : run Return v.
|
adam@352
|
411 run.
|
adam@352
|
412 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
413 End Return.
|
adam@352
|
414
|
adam@474
|
415 (** The name [Return] was meant to be suggestive of the standard operations of %\index{monad}%monads%~\cite{Monads}%. The other standard operation is [Bind], which lets us run one computation and, if it terminates, pass its result off to another computation. We implement bind using the notation [let (x, y) := e1 in e2], for pulling apart the value [e1] which may be thought of as a pair. The second component of a [computation] is a proof, which we do not need to mention directly in the definition of [Bind]. *)
|
adam@352
|
416
|
adam@352
|
417 Section Bind.
|
adam@352
|
418 Variables A B : Type.
|
adam@352
|
419 Variable m1 : computation A.
|
adam@352
|
420 Variable m2 : A -> computation B.
|
adam@352
|
421
|
adam@352
|
422 Definition Bind : computation B.
|
adam@352
|
423 exists (fun n =>
|
adam@357
|
424 let (f1, _) := m1 in
|
adam@352
|
425 match f1 n with
|
adam@352
|
426 | None => None
|
adam@352
|
427 | Some v =>
|
adam@357
|
428 let (f2, _) := m2 v in
|
adam@352
|
429 f2 n
|
adam@352
|
430 end); abstract run.
|
adam@352
|
431 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
432
|
adam@352
|
433 Theorem run_Bind : forall (v1 : A) (v2 : B),
|
adam@352
|
434 run m1 v1
|
adam@352
|
435 -> run (m2 v1) v2
|
adam@352
|
436 -> run Bind v2.
|
adam@352
|
437 run; match goal with
|
adam@352
|
438 | [ x : nat, y : nat |- _ ] => exists (max x y)
|
adam@352
|
439 end; run.
|
adam@352
|
440 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
441 End Bind.
|
adam@352
|
442
|
adam@355
|
443 (** A simple notation lets us write [Bind] calls the way they appear in Haskell. *)
|
adam@352
|
444
|
adam@352
|
445 Notation "x <- m1 ; m2" :=
|
adam@352
|
446 (Bind m1 (fun x => m2)) (right associativity, at level 70).
|
adam@352
|
447
|
adam@424
|
448 (** We can verify that we have indeed defined a monad, by proving the standard monad laws. Part of the exercise is choosing an appropriate notion of equality between computations. We use "equality at all approximation levels." *)
|
adam@355
|
449
|
adam@352
|
450 Definition meq A (m1 m2 : computation A) := forall n, proj1_sig m1 n = proj1_sig m2 n.
|
adam@352
|
451
|
adam@352
|
452 Theorem left_identity : forall A B (a : A) (f : A -> computation B),
|
adam@352
|
453 meq (Bind (Return a) f) (f a).
|
adam@352
|
454 run.
|
adam@352
|
455 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
456
|
adam@352
|
457 Theorem right_identity : forall A (m : computation A),
|
adam@352
|
458 meq (Bind m (@Return _)) m.
|
adam@352
|
459 run.
|
adam@352
|
460 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
461
|
adam@357
|
462 Theorem associativity : forall A B C (m : computation A)
|
adam@357
|
463 (f : A -> computation B) (g : B -> computation C),
|
adam@352
|
464 meq (Bind (Bind m f) g) (Bind m (fun x => Bind (f x) g)).
|
adam@352
|
465 run.
|
adam@352
|
466 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
467
|
adam@398
|
468 (** Now we come to the piece most directly inspired by domain theory. We want to support general recursive function definitions, but domain theory tells us that not all definitions are reasonable; some fail to be _continuous_ and thus represent unrealizable computations. To formalize an analogous notion of continuity for our non-termination monad, we write down the approximation relation on computation results that we have had in mind all along. *)
|
adam@352
|
469
|
adam@352
|
470 Section lattice.
|
adam@352
|
471 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@352
|
472
|
adam@352
|
473 Definition leq (x y : option A) :=
|
adam@352
|
474 forall v, x = Some v -> y = Some v.
|
adam@352
|
475 End lattice.
|
adam@352
|
476
|
adam@355
|
477 (** We now have the tools we need to define a new [Fix] combinator that, unlike the one we saw in the prior section, does not require a termination proof, and in fact admits recursive definition of functions that fail to terminate on some or all inputs. *)
|
adam@352
|
478
|
adam@352
|
479 Section Fix.
|
adam@475
|
480
|
adam@355
|
481 (** First, we have the function domain and range types. *)
|
adam@355
|
482
|
adam@352
|
483 Variables A B : Type.
|
adam@355
|
484
|
adam@355
|
485 (** Next comes the function body, which is written as though it can be parameterized over itself, for recursive calls. *)
|
adam@355
|
486
|
adam@352
|
487 Variable f : (A -> computation B) -> (A -> computation B).
|
adam@352
|
488
|
adam@355
|
489 (** Finally, we impose an obligation to prove that the body [f] is continuous. That is, when [f] terminates according to one recursive version of itself, it also terminates with the same result at the same approximation level when passed a recursive version that refines the original, according to [leq]. *)
|
adam@355
|
490
|
adam@352
|
491 Hypothesis f_continuous : forall n v v1 x,
|
adam@352
|
492 runTo (f v1 x) n v
|
adam@352
|
493 -> forall (v2 : A -> computation B),
|
adam@352
|
494 (forall x, leq (proj1_sig (v1 x) n) (proj1_sig (v2 x) n))
|
adam@352
|
495 -> runTo (f v2 x) n v.
|
adam@352
|
496
|
adam@355
|
497 (** The computational part of the [Fix] combinator is easy to define. At approximation level 0, we diverge; at higher levels, we run the body with a functional argument drawn from the next lower level. *)
|
adam@355
|
498
|
adam@352
|
499 Fixpoint Fix' (n : nat) (x : A) : computation B :=
|
adam@352
|
500 match n with
|
adam@352
|
501 | O => Bottom _
|
adam@352
|
502 | S n' => f (Fix' n') x
|
adam@352
|
503 end.
|
adam@352
|
504
|
adam@355
|
505 (** Now it is straightforward to package [Fix'] as a computation combinator [Fix]. *)
|
adam@355
|
506
|
adam@352
|
507 Hint Extern 1 (_ >= _) => omega.
|
adam@352
|
508 Hint Unfold leq.
|
adam@352
|
509
|
adam@352
|
510 Lemma Fix'_ok : forall steps n x v, proj1_sig (Fix' n x) steps = Some v
|
adam@352
|
511 -> forall n', n' >= n
|
adam@352
|
512 -> proj1_sig (Fix' n' x) steps = Some v.
|
adam@352
|
513 unfold runTo in *; induction n; crush;
|
adam@352
|
514 match goal with
|
adam@352
|
515 | [ H : _ >= _ |- _ ] => inversion H; crush; eauto
|
adam@352
|
516 end.
|
adam@352
|
517 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
518
|
adam@352
|
519 Hint Resolve Fix'_ok.
|
adam@352
|
520
|
adam@352
|
521 Hint Extern 1 (proj1_sig _ _ = _) => simpl;
|
adam@352
|
522 match goal with
|
adam@352
|
523 | [ |- proj1_sig ?E _ = _ ] => eapply (proj2_sig E)
|
adam@352
|
524 end.
|
adam@352
|
525
|
adam@352
|
526 Definition Fix : A -> computation B.
|
adam@352
|
527 intro x; exists (fun n => proj1_sig (Fix' n x) n); abstract run.
|
adam@352
|
528 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
529
|
adam@355
|
530 (** Finally, we can prove that [Fix] obeys the expected computation rule. *)
|
adam@352
|
531
|
adam@352
|
532 Theorem run_Fix : forall x v,
|
adam@352
|
533 run (f Fix x) v
|
adam@352
|
534 -> run (Fix x) v.
|
adam@352
|
535 run; match goal with
|
adam@352
|
536 | [ n : nat |- _ ] => exists (S n); eauto
|
adam@352
|
537 end.
|
adam@352
|
538 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
539 End Fix.
|
adam@352
|
540
|
adam@355
|
541 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@352
|
542 Lemma leq_Some : forall A (x y : A), leq (Some x) (Some y)
|
adam@352
|
543 -> x = y.
|
adam@426
|
544 intros ? ? ? H; generalize (H _ (eq_refl _)); crush.
|
adam@352
|
545 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
546
|
adam@352
|
547 Lemma leq_None : forall A (x y : A), leq (Some x) None
|
adam@352
|
548 -> False.
|
adam@426
|
549 intros ? ? ? H; generalize (H _ (eq_refl _)); crush.
|
adam@352
|
550 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
551
|
adam@355
|
552 Ltac mergeSort' := run;
|
adam@355
|
553 repeat (match goal with
|
adam@355
|
554 | [ |- context[match ?E with O => _ | S _ => _ end] ] => destruct E
|
adam@355
|
555 end; run);
|
adam@355
|
556 repeat match goal with
|
adam@355
|
557 | [ H : forall x, leq (proj1_sig (?f x) _) (proj1_sig (?g x) _) |- _ ] =>
|
adam@355
|
558 match goal with
|
adam@355
|
559 | [ H1 : f ?arg = _, H2 : g ?arg = _ |- _ ] =>
|
adam@355
|
560 generalize (H arg); rewrite H1; rewrite H2; clear H1 H2; simpl; intro
|
adam@355
|
561 end
|
adam@355
|
562 end; run; repeat match goal with
|
adam@355
|
563 | [ H : _ |- _ ] => (apply leq_None in H; tauto) || (apply leq_Some in H; subst)
|
adam@355
|
564 end; auto.
|
adam@355
|
565 (* end hide *)
|
adam@355
|
566
|
adam@355
|
567 (** After all that work, it is now fairly painless to define a version of [mergeSort] that requires no proof of termination. We appeal to a program-specific tactic whose definition is hidden here but present in the book source. *)
|
adam@355
|
568
|
adam@352
|
569 Definition mergeSort' : forall A, (A -> A -> bool) -> list A -> computation (list A).
|
adam@352
|
570 refine (fun A le => Fix
|
adam@352
|
571 (fun (mergeSort : list A -> computation (list A))
|
adam@352
|
572 (ls : list A) =>
|
adam@352
|
573 if le_lt_dec 2 (length ls)
|
adam@480
|
574 then let lss := split ls in
|
adam@352
|
575 ls1 <- mergeSort (fst lss);
|
adam@352
|
576 ls2 <- mergeSort (snd lss);
|
adam@352
|
577 Return (merge le ls1 ls2)
|
adam@355
|
578 else Return ls) _); abstract mergeSort'.
|
adam@352
|
579 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
580
|
adam@424
|
581 (** Furthermore, "running" [mergeSort'] on concrete inputs is as easy as choosing a sufficiently high approximation level and letting Coq's computation rules do the rest. Contrast this with the proof work that goes into deriving an evaluation fact for a deeply embedded language, with one explicit proof rule application per execution step. *)
|
adam@352
|
582
|
adam@352
|
583 Lemma test_mergeSort' : run (mergeSort' leb (1 :: 2 :: 36 :: 8 :: 19 :: nil))
|
adam@352
|
584 (1 :: 2 :: 8 :: 19 :: 36 :: nil).
|
adam@352
|
585 exists 4; reflexivity.
|
adam@352
|
586 Qed.
|
adam@352
|
587
|
adam@453
|
588 (** There is another benefit of our new [Fix] compared with the one we used in the previous section: we can now write recursive functions that sometimes fail to terminate, without losing easy reasoning principles for the terminating cases. Consider this simple example, which appeals to another tactic whose definition we elide here. *)
|
adam@355
|
589
|
adam@355
|
590 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@355
|
591 Ltac looper := unfold leq in *; run;
|
adam@355
|
592 repeat match goal with
|
adam@355
|
593 | [ x : unit |- _ ] => destruct x
|
adam@355
|
594 | [ x : bool |- _ ] => destruct x
|
adam@355
|
595 end; auto.
|
adam@355
|
596 (* end hide *)
|
adam@355
|
597
|
adam@352
|
598 Definition looper : bool -> computation unit.
|
adam@352
|
599 refine (Fix (fun looper (b : bool) =>
|
adam@355
|
600 if b then Return tt else looper b) _); abstract looper.
|
adam@352
|
601 Defined.
|
adam@352
|
602
|
adam@352
|
603 Lemma test_looper : run (looper true) tt.
|
adam@352
|
604 exists 1; reflexivity.
|
adam@352
|
605 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
606
|
adam@355
|
607 (** As before, proving outputs for specific inputs is as easy as demonstrating a high enough approximation level.
|
adam@355
|
608
|
adam@480
|
609 There are other theorems that are important to prove about combinators like [Return], [Bind], and [Fix]. In general, for a computation [c], we sometimes have a hypothesis proving [run c v] for some [v], and we want to perform inversion to deduce what [v] must be. Each combinator should ideally have a theorem of that kind, for [c] built directly from that combinator. We have omitted such theorems here, but they are not hard to prove. In general, the domain theory-inspired approach avoids the type-theoretic "gotchas" that tend to show up in approaches that try to mix normal Coq computation with explicit syntax types. The next section of this chapter demonstrates two alternate approaches of that sort. In the final section of the chapter, we review the pros and cons of the different choices, coming to the conclusion that none of them is obviously better than any one of the others for all situations. *)
|
adam@355
|
610
|
adam@354
|
611
|
adam@354
|
612 (** * Co-Inductive Non-Termination Monads *)
|
adam@354
|
613
|
adam@356
|
614 (** There are two key downsides to both of the previous approaches: both require unusual syntax based on explicit calls to fixpoint combinators, and both generate immediate proof obligations about the bodies of recursive definitions. In Chapter 5, we have already seen how co-inductive types support recursive definitions that exhibit certain well-behaved varieties of non-termination. It turns out that we can leverage that co-induction support for encoding of general recursive definitions, by adding layers of co-inductive syntax. In effect, we mix elements of shallow and deep embeddings.
|
adam@356
|
615
|
adam@356
|
616 Our first example of this kind, proposed by Capretta%~\cite{Capretta}%, defines a silly-looking type of thunks; that is, computations that may be forced to yield results, if they terminate. *)
|
adam@356
|
617
|
adam@354
|
618 CoInductive thunk (A : Type) : Type :=
|
adam@354
|
619 | Answer : A -> thunk A
|
adam@354
|
620 | Think : thunk A -> thunk A.
|
adam@354
|
621
|
adam@356
|
622 (** A computation is either an immediate [Answer] or another computation wrapped inside [Think]. Since [thunk] is co-inductive, every [thunk] type is inhabited by an infinite nesting of [Think]s, standing for non-termination. Terminating results are [Answer] wrapped inside some finite number of [Think]s.
|
adam@356
|
623
|
adam@424
|
624 Why bother to write such a strange definition? The definition of [thunk] is motivated by the ability it gives us to define a "bind" operation, similar to the one we defined in the previous section. *)
|
adam@356
|
625
|
adam@356
|
626 CoFixpoint TBind A B (m1 : thunk A) (m2 : A -> thunk B) : thunk B :=
|
adam@354
|
627 match m1 with
|
adam@354
|
628 | Answer x => m2 x
|
adam@354
|
629 | Think m1' => Think (TBind m1' m2)
|
adam@354
|
630 end.
|
adam@354
|
631
|
adam@356
|
632 (** Note that the definition would violate the co-recursion guardedness restriction if we left out the seemingly superfluous [Think] on the righthand side of the second [match] branch.
|
adam@356
|
633
|
adam@356
|
634 We can prove that [Answer] and [TBind] form a monad for [thunk]. The proof is omitted here but present in the book source. As usual for this sort of proof, a key element is choosing an appropriate notion of equality for [thunk]s. *)
|
adam@356
|
635
|
adam@356
|
636 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@354
|
637 CoInductive thunk_eq A : thunk A -> thunk A -> Prop :=
|
adam@354
|
638 | EqAnswer : forall x, thunk_eq (Answer x) (Answer x)
|
adam@354
|
639 | EqThinkL : forall m1 m2, thunk_eq m1 m2 -> thunk_eq (Think m1) m2
|
adam@354
|
640 | EqThinkR : forall m1 m2, thunk_eq m1 m2 -> thunk_eq m1 (Think m2).
|
adam@354
|
641
|
adam@354
|
642 Section thunk_eq_coind.
|
adam@354
|
643 Variable A : Type.
|
adam@354
|
644 Variable P : thunk A -> thunk A -> Prop.
|
adam@354
|
645
|
adam@354
|
646 Hypothesis H : forall m1 m2, P m1 m2
|
adam@354
|
647 -> match m1, m2 with
|
adam@354
|
648 | Answer x1, Answer x2 => x1 = x2
|
adam@354
|
649 | Think m1', Think m2' => P m1' m2'
|
adam@354
|
650 | Think m1', _ => P m1' m2
|
adam@354
|
651 | _, Think m2' => P m1 m2'
|
adam@354
|
652 end.
|
adam@354
|
653
|
adam@354
|
654 Theorem thunk_eq_coind : forall m1 m2, P m1 m2 -> thunk_eq m1 m2.
|
adam@354
|
655 cofix; intros;
|
adam@354
|
656 match goal with
|
adam@354
|
657 | [ H' : P _ _ |- _ ] => specialize (H H'); clear H'
|
adam@354
|
658 end; destruct m1; destruct m2; subst; repeat constructor; auto.
|
adam@354
|
659 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
660 End thunk_eq_coind.
|
adam@356
|
661 (* end hide *)
|
adam@356
|
662
|
adam@356
|
663 (** In the proofs to follow, we will need a function similar to one we saw in Chapter 5, to pull apart and reassemble a [thunk] in a way that provokes reduction of co-recursive calls. *)
|
adam@354
|
664
|
adam@354
|
665 Definition frob A (m : thunk A) : thunk A :=
|
adam@354
|
666 match m with
|
adam@354
|
667 | Answer x => Answer x
|
adam@354
|
668 | Think m' => Think m'
|
adam@354
|
669 end.
|
adam@354
|
670
|
adam@354
|
671 Theorem frob_eq : forall A (m : thunk A), frob m = m.
|
adam@354
|
672 destruct m; reflexivity.
|
adam@354
|
673 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
674
|
adam@356
|
675 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@354
|
676 Theorem thunk_eq_frob : forall A (m1 m2 : thunk A),
|
adam@354
|
677 thunk_eq (frob m1) (frob m2)
|
adam@354
|
678 -> thunk_eq m1 m2.
|
adam@354
|
679 intros; repeat rewrite frob_eq in *; auto.
|
adam@354
|
680 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
681
|
adam@354
|
682 Ltac findDestr := match goal with
|
adam@354
|
683 | [ |- context[match ?E with Answer _ => _ | Think _ => _ end] ] =>
|
adam@354
|
684 match E with
|
adam@354
|
685 | context[match _ with Answer _ => _ | Think _ => _ end] => fail 1
|
adam@354
|
686 | _ => destruct E
|
adam@354
|
687 end
|
adam@354
|
688 end.
|
adam@354
|
689
|
adam@354
|
690 Theorem thunk_eq_refl : forall A (m : thunk A), thunk_eq m m.
|
adam@354
|
691 intros; apply (thunk_eq_coind (fun m1 m2 => m1 = m2)); crush; findDestr; reflexivity.
|
adam@354
|
692 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
693
|
adam@354
|
694 Hint Resolve thunk_eq_refl.
|
adam@354
|
695
|
adam@354
|
696 Theorem tleft_identity : forall A B (a : A) (f : A -> thunk B),
|
adam@354
|
697 thunk_eq (TBind (Answer a) f) (f a).
|
adam@354
|
698 intros; apply thunk_eq_frob; crush.
|
adam@354
|
699 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
700
|
adam@354
|
701 Theorem tright_identity : forall A (m : thunk A),
|
adam@354
|
702 thunk_eq (TBind m (@Answer _)) m.
|
adam@354
|
703 intros; apply (thunk_eq_coind (fun m1 m2 => m1 = TBind m2 (@Answer _))); crush;
|
adam@354
|
704 findDestr; reflexivity.
|
adam@354
|
705 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
706
|
adam@354
|
707 Lemma TBind_Answer : forall (A B : Type) (v : A) (m2 : A -> thunk B),
|
adam@354
|
708 TBind (Answer v) m2 = m2 v.
|
adam@354
|
709 intros; rewrite <- (frob_eq (TBind (Answer v) m2));
|
adam@354
|
710 simpl; findDestr; reflexivity.
|
adam@354
|
711 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
712
|
adam@375
|
713 Hint Rewrite TBind_Answer.
|
adam@354
|
714
|
adam@355
|
715 (** printing exists $\exists$ *)
|
adam@355
|
716
|
adam@354
|
717 Theorem tassociativity : forall A B C (m : thunk A) (f : A -> thunk B) (g : B -> thunk C),
|
adam@354
|
718 thunk_eq (TBind (TBind m f) g) (TBind m (fun x => TBind (f x) g)).
|
adam@354
|
719 intros; apply (thunk_eq_coind (fun m1 m2 => (exists m,
|
adam@354
|
720 m1 = TBind (TBind m f) g
|
adam@354
|
721 /\ m2 = TBind m (fun x => TBind (f x) g))
|
adam@354
|
722 \/ m1 = m2)); crush; eauto; repeat (findDestr; crush; eauto).
|
adam@354
|
723 Qed.
|
adam@356
|
724 (* end hide *)
|
adam@356
|
725
|
adam@356
|
726 (** As a simple example, here is how we might define a tail-recursive factorial function. *)
|
adam@354
|
727
|
adam@354
|
728 CoFixpoint fact (n acc : nat) : thunk nat :=
|
adam@354
|
729 match n with
|
adam@354
|
730 | O => Answer acc
|
adam@354
|
731 | S n' => Think (fact n' (S n' * acc))
|
adam@354
|
732 end.
|
adam@354
|
733
|
adam@356
|
734 (** To test our definition, we need an evaluation relation that characterizes results of evaluating [thunk]s. *)
|
adam@356
|
735
|
adam@354
|
736 Inductive eval A : thunk A -> A -> Prop :=
|
adam@354
|
737 | EvalAnswer : forall x, eval (Answer x) x
|
adam@354
|
738 | EvalThink : forall m x, eval m x -> eval (Think m) x.
|
adam@354
|
739
|
adam@375
|
740 Hint Rewrite frob_eq.
|
adam@354
|
741
|
adam@354
|
742 Lemma eval_frob : forall A (c : thunk A) x,
|
adam@354
|
743 eval (frob c) x
|
adam@354
|
744 -> eval c x.
|
adam@354
|
745 crush.
|
adam@354
|
746 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
747
|
adam@354
|
748 Theorem eval_fact : eval (fact 5 1) 120.
|
adam@354
|
749 repeat (apply eval_frob; simpl; constructor).
|
adam@354
|
750 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
751
|
adam@356
|
752 (** We need to apply constructors of [eval] explicitly, but the process is easy to automate completely for concrete input programs.
|
adam@356
|
753
|
adam@465
|
754 Now consider another very similar definition, this time of a Fibonacci number function. *)
|
adam@357
|
755
|
adam@357
|
756 Notation "x <- m1 ; m2" :=
|
adam@357
|
757 (TBind m1 (fun x => m2)) (right associativity, at level 70).
|
adam@357
|
758
|
adam@404
|
759 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@437
|
760 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@424
|
761 Definition fib := pred.
|
adam@437
|
762 (* end thide *)
|
adam@404
|
763 (* end hide *)
|
adam@404
|
764
|
adam@453
|
765 (** %\vspace{-.3in}%[[
|
adam@354
|
766 CoFixpoint fib (n : nat) : thunk nat :=
|
adam@354
|
767 match n with
|
adam@354
|
768 | 0 => Answer 1
|
adam@354
|
769 | 1 => Answer 1
|
adam@357
|
770 | _ => n1 <- fib (pred n);
|
adam@357
|
771 n2 <- fib (pred (pred n));
|
adam@357
|
772 Answer (n1 + n2)
|
adam@354
|
773 end.
|
adam@354
|
774 ]]
|
adam@354
|
775
|
adam@356
|
776 Coq complains that the guardedness condition is violated. The two recursive calls are immediate arguments to [TBind], but [TBind] is not a constructor of [thunk]. Rather, it is a defined function. This example shows a very serious limitation of [thunk] for traditional functional programming: it is not, in general, possible to make recursive calls and then make further recursive calls, depending on the first call's result. The [fact] example succeeded because it was already tail recursive, meaning no further computation is needed after a recursive call.
|
adam@356
|
777
|
adam@356
|
778 %\medskip%
|
adam@356
|
779
|
adam@424
|
780 I know no easy fix for this problem of [thunk], but we can define an alternate co-inductive monad that avoids the problem, based on a proposal by Megacz%~\cite{Megacz}%. We ran into trouble because [TBind] was not a constructor of [thunk], so let us define a new type family where "bind" is a constructor. *)
|
adam@354
|
781
|
adam@354
|
782 CoInductive comp (A : Type) : Type :=
|
adam@354
|
783 | Ret : A -> comp A
|
adam@354
|
784 | Bnd : forall B, comp B -> (B -> comp A) -> comp A.
|
adam@354
|
785
|
adam@404
|
786 (** This example shows off Coq's support for%\index{recursively non-uniform parameters}% _recursively non-uniform parameters_, as in the case of the parameter [A] declared above, where each constructor's type ends in [comp A], but there is a recursive use of [comp] with a different parameter [B]. Beside that technical wrinkle, we see the simplest possible definition of a monad, via a type whose two constructors are precisely the monad operators.
|
adam@356
|
787
|
adam@356
|
788 It is easy to define the semantics of terminating [comp] computations. *)
|
adam@356
|
789
|
adam@354
|
790 Inductive exec A : comp A -> A -> Prop :=
|
adam@354
|
791 | ExecRet : forall x, exec (Ret x) x
|
adam@354
|
792 | ExecBnd : forall B (c : comp B) (f : B -> comp A) x1 x2, exec (A := B) c x1
|
adam@354
|
793 -> exec (f x1) x2
|
adam@354
|
794 -> exec (Bnd c f) x2.
|
adam@354
|
795
|
adam@356
|
796 (** We can also prove that [Ret] and [Bnd] form a monad according to a notion of [comp] equality based on [exec], but we omit details here; they are in the book source at this point. *)
|
adam@356
|
797
|
adam@356
|
798 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@354
|
799 Hint Constructors exec.
|
adam@354
|
800
|
adam@354
|
801 Definition comp_eq A (c1 c2 : comp A) := forall r, exec c1 r <-> exec c2 r.
|
adam@354
|
802
|
adam@354
|
803 Ltac inverter := repeat match goal with
|
adam@354
|
804 | [ H : exec _ _ |- _ ] => inversion H; []; crush
|
adam@354
|
805 end.
|
adam@354
|
806
|
adam@354
|
807 Theorem cleft_identity : forall A B (a : A) (f : A -> comp B),
|
adam@354
|
808 comp_eq (Bnd (Ret a) f) (f a).
|
adam@354
|
809 red; crush; inverter; eauto.
|
adam@354
|
810 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
811
|
adam@354
|
812 Theorem cright_identity : forall A (m : comp A),
|
adam@354
|
813 comp_eq (Bnd m (@Ret _)) m.
|
adam@354
|
814 red; crush; inverter; eauto.
|
adam@354
|
815 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
816
|
adam@354
|
817 Lemma cassociativity1 : forall A B C (f : A -> comp B) (g : B -> comp C) r c,
|
adam@354
|
818 exec c r
|
adam@354
|
819 -> forall m, c = Bnd (Bnd m f) g
|
adam@354
|
820 -> exec (Bnd m (fun x => Bnd (f x) g)) r.
|
adam@354
|
821 induction 1; crush.
|
adam@354
|
822 match goal with
|
adam@354
|
823 | [ H : Bnd _ _ = Bnd _ _ |- _ ] => injection H; clear H; intros; try subst
|
adam@354
|
824 end.
|
adam@354
|
825 move H3 after A.
|
adam@354
|
826 generalize dependent B0.
|
adam@354
|
827 do 2 intro.
|
adam@354
|
828 subst.
|
adam@354
|
829 crush.
|
adam@354
|
830 inversion H; clear H; crush.
|
adam@354
|
831 eauto.
|
adam@354
|
832 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
833
|
adam@354
|
834 Lemma cassociativity2 : forall A B C (f : A -> comp B) (g : B -> comp C) r c,
|
adam@354
|
835 exec c r
|
adam@354
|
836 -> forall m, c = Bnd m (fun x => Bnd (f x) g)
|
adam@354
|
837 -> exec (Bnd (Bnd m f) g) r.
|
adam@354
|
838 induction 1; crush.
|
adam@354
|
839 match goal with
|
adam@354
|
840 | [ H : Bnd _ _ = Bnd _ _ |- _ ] => injection H; clear H; intros; try subst
|
adam@354
|
841 end.
|
adam@354
|
842 move H3 after B.
|
adam@354
|
843 generalize dependent B0.
|
adam@354
|
844 do 2 intro.
|
adam@354
|
845 subst.
|
adam@354
|
846 crush.
|
adam@354
|
847 inversion H0; clear H0; crush.
|
adam@354
|
848 eauto.
|
adam@354
|
849 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
850
|
adam@354
|
851 Hint Resolve cassociativity1 cassociativity2.
|
adam@354
|
852
|
adam@354
|
853 Theorem cassociativity : forall A B C (m : comp A) (f : A -> comp B) (g : B -> comp C),
|
adam@354
|
854 comp_eq (Bnd (Bnd m f) g) (Bnd m (fun x => Bnd (f x) g)).
|
adam@354
|
855 red; crush; eauto.
|
adam@354
|
856 Qed.
|
adam@356
|
857 (* end hide *)
|
adam@356
|
858
|
adam@469
|
859 (** Not only can we define the Fibonacci function with the new monad, but even our running example of merge sort becomes definable. By shadowing our previous notation for "bind," we can write almost exactly the same code as in our previous [mergeSort'] definition, but with less syntactic clutter. *)
|
adam@356
|
860
|
adam@356
|
861 Notation "x <- m1 ; m2" := (Bnd m1 (fun x => m2)).
|
adam@354
|
862
|
adam@354
|
863 CoFixpoint mergeSort'' A (le : A -> A -> bool) (ls : list A) : comp (list A) :=
|
adam@354
|
864 if le_lt_dec 2 (length ls)
|
adam@480
|
865 then let lss := split ls in
|
adam@356
|
866 ls1 <- mergeSort'' le (fst lss);
|
adam@356
|
867 ls2 <- mergeSort'' le (snd lss);
|
adam@356
|
868 Ret (merge le ls1 ls2)
|
adam@354
|
869 else Ret ls.
|
adam@354
|
870
|
adam@356
|
871 (** To execute this function, we go through the usual exercise of writing a function to catalyze evaluation of co-recursive calls. *)
|
adam@356
|
872
|
adam@354
|
873 Definition frob' A (c : comp A) :=
|
adam@354
|
874 match c with
|
adam@354
|
875 | Ret x => Ret x
|
adam@354
|
876 | Bnd _ c' f => Bnd c' f
|
adam@354
|
877 end.
|
adam@354
|
878
|
adam@354
|
879 Lemma exec_frob : forall A (c : comp A) x,
|
adam@354
|
880 exec (frob' c) x
|
adam@354
|
881 -> exec c x.
|
adam@356
|
882 destruct c; crush.
|
adam@354
|
883 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
884
|
adam@356
|
885 (** Now the same sort of proof script that we applied for testing [thunk]s will get the job done. *)
|
adam@356
|
886
|
adam@354
|
887 Lemma test_mergeSort'' : exec (mergeSort'' leb (1 :: 2 :: 36 :: 8 :: 19 :: nil))
|
adam@354
|
888 (1 :: 2 :: 8 :: 19 :: 36 :: nil).
|
adam@354
|
889 repeat (apply exec_frob; simpl; econstructor).
|
adam@354
|
890 Qed.
|
adam@354
|
891
|
adam@356
|
892 (** Have we finally reached the ideal solution for encoding general recursive definitions, with minimal hassle in syntax and proof obligations? Unfortunately, we have not, as [comp] has a serious expressivity weakness. Consider the following definition of a curried addition function: *)
|
adam@356
|
893
|
adam@354
|
894 Definition curriedAdd (n : nat) := Ret (fun m : nat => Ret (n + m)).
|
adam@354
|
895
|
adam@356
|
896 (** This definition works fine, but we run into trouble when we try to apply it in a trivial way.
|
adam@356
|
897 [[
|
adam@356
|
898 Definition testCurriedAdd := Bnd (curriedAdd 2) (fun f => f 3).
|
adam@354
|
899 ]]
|
adam@354
|
900
|
adam@354
|
901 <<
|
adam@354
|
902 Error: Universe inconsistency.
|
adam@354
|
903 >>
|
adam@356
|
904
|
adam@496
|
905 The problem has to do with rules for inductive definitions that we will study in more detail in Chapter 12. Briefly, recall that the type of the constructor [Bnd] quantifies over a type [B]. To make [testCurriedAdd] work, we would need to instantiate [B] as [nat -> comp nat]. However, Coq enforces a %\emph{predicativity restriction}% that (roughly) no quantifier in an inductive or co-inductive type's definition may ever be instantiated with a term that contains the type being defined. Chapter 12 presents the exact mechanism by which this restriction is enforced, but for now our conclusion is that [comp] is fatally flawed as a way of encoding interesting higher-order functional programs that use general recursion. *)
|
adam@354
|
906
|
adam@354
|
907
|
adam@357
|
908 (** * Comparing the Alternatives *)
|
adam@354
|
909
|
adam@453
|
910 (** We have seen four different approaches to encoding general recursive definitions in Coq. Among them there is no clear champion that dominates the others in every important way. Instead, we close the chapter by comparing the techniques along a number of dimensions. Every technique allows recursive definitions with termination arguments that go beyond Coq's built-in termination checking, so we must turn to subtler points to highlight differences.
|
adam@356
|
911
|
adam@356
|
912 One useful property is automatic integration with normal Coq programming. That is, we would like the type of a function to be the same, whether or not that function is defined using an interesting recursion pattern. Only the first of the four techniques, well-founded recursion, meets this criterion. It is also the only one of the four to meet the related criterion that evaluation of function calls can take place entirely inside Coq's built-in computation machinery. The monad inspired by domain theory occupies some middle ground in this dimension, since generally standard computation is enough to evaluate a term once a high enough approximation level is provided.
|
adam@356
|
913
|
adam@356
|
914 Another useful property is that a function and its termination argument may be developed separately. We may even want to define functions that fail to terminate on some or all inputs. The well-founded recursion technique does not have this property, but the other three do.
|
adam@356
|
915
|
adam@480
|
916 One minor plus is the ability to write recursive definitions in natural syntax, rather than with calls to higher-order combinators. This downside of the first two techniques is actually rather easy to get around using Coq's notation mechanism, though we leave the details as an exercise for the reader. (For this and other details of notations, see Chapter 12 of the Coq 8.4 manual.)
|
adam@356
|
917
|
adam@465
|
918 The first two techniques impose proof obligations that are more basic than termination arguments, where well-founded recursion requires a proof of extensionality and domain-theoretic recursion requires a proof of continuity. A function may not be defined, and thus may not be computed with, until these obligations are proved. The co-inductive techniques avoid this problem, as recursive definitions may be made without any proof obligations.
|
adam@356
|
919
|
adam@356
|
920 We can also consider support for common idioms in functional programming. For instance, the [thunk] monad effectively only supports recursion that is tail recursion, while the others allow arbitrary recursion schemes.
|
adam@356
|
921
|
adam@356
|
922 On the other hand, the [comp] monad does not support the effective mixing of higher-order functions and general recursion, while all the other techniques do. For instance, we can finish the failed [curriedAdd] example in the domain-theoretic monad. *)
|
adam@356
|
923
|
adam@354
|
924 Definition curriedAdd' (n : nat) := Return (fun m : nat => Return (n + m)).
|
adam@354
|
925
|
adam@356
|
926 Definition testCurriedAdd := Bind (curriedAdd' 2) (fun f => f 3).
|
adam@356
|
927
|
adam@357
|
928 (** The same techniques also apply to more interesting higher-order functions like list map, and, as in all four techniques, we can mix primitive and general recursion, preferring the former when possible to avoid proof obligations. *)
|
adam@354
|
929
|
adam@354
|
930 Fixpoint map A B (f : A -> computation B) (ls : list A) : computation (list B) :=
|
adam@354
|
931 match ls with
|
adam@354
|
932 | nil => Return nil
|
adam@354
|
933 | x :: ls' => Bind (f x) (fun x' =>
|
adam@354
|
934 Bind (map f ls') (fun ls'' =>
|
adam@354
|
935 Return (x' :: ls'')))
|
adam@354
|
936 end.
|
adam@354
|
937
|
adam@355
|
938 (** remove printing exists *)
|
adam@356
|
939 Theorem test_map : run (map (fun x => Return (S x)) (1 :: 2 :: 3 :: nil))
|
adam@356
|
940 (2 :: 3 :: 4 :: nil).
|
adam@354
|
941 exists 1; reflexivity.
|
adam@354
|
942 Qed.
|
adam@356
|
943
|
adam@524
|
944 (** One further disadvantage of [comp] is that we cannot prove an inversion lemma for executions of [Bind] without appealing to an _axiom_, a logical complication that we discuss at more length in Chapter 12. The other three techniques allow proof of all the important theorems within the normal logic of Coq.
|
adam@356
|
945
|
adam@357
|
946 Perhaps one theme of our comparison is that one must trade off between, on one hand, functional programming expressiveness and compatibility with normal Coq types and computation; and, on the other hand, the level of proof obligations one is willing to handle at function definition time. *)
|