adam@367
|
1 (* Copyright (c) 2009-2011, Adam Chlipala
|
adamc@235
|
2 *
|
adamc@235
|
3 * This work is licensed under a
|
adamc@235
|
4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
|
adamc@235
|
5 * Unported License.
|
adamc@235
|
6 * The license text is available at:
|
adamc@235
|
7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
|
adamc@235
|
8 *)
|
adamc@235
|
9
|
adamc@235
|
10 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@236
|
11 Require Import Arith.
|
adamc@236
|
12
|
adam@314
|
13 Require Import CpdtTactics.
|
adamc@235
|
14
|
adamc@235
|
15 Set Implicit Arguments.
|
adamc@235
|
16 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@235
|
17
|
adamc@235
|
18
|
adamc@235
|
19 (** %\chapter{Proving in the Large}% *)
|
adamc@235
|
20
|
adam@367
|
21 (** It is somewhat unfortunate that the term %``%#"#theorem proving#"#%''% looks so much like the word %``%#"#theory.#"#%''% Most researchers and practitioners in software assume that mechanized theorem proving is profoundly impractical. Indeed, until recently, most advances in theorem proving for higher-order logics have been largely theoretical. However, starting around the beginning of the 21st century, there was a surge in the use of proof assistants in serious verification efforts. That line of work is still quite new, but I believe it is not too soon to distill some lessons on how to work effectively with large formal proofs.
|
adamc@236
|
22
|
adamc@236
|
23 Thus, this chapter gives some tips for structuring and maintaining large Coq developments. *)
|
adamc@236
|
24
|
adamc@236
|
25
|
adamc@236
|
26 (** * Ltac Anti-Patterns *)
|
adamc@236
|
27
|
adam@367
|
28 (** In this book, I have been following an unusual style, where proofs are not considered finished until they are %\index{fully automated proofs}``%#"#fully automated,#"#%''% in a certain sense. Each such theorem is proved by a single tactic. Since Ltac is a Turing-complete programming language, it is not hard to squeeze arbitrary heuristics into single tactics, using operators like the semicolon to combine steps. In contrast, most Ltac proofs %``%#"#in the wild#"#%''% consist of many steps, performed by individual tactics followed by periods. Is it really worth drawing a distinction between proof steps terminated by semicolons and steps terminated by periods?
|
adamc@236
|
29
|
adamc@237
|
30 I argue that this is, in fact, a very important distinction, with serious consequences for a majority of important verification domains. The more uninteresting drudge work a proof domain involves, the more important it is to work to prove theorems with single tactics. From an automation standpoint, single-tactic proofs can be extremely effective, and automation becomes more and more critical as proofs are populated by more uninteresting detail. In this section, I will give some examples of the consequences of more common proof styles.
|
adamc@236
|
31
|
adamc@236
|
32 As a running example, consider a basic language of arithmetic expressions, an interpreter for it, and a transformation that scales up every constant in an expression. *)
|
adamc@236
|
33
|
adamc@236
|
34 Inductive exp : Set :=
|
adamc@236
|
35 | Const : nat -> exp
|
adamc@236
|
36 | Plus : exp -> exp -> exp.
|
adamc@236
|
37
|
adamc@236
|
38 Fixpoint eval (e : exp) : nat :=
|
adamc@236
|
39 match e with
|
adamc@236
|
40 | Const n => n
|
adamc@236
|
41 | Plus e1 e2 => eval e1 + eval e2
|
adamc@236
|
42 end.
|
adamc@236
|
43
|
adamc@236
|
44 Fixpoint times (k : nat) (e : exp) : exp :=
|
adamc@236
|
45 match e with
|
adamc@236
|
46 | Const n => Const (k * n)
|
adamc@236
|
47 | Plus e1 e2 => Plus (times k e1) (times k e2)
|
adamc@236
|
48 end.
|
adamc@236
|
49
|
adamc@236
|
50 (** We can write a very manual proof that [double] really doubles an expression's value. *)
|
adamc@236
|
51
|
adamc@236
|
52 Theorem eval_times : forall k e,
|
adamc@236
|
53 eval (times k e) = k * eval e.
|
adamc@236
|
54 induction e.
|
adamc@236
|
55
|
adamc@236
|
56 trivial.
|
adamc@236
|
57
|
adamc@236
|
58 simpl.
|
adamc@236
|
59 rewrite IHe1.
|
adamc@236
|
60 rewrite IHe2.
|
adamc@236
|
61 rewrite mult_plus_distr_l.
|
adamc@236
|
62 trivial.
|
adamc@236
|
63 Qed.
|
adamc@236
|
64
|
adam@368
|
65 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@367
|
66 (** We use spaces to separate the two inductive cases, but note that these spaces have no real semantic content; Coq does not enforce that our spacing matches the real case structure of a proof. The second case mentions automatically generated hypothesis names explicitly. As a result, innocuous changes to the theorem statement can invalidate the proof. *)
|
adamc@236
|
67
|
adamc@236
|
68 Reset eval_times.
|
adamc@236
|
69
|
adam@368
|
70 Theorem eval_times : forall k x,
|
adamc@236
|
71 eval (times k x) = k * eval x.
|
adamc@236
|
72 induction x.
|
adamc@236
|
73
|
adamc@236
|
74 trivial.
|
adamc@236
|
75
|
adamc@236
|
76 simpl.
|
adam@367
|
77 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adamc@236
|
78 rewrite IHe1.
|
adam@367
|
79 ]]
|
adamc@236
|
80
|
adam@367
|
81 <<
|
adamc@236
|
82 Error: The reference IHe1 was not found in the current environment.
|
adam@367
|
83 >>
|
adamc@236
|
84
|
adamc@236
|
85 The inductive hypotheses are named [IHx1] and [IHx2] now, not [IHe1] and [IHe2]. *)
|
adamc@236
|
86
|
adamc@236
|
87 Abort.
|
adamc@236
|
88
|
adamc@236
|
89 (** We might decide to use a more explicit invocation of [induction] to give explicit binders for all of the names that we will reference later in the proof. *)
|
adamc@236
|
90
|
adamc@236
|
91 Theorem eval_times : forall k e,
|
adamc@236
|
92 eval (times k e) = k * eval e.
|
adamc@236
|
93 induction e as [ | ? IHe1 ? IHe2 ].
|
adamc@236
|
94
|
adamc@236
|
95 trivial.
|
adamc@236
|
96
|
adamc@236
|
97 simpl.
|
adamc@236
|
98 rewrite IHe1.
|
adamc@236
|
99 rewrite IHe2.
|
adamc@236
|
100 rewrite mult_plus_distr_l.
|
adamc@236
|
101 trivial.
|
adamc@236
|
102 Qed.
|
adamc@236
|
103
|
adam@367
|
104 (** We pass %\index{tactics!induction}%[induction] an %\index{intro pattern}\textit{%#<i>#intro pattern#</i>#%}%, using a [|] character to separate out instructions for the different inductive cases. Within a case, we write [?] to ask Coq to generate a name automatically, and we write an explicit name to assign that name to the corresponding new variable. It is apparent that, to use intro patterns to avoid proof brittleness, one needs to keep track of the seemingly unimportant facts of the orders in which variables are introduced. Thus, the script keeps working if we replace [e] by [x], but it has become more cluttered. Arguably, neither proof is particularly easy to follow.
|
adamc@236
|
105
|
adamc@237
|
106 That category of complaint has to do with understanding proofs as static artifacts. As with programming in general, with serious projects, it tends to be much more important to be able to support evolution of proofs as specifications change. Unstructured proofs like the above examples can be very hard to update in concert with theorem statements. For instance, consider how the last proof script plays out when we modify [times] to introduce a bug. *)
|
adamc@236
|
107
|
adamc@236
|
108 Reset times.
|
adamc@236
|
109
|
adamc@236
|
110 Fixpoint times (k : nat) (e : exp) : exp :=
|
adamc@236
|
111 match e with
|
adamc@236
|
112 | Const n => Const (1 + k * n)
|
adamc@236
|
113 | Plus e1 e2 => Plus (times k e1) (times k e2)
|
adamc@236
|
114 end.
|
adamc@236
|
115
|
adamc@236
|
116 Theorem eval_times : forall k e,
|
adamc@236
|
117 eval (times k e) = k * eval e.
|
adamc@236
|
118 induction e as [ | ? IHe1 ? IHe2 ].
|
adamc@236
|
119
|
adamc@236
|
120 trivial.
|
adamc@236
|
121
|
adamc@236
|
122 simpl.
|
adam@367
|
123 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adamc@236
|
124 rewrite IHe1.
|
adam@367
|
125 ]]
|
adamc@236
|
126
|
adam@367
|
127 <<
|
adamc@236
|
128 Error: The reference IHe1 was not found in the current environment.
|
adam@367
|
129 >>
|
adam@302
|
130 *)
|
adamc@236
|
131
|
adamc@236
|
132 Abort.
|
adamc@236
|
133
|
adam@367
|
134 (** Can you spot what went wrong, without stepping through the script step-by-step? The problem is that [trivial] never fails. Originally, [trivial] had been succeeding in proving an equality that follows by reflexivity. Our change to [times] leads to a case where that equality is no longer true. The invocation [trivial] happily leaves the false equality in place, and we continue on to the span of tactics intended for the second inductive case. Unfortunately, those tactics end up being applied to the %\textit{%#<i>#first#</i>#%}% case instead.
|
adamc@237
|
135
|
adam@367
|
136 The problem with [trivial] could be %``%#"#solved#"#%''% by writing, e.g., [trivial; fail] instead, so that an error is signaled early on if something unexpected happens. However, the root problem is that the syntax of a tactic invocation does not imply how many subgoals it produces. Much more confusing instances of this problem are possible. For example, if a lemma [L] is modified to take an extra hypothesis, then uses of [apply L] will general more subgoals than before. Old unstructured proof scripts will become hopelessly jumbled, with tactics applied to inappropriate subgoals. Because of the lack of structure, there is usually relatively little to be gleaned from knowledge of the precise point in a proof script where an error is raised. *)
|
adamc@236
|
137
|
adamc@236
|
138 Reset times.
|
adamc@236
|
139
|
adamc@236
|
140 Fixpoint times (k : nat) (e : exp) : exp :=
|
adamc@236
|
141 match e with
|
adamc@236
|
142 | Const n => Const (k * n)
|
adamc@236
|
143 | Plus e1 e2 => Plus (times k e1) (times k e2)
|
adamc@236
|
144 end.
|
adamc@236
|
145
|
adamc@237
|
146 (** Many real developments try to make essentially unstructured proofs look structured by applying careful indentation conventions, idempotent case-marker tactics included soley to serve as documentation, and so on. All of these strategies suffer from the same kind of failure of abstraction that was just demonstrated. I like to say that if you find yourself caring about indentation in a proof script, it is a sign that the script is structured poorly.
|
adamc@236
|
147
|
adamc@236
|
148 We can rewrite the current proof with a single tactic. *)
|
adamc@236
|
149
|
adamc@236
|
150 Theorem eval_times : forall k e,
|
adamc@236
|
151 eval (times k e) = k * eval e.
|
adamc@236
|
152 induction e as [ | ? IHe1 ? IHe2 ]; [
|
adamc@236
|
153 trivial
|
adamc@236
|
154 | simpl; rewrite IHe1; rewrite IHe2; rewrite mult_plus_distr_l; trivial ].
|
adamc@236
|
155 Qed.
|
adamc@236
|
156
|
adamc@236
|
157 (** This is an improvement in robustness of the script. We no longer need to worry about tactics from one case being applied to a different case. Still, the proof script is not especially readable. Probably most readers would not find it helpful in explaining why the theorem is true.
|
adamc@236
|
158
|
adamc@236
|
159 The situation gets worse in considering extensions to the theorem we want to prove. Let us add multiplication nodes to our [exp] type and see how the proof fares. *)
|
adamc@236
|
160
|
adamc@236
|
161 Reset exp.
|
adamc@236
|
162
|
adamc@236
|
163 Inductive exp : Set :=
|
adamc@236
|
164 | Const : nat -> exp
|
adamc@236
|
165 | Plus : exp -> exp -> exp
|
adamc@236
|
166 | Mult : exp -> exp -> exp.
|
adamc@236
|
167
|
adamc@236
|
168 Fixpoint eval (e : exp) : nat :=
|
adamc@236
|
169 match e with
|
adamc@236
|
170 | Const n => n
|
adamc@236
|
171 | Plus e1 e2 => eval e1 + eval e2
|
adamc@236
|
172 | Mult e1 e2 => eval e1 * eval e2
|
adamc@236
|
173 end.
|
adamc@236
|
174
|
adamc@236
|
175 Fixpoint times (k : nat) (e : exp) : exp :=
|
adamc@236
|
176 match e with
|
adamc@236
|
177 | Const n => Const (k * n)
|
adamc@236
|
178 | Plus e1 e2 => Plus (times k e1) (times k e2)
|
adamc@236
|
179 | Mult e1 e2 => Mult (times k e1) e2
|
adamc@236
|
180 end.
|
adamc@236
|
181
|
adamc@236
|
182 Theorem eval_times : forall k e,
|
adamc@236
|
183 eval (times k e) = k * eval e.
|
adam@367
|
184 (** %\vspace{-.25in}%[[
|
adamc@236
|
185 induction e as [ | ? IHe1 ? IHe2 ]; [
|
adamc@236
|
186 trivial
|
adamc@236
|
187 | simpl; rewrite IHe1; rewrite IHe2; rewrite mult_plus_distr_l; trivial ].
|
adam@367
|
188 ]]
|
adamc@236
|
189
|
adam@367
|
190 <<
|
adamc@236
|
191 Error: Expects a disjunctive pattern with 3 branches.
|
adam@367
|
192 >>
|
adam@302
|
193 *)
|
adamc@236
|
194
|
adamc@236
|
195 Abort.
|
adamc@236
|
196
|
adamc@236
|
197 (** Unsurprisingly, the old proof fails, because it explicitly says that there are two inductive cases. To update the script, we must, at a minimum, remember the order in which the inductive cases are generated, so that we can insert the new case in the appropriate place. Even then, it will be painful to add the case, because we cannot walk through proof steps interactively when they occur inside an explicit set of cases. *)
|
adamc@236
|
198
|
adamc@236
|
199 Theorem eval_times : forall k e,
|
adamc@236
|
200 eval (times k e) = k * eval e.
|
adamc@236
|
201 induction e as [ | ? IHe1 ? IHe2 | ? IHe1 ? IHe2 ]; [
|
adamc@236
|
202 trivial
|
adamc@236
|
203 | simpl; rewrite IHe1; rewrite IHe2; rewrite mult_plus_distr_l; trivial
|
adamc@236
|
204 | simpl; rewrite IHe1; rewrite mult_assoc; trivial ].
|
adamc@236
|
205 Qed.
|
adamc@236
|
206
|
adamc@236
|
207 (** Now we are in a position to see how much nicer is the style of proof that we have followed in most of this book. *)
|
adamc@236
|
208
|
adamc@236
|
209 Reset eval_times.
|
adamc@236
|
210
|
adamc@238
|
211 Hint Rewrite mult_plus_distr_l : cpdt.
|
adamc@238
|
212
|
adamc@236
|
213 Theorem eval_times : forall k e,
|
adamc@236
|
214 eval (times k e) = k * eval e.
|
adamc@236
|
215 induction e; crush.
|
adamc@236
|
216 Qed.
|
adam@368
|
217 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@236
|
218
|
adamc@237
|
219 (** This style is motivated by a hard truth: one person's manual proof script is almost always mostly inscrutable to most everyone else. I claim that step-by-step formal proofs are a poor way of conveying information. Thus, we had might as well cut out the steps and automate as much as possible.
|
adamc@237
|
220
|
adamc@237
|
221 What about the illustrative value of proofs? Most informal proofs are read to convey the big ideas of proofs. How can reading [induction e; crush] convey any big ideas? My position is that any ideas that standard automation can find are not very big after all, and the %\textit{%#<i>#real#</i>#%}% big ideas should be expressed through lemmas that are added as hints.
|
adamc@237
|
222
|
adamc@237
|
223 An example should help illustrate what I mean. Consider this function, which rewrites an expression using associativity of addition and multiplication. *)
|
adamc@237
|
224
|
adamc@237
|
225 Fixpoint reassoc (e : exp) : exp :=
|
adamc@237
|
226 match e with
|
adamc@237
|
227 | Const _ => e
|
adamc@237
|
228 | Plus e1 e2 =>
|
adamc@237
|
229 let e1' := reassoc e1 in
|
adamc@237
|
230 let e2' := reassoc e2 in
|
adamc@237
|
231 match e2' with
|
adamc@237
|
232 | Plus e21 e22 => Plus (Plus e1' e21) e22
|
adamc@237
|
233 | _ => Plus e1' e2'
|
adamc@237
|
234 end
|
adamc@237
|
235 | Mult e1 e2 =>
|
adamc@237
|
236 let e1' := reassoc e1 in
|
adamc@237
|
237 let e2' := reassoc e2 in
|
adamc@237
|
238 match e2' with
|
adamc@237
|
239 | Mult e21 e22 => Mult (Mult e1' e21) e22
|
adamc@237
|
240 | _ => Mult e1' e2'
|
adamc@237
|
241 end
|
adamc@237
|
242 end.
|
adamc@237
|
243
|
adamc@237
|
244 Theorem reassoc_correct : forall e, eval (reassoc e) = eval e.
|
adam@368
|
245 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@237
|
246 induction e; crush;
|
adamc@237
|
247 match goal with
|
adamc@237
|
248 | [ |- context[match ?E with Const _ => _ | Plus _ _ => _ | Mult _ _ => _ end] ] =>
|
adamc@237
|
249 destruct E; crush
|
adamc@237
|
250 end.
|
adamc@237
|
251
|
adamc@237
|
252 (** One subgoal remains:
|
adamc@237
|
253 [[
|
adamc@237
|
254 IHe2 : eval e3 * eval e4 = eval e2
|
adamc@237
|
255 ============================
|
adamc@237
|
256 eval e1 * eval e3 * eval e4 = eval e1 * eval e2
|
adamc@237
|
257 ]]
|
adamc@237
|
258
|
adamc@237
|
259 [crush] does not know how to finish this goal. We could finish the proof manually. *)
|
adamc@237
|
260
|
adamc@237
|
261 rewrite <- IHe2; crush.
|
adamc@237
|
262
|
adamc@237
|
263 (** However, the proof would be easier to understand and maintain if we separated this insight into a separate lemma. *)
|
adamc@237
|
264
|
adamc@237
|
265 Abort.
|
adamc@237
|
266
|
adamc@237
|
267 Lemma rewr : forall a b c d, b * c = d -> a * b * c = a * d.
|
adamc@237
|
268 crush.
|
adamc@237
|
269 Qed.
|
adamc@237
|
270
|
adamc@237
|
271 Hint Resolve rewr.
|
adamc@237
|
272
|
adamc@237
|
273 Theorem reassoc_correct : forall e, eval (reassoc e) = eval e.
|
adamc@237
|
274 induction e; crush;
|
adamc@237
|
275 match goal with
|
adamc@237
|
276 | [ |- context[match ?E with Const _ => _ | Plus _ _ => _ | Mult _ _ => _ end] ] =>
|
adamc@237
|
277 destruct E; crush
|
adamc@237
|
278 end.
|
adamc@237
|
279 Qed.
|
adam@368
|
280 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@237
|
281
|
adamc@237
|
282 (** In the limit, a complicated inductive proof might rely on one hint for each inductive case. The lemma for each hint could restate the associated case. Compared to manual proof scripts, we arrive at more readable results. Scripts no longer need to depend on the order in which cases are generated. The lemmas are easier to digest separately than are fragments of tactic code, since lemma statements include complete proof contexts. Such contexts can only be extracted from monolithic manual proofs by stepping through scripts interactively.
|
adamc@237
|
283
|
adamc@237
|
284 The more common situation is that a large induction has several easy cases that automation makes short work of. In the remaining cases, automation performs some standard simplification. Among these cases, some may require quite involved proofs; such a case may deserve a hint lemma of its own, where the lemma statement may copy the simplified version of the case. Alternatively, the proof script for the main theorem may be extended with some automation code targeted at the specific case. Even such targeted scripting is more desirable than manual proving, because it may be read and understood without knowledge of a proof's hierarchical structure, case ordering, or name binding structure. *)
|
adamc@237
|
285
|
adamc@235
|
286
|
adamc@238
|
287 (** * Debugging and Maintaining Automation *)
|
adamc@238
|
288
|
adam@367
|
289 (** Fully automated proofs are desirable because they open up possibilities for automatic adaptation to changes of specification. A well-engineered script within a narrow domain can survive many changes to the formulation of the problem it solves. Still, as we are working with higher-order logic, most theorems fall within no obvious decidable theories. It is inevitable that most long-lived automated proofs will need updating.
|
adamc@238
|
290
|
adam@367
|
291 Before we are ready to update our proofs, we need to write them in the first place. While fully automated scripts are most robust to changes of specification, it is hard to write every new proof directly in that form. Instead, it is useful to begin a theorem with exploratory proving and then gradually refine it into a suitable automated form.
|
adamc@238
|
292
|
adam@350
|
293 Consider this theorem from Chapter 8, which we begin by proving in a mostly manual way, invoking [crush] after each steop to discharge any low-hanging fruit. Our manual effort involves choosing which expressions to case-analyze on. *)
|
adamc@238
|
294
|
adamc@238
|
295 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@238
|
296 Require Import MoreDep.
|
adamc@238
|
297 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@238
|
298
|
adamc@238
|
299 Theorem cfold_correct : forall t (e : exp t), expDenote e = expDenote (cfold e).
|
adam@368
|
300 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@238
|
301 induction e; crush.
|
adamc@238
|
302
|
adamc@238
|
303 dep_destruct (cfold e1); crush.
|
adamc@238
|
304 dep_destruct (cfold e2); crush.
|
adamc@238
|
305
|
adamc@238
|
306 dep_destruct (cfold e1); crush.
|
adamc@238
|
307 dep_destruct (cfold e2); crush.
|
adamc@238
|
308
|
adamc@238
|
309 dep_destruct (cfold e1); crush.
|
adamc@238
|
310 dep_destruct (cfold e2); crush.
|
adamc@238
|
311
|
adamc@238
|
312 dep_destruct (cfold e1); crush.
|
adamc@238
|
313 dep_destruct (expDenote e1); crush.
|
adamc@238
|
314
|
adamc@238
|
315 dep_destruct (cfold e); crush.
|
adamc@238
|
316
|
adamc@238
|
317 dep_destruct (cfold e); crush.
|
adamc@238
|
318 Qed.
|
adamc@238
|
319
|
adamc@238
|
320 (** In this complete proof, it is hard to avoid noticing a pattern. We rework the proof, abstracting over the patterns we find. *)
|
adamc@238
|
321
|
adamc@238
|
322 Reset cfold_correct.
|
adamc@238
|
323
|
adamc@238
|
324 Theorem cfold_correct : forall t (e : exp t), expDenote e = expDenote (cfold e).
|
adamc@238
|
325 induction e; crush.
|
adamc@238
|
326
|
adamc@238
|
327 (** The expression we want to destruct here turns out to be the discriminee of a [match], and we can easily enough write a tactic that destructs all such expressions. *)
|
adamc@238
|
328
|
adamc@238
|
329 Ltac t :=
|
adamc@238
|
330 repeat (match goal with
|
adamc@238
|
331 | [ |- context[match ?E with NConst _ => _ | Plus _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
332 | Eq _ _ => _ | BConst _ => _ | And _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
333 | If _ _ _ _ => _ | Pair _ _ _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
334 | Fst _ _ _ => _ | Snd _ _ _ => _ end] ] =>
|
adamc@238
|
335 dep_destruct E
|
adamc@238
|
336 end; crush).
|
adamc@238
|
337
|
adamc@238
|
338 t.
|
adamc@238
|
339
|
adamc@238
|
340 (** This tactic invocation discharges the whole case. It does the same on the next two cases, but it gets stuck on the fourth case. *)
|
adamc@238
|
341
|
adamc@238
|
342 t.
|
adamc@238
|
343
|
adamc@238
|
344 t.
|
adamc@238
|
345
|
adamc@238
|
346 t.
|
adamc@238
|
347
|
adamc@238
|
348 (** The subgoal's conclusion is:
|
adamc@238
|
349 [[
|
adamc@238
|
350 ============================
|
adamc@238
|
351 (if expDenote e1 then expDenote (cfold e2) else expDenote (cfold e3)) =
|
adamc@238
|
352 expDenote (if expDenote e1 then cfold e2 else cfold e3)
|
adamc@238
|
353 ]]
|
adamc@238
|
354
|
adamc@238
|
355 We need to expand our [t] tactic to handle this case. *)
|
adamc@238
|
356
|
adamc@238
|
357 Ltac t' :=
|
adamc@238
|
358 repeat (match goal with
|
adamc@238
|
359 | [ |- context[match ?E with NConst _ => _ | Plus _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
360 | Eq _ _ => _ | BConst _ => _ | And _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
361 | If _ _ _ _ => _ | Pair _ _ _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
362 | Fst _ _ _ => _ | Snd _ _ _ => _ end] ] =>
|
adamc@238
|
363 dep_destruct E
|
adamc@238
|
364 | [ |- (if ?E then _ else _) = _ ] => destruct E
|
adamc@238
|
365 end; crush).
|
adamc@238
|
366
|
adamc@238
|
367 t'.
|
adamc@238
|
368
|
adamc@238
|
369 (** Now the goal is discharged, but [t'] has no effect on the next subgoal. *)
|
adamc@238
|
370
|
adamc@238
|
371 t'.
|
adamc@238
|
372
|
adamc@238
|
373 (** A final revision of [t] finishes the proof. *)
|
adamc@238
|
374
|
adamc@238
|
375 Ltac t'' :=
|
adamc@238
|
376 repeat (match goal with
|
adamc@238
|
377 | [ |- context[match ?E with NConst _ => _ | Plus _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
378 | Eq _ _ => _ | BConst _ => _ | And _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
379 | If _ _ _ _ => _ | Pair _ _ _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
380 | Fst _ _ _ => _ | Snd _ _ _ => _ end] ] =>
|
adamc@238
|
381 dep_destruct E
|
adamc@238
|
382 | [ |- (if ?E then _ else _) = _ ] => destruct E
|
adamc@238
|
383 | [ |- context[match pairOut ?E with Some _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
384 | None => _ end] ] =>
|
adamc@238
|
385 dep_destruct E
|
adamc@238
|
386 end; crush).
|
adamc@238
|
387
|
adamc@238
|
388 t''.
|
adamc@238
|
389
|
adamc@238
|
390 t''.
|
adamc@238
|
391 Qed.
|
adamc@238
|
392
|
adam@367
|
393 (** We can take the final tactic and move it into the initial part of the proof script, arriving at a nicely automated proof. *)
|
adamc@238
|
394
|
adamc@238
|
395 Reset t.
|
adamc@238
|
396
|
adamc@238
|
397 Theorem cfold_correct : forall t (e : exp t), expDenote e = expDenote (cfold e).
|
adamc@238
|
398 induction e; crush;
|
adamc@238
|
399 repeat (match goal with
|
adamc@238
|
400 | [ |- context[match ?E with NConst _ => _ | Plus _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
401 | Eq _ _ => _ | BConst _ => _ | And _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
402 | If _ _ _ _ => _ | Pair _ _ _ _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
403 | Fst _ _ _ => _ | Snd _ _ _ => _ end] ] =>
|
adamc@238
|
404 dep_destruct E
|
adamc@238
|
405 | [ |- (if ?E then _ else _) = _ ] => destruct E
|
adamc@238
|
406 | [ |- context[match pairOut ?E with Some _ => _
|
adamc@238
|
407 | None => _ end] ] =>
|
adamc@238
|
408 dep_destruct E
|
adamc@238
|
409 end; crush).
|
adamc@238
|
410 Qed.
|
adam@368
|
411 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@238
|
412
|
adam@367
|
413 (** Even after we put together nice automated proofs, we must deal with specification changes that can invalidate them. It is not generally possible to step through single-tactic proofs interactively. There is a command %\index{Vernacular commands!Debug On}%[Debug On] that lets us step through points in tactic execution, but the debugger tends to make counterintuitive choices of which points we would like to stop at, and per-point output is quite verbose, so most Coq users do not find this debugging mode very helpful. How are we to understand what has broken in a script that used to work?
|
adamc@240
|
414
|
adamc@240
|
415 An example helps demonstrate a useful approach. Consider what would have happened in our proof of [reassoc_correct] if we had first added an unfortunate rewriting hint. *)
|
adamc@240
|
416
|
adamc@240
|
417 Reset reassoc_correct.
|
adamc@240
|
418
|
adamc@240
|
419 Theorem confounder : forall e1 e2 e3,
|
adamc@240
|
420 eval e1 * eval e2 * eval e3 = eval e1 * (eval e2 + 1 - 1) * eval e3.
|
adamc@240
|
421 crush.
|
adamc@240
|
422 Qed.
|
adamc@240
|
423
|
adamc@240
|
424 Hint Rewrite confounder : cpdt.
|
adamc@240
|
425
|
adamc@240
|
426 Theorem reassoc_correct : forall e, eval (reassoc e) = eval e.
|
adam@368
|
427 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@240
|
428 induction e; crush;
|
adamc@240
|
429 match goal with
|
adamc@240
|
430 | [ |- context[match ?E with Const _ => _ | Plus _ _ => _ | Mult _ _ => _ end] ] =>
|
adamc@240
|
431 destruct E; crush
|
adamc@240
|
432 end.
|
adamc@240
|
433
|
adamc@240
|
434 (** One subgoal remains:
|
adamc@240
|
435
|
adamc@240
|
436 [[
|
adamc@240
|
437 ============================
|
adamc@240
|
438 eval e1 * (eval e3 + 1 - 1) * eval e4 = eval e1 * eval e2
|
adamc@240
|
439 ]]
|
adamc@240
|
440
|
adam@367
|
441 The poorly chosen rewrite rule fired, changing the goal to a form where another hint no longer applies. Imagine that we are in the middle of a large development with many hints. How would we diagnose the problem? First, we might not be sure which case of the inductive proof has gone wrong. It is useful to separate out our automation procedure and apply it manually. *)
|
adamc@240
|
442
|
adamc@240
|
443 Restart.
|
adamc@240
|
444
|
adamc@240
|
445 Ltac t := crush; match goal with
|
adamc@240
|
446 | [ |- context[match ?E with Const _ => _ | Plus _ _ => _
|
adamc@240
|
447 | Mult _ _ => _ end] ] =>
|
adamc@240
|
448 destruct E; crush
|
adamc@240
|
449 end.
|
adamc@240
|
450
|
adamc@240
|
451 induction e.
|
adamc@240
|
452
|
adamc@240
|
453 (** Since we see the subgoals before any simplification occurs, it is clear that this is the case for constants. [t] makes short work of it. *)
|
adamc@240
|
454
|
adamc@240
|
455 t.
|
adamc@240
|
456
|
adamc@240
|
457 (** The next subgoal, for addition, is also discharged without trouble. *)
|
adamc@240
|
458
|
adamc@240
|
459 t.
|
adamc@240
|
460
|
adamc@240
|
461 (** The final subgoal is for multiplication, and it is here that we get stuck in the proof state summarized above. *)
|
adamc@240
|
462
|
adamc@240
|
463 t.
|
adamc@240
|
464
|
adam@367
|
465 (** What is [t] doing to get us to this point? The %\index{tactics!info}%[info] command can help us answer this kind of question. *)
|
adamc@240
|
466
|
adamc@240
|
467 (** remove printing * *)
|
adamc@240
|
468 Undo.
|
adamc@240
|
469 info t.
|
adam@367
|
470 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adamc@240
|
471 == simpl in *; intuition; subst; autorewrite with cpdt in *;
|
adamc@240
|
472 simpl in *; intuition; subst; autorewrite with cpdt in *;
|
adamc@240
|
473 simpl in *; intuition; subst; destruct (reassoc e2).
|
adamc@240
|
474 simpl in *; intuition.
|
adamc@240
|
475
|
adamc@240
|
476 simpl in *; intuition.
|
adamc@240
|
477
|
adamc@240
|
478 simpl in *; intuition; subst; autorewrite with cpdt in *;
|
adamc@240
|
479 refine (eq_ind_r
|
adamc@240
|
480 (fun n : nat =>
|
adamc@240
|
481 n * (eval e3 + 1 - 1) * eval e4 = eval e1 * eval e2) _ IHe1);
|
adamc@240
|
482 autorewrite with cpdt in *; simpl in *; intuition;
|
adamc@240
|
483 subst; autorewrite with cpdt in *; simpl in *;
|
adamc@240
|
484 intuition; subst.
|
adamc@240
|
485
|
adamc@240
|
486 ]]
|
adamc@240
|
487
|
adamc@240
|
488 A detailed trace of [t]'s execution appears. Since we are using the very general [crush] tactic, many of these steps have no effect and only occur as instances of a more general strategy. We can copy-and-paste the details to see where things go wrong. *)
|
adamc@240
|
489
|
adamc@240
|
490 Undo.
|
adamc@240
|
491
|
adamc@240
|
492 (** We arbitrarily split the script into chunks. The first few seem not to do any harm. *)
|
adamc@240
|
493
|
adamc@240
|
494 simpl in *; intuition; subst; autorewrite with cpdt in *.
|
adamc@240
|
495 simpl in *; intuition; subst; autorewrite with cpdt in *.
|
adamc@240
|
496 simpl in *; intuition; subst; destruct (reassoc e2).
|
adamc@240
|
497 simpl in *; intuition.
|
adamc@240
|
498 simpl in *; intuition.
|
adamc@240
|
499
|
adamc@240
|
500 (** The next step is revealed as the culprit, bringing us to the final unproved subgoal. *)
|
adamc@240
|
501
|
adamc@240
|
502 simpl in *; intuition; subst; autorewrite with cpdt in *.
|
adamc@240
|
503
|
adamc@240
|
504 (** We can split the steps further to assign blame. *)
|
adamc@240
|
505
|
adamc@240
|
506 Undo.
|
adamc@240
|
507
|
adamc@240
|
508 simpl in *.
|
adamc@240
|
509 intuition.
|
adamc@240
|
510 subst.
|
adamc@240
|
511 autorewrite with cpdt in *.
|
adamc@240
|
512
|
adamc@240
|
513 (** It was the final of these four tactics that made the rewrite. We can find out exactly what happened. The [info] command presents hierarchical views of proof steps, and we can zoom down to a lower level of detail by applying [info] to one of the steps that appeared in the original trace. *)
|
adamc@240
|
514
|
adamc@240
|
515 Undo.
|
adamc@240
|
516
|
adamc@240
|
517 info autorewrite with cpdt in *.
|
adam@367
|
518 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adamc@240
|
519 == refine (eq_ind_r (fun n : nat => n = eval e1 * eval e2) _
|
adamc@240
|
520 (confounder (reassoc e1) e3 e4)).
|
adamc@240
|
521 ]]
|
adamc@240
|
522
|
adamc@240
|
523 The way a rewrite is displayed is somewhat baroque, but we can see that theorem [confounder] is the final culprit. At this point, we could remove that hint, prove an alternate version of the key lemma [rewr], or come up with some other remedy. Fixing this kind of problem tends to be relatively easy once the problem is revealed. *)
|
adamc@240
|
524
|
adamc@240
|
525 Abort.
|
adam@368
|
526 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@240
|
527
|
adamc@240
|
528 (** printing * $\times$ *)
|
adamc@240
|
529
|
adamc@241
|
530 (** Sometimes a change to a development has undesirable performance consequences, even if it does not prevent any old proof scripts from completing. If the performance consequences are severe enough, the proof scripts can be considered broken for practical purposes.
|
adamc@241
|
531
|
adamc@241
|
532 Here is one example of a performance surprise. *)
|
adamc@241
|
533
|
adamc@239
|
534 Section slow.
|
adamc@239
|
535 Hint Resolve trans_eq.
|
adamc@239
|
536
|
adamc@241
|
537 (** The central element of the problem is the addition of transitivity as a hint. With transitivity available, it is easy for proof search to wind up exploring exponential search spaces. We also add a few other arbitrary variables and hypotheses, designed to lead to trouble later. *)
|
adamc@241
|
538
|
adamc@239
|
539 Variable A : Set.
|
adamc@239
|
540 Variables P Q R S : A -> A -> Prop.
|
adamc@239
|
541 Variable f : A -> A.
|
adamc@239
|
542
|
adamc@239
|
543 Hypothesis H1 : forall x y, P x y -> Q x y -> R x y -> f x = f y.
|
adamc@239
|
544 Hypothesis H2 : forall x y, S x y -> R x y.
|
adamc@239
|
545
|
adam@367
|
546 (** We prove a simple lemma very quickly, using the %\index{Vernacular commands!Time}%[Time] command to measure exactly how quickly. *)
|
adamc@241
|
547
|
adamc@239
|
548 Lemma slow : forall x y, P x y -> Q x y -> S x y -> f x = f y.
|
adamc@241
|
549 Time eauto 6.
|
adam@367
|
550 (** %\vspace{-.2in}%[[
|
adamc@241
|
551 Finished transaction in 0. secs (0.068004u,0.s)
|
adam@302
|
552 ]]
|
adam@302
|
553 *)
|
adamc@241
|
554
|
adamc@239
|
555 Qed.
|
adamc@239
|
556
|
adamc@241
|
557 (** Now we add a different hypothesis, which is innocent enough; in fact, it is even provable as a theorem. *)
|
adamc@241
|
558
|
adamc@239
|
559 Hypothesis H3 : forall x y, x = y -> f x = f y.
|
adamc@239
|
560
|
adamc@239
|
561 Lemma slow' : forall x y, P x y -> Q x y -> S x y -> f x = f y.
|
adamc@241
|
562 Time eauto 6.
|
adam@367
|
563 (** %\vspace{-.2in}%[[
|
adamc@241
|
564 Finished transaction in 2. secs (1.264079u,0.s)
|
adamc@241
|
565 ]]
|
adamc@241
|
566
|
adamc@241
|
567 Why has the search time gone up so much? The [info] command is not much help, since it only shows the result of search, not all of the paths that turned out to be worthless. *)
|
adamc@241
|
568
|
adam@368
|
569 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@241
|
570 Restart.
|
adamc@241
|
571 info eauto 6.
|
adam@367
|
572 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adamc@241
|
573 == intro x; intro y; intro H; intro H0; intro H4;
|
adamc@241
|
574 simple eapply trans_eq.
|
adamc@241
|
575 simple apply refl_equal.
|
adamc@241
|
576
|
adamc@241
|
577 simple eapply trans_eq.
|
adamc@241
|
578 simple apply refl_equal.
|
adamc@241
|
579
|
adamc@241
|
580 simple eapply trans_eq.
|
adamc@241
|
581 simple apply refl_equal.
|
adamc@241
|
582
|
adamc@241
|
583 simple apply H1.
|
adamc@241
|
584 eexact H.
|
adamc@241
|
585
|
adamc@241
|
586 eexact H0.
|
adamc@241
|
587
|
adamc@241
|
588 simple apply H2; eexact H4.
|
adamc@241
|
589 ]]
|
adamc@241
|
590
|
adam@367
|
591 This output does not tell us why proof search takes so long, but it does provide a clue that would be useful if we had forgotten that we added transitivity as a hint. The [eauto] tactic is applying depth-first search, and the proof script where the real action is ends up buried inside a chain of pointless invocations of transitivity, where each invocation uses reflexivity to discharge one subgoal. Each increment to the depth argument to [eauto] adds another silly use of transitivity. This wasted proof effort only adds linear time overhead, as long as proof search never makes false steps. No false steps were made before we added the new hypothesis, but somehow the addition made possible a new faulty path. To understand which paths we enabled, we can use the %\index{tactics!debug}%[debug] command. *)
|
adamc@241
|
592
|
adamc@241
|
593 Restart.
|
adamc@241
|
594 debug eauto 6.
|
adamc@241
|
595
|
adamc@241
|
596 (** The output is a large proof tree. The beginning of the tree is enough to reveal what is happening:
|
adamc@241
|
597 [[
|
adamc@241
|
598 1 depth=6
|
adamc@241
|
599 1.1 depth=6 intro
|
adamc@241
|
600 1.1.1 depth=6 intro
|
adamc@241
|
601 1.1.1.1 depth=6 intro
|
adamc@241
|
602 1.1.1.1.1 depth=6 intro
|
adamc@241
|
603 1.1.1.1.1.1 depth=6 intro
|
adamc@241
|
604 1.1.1.1.1.1.1 depth=5 apply H3
|
adamc@241
|
605 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1 depth=4 eapply trans_eq
|
adamc@241
|
606 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1 depth=4 apply refl_equal
|
adamc@241
|
607 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1 depth=3 eapply trans_eq
|
adamc@241
|
608 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1 depth=3 apply refl_equal
|
adamc@241
|
609 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1 depth=2 eapply trans_eq
|
adamc@241
|
610 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1 depth=2 apply refl_equal
|
adamc@241
|
611 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1 depth=1 eapply trans_eq
|
adamc@241
|
612 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1 depth=1 apply refl_equal
|
adamc@241
|
613 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1 depth=0 eapply trans_eq
|
adamc@241
|
614 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.2 depth=1 apply sym_eq ; trivial
|
adamc@241
|
615 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.2.1 depth=0 eapply trans_eq
|
adamc@241
|
616 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.3 depth=0 eapply trans_eq
|
adamc@241
|
617 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.2 depth=2 apply sym_eq ; trivial
|
adamc@241
|
618 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.2.1 depth=1 eapply trans_eq
|
adamc@241
|
619 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.2.1.1 depth=1 apply refl_equal
|
adamc@241
|
620 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.2.1.1.1 depth=0 eapply trans_eq
|
adamc@241
|
621 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.2.1.2 depth=1 apply sym_eq ; trivial
|
adamc@241
|
622 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.2.1.2.1 depth=0 eapply trans_eq
|
adamc@241
|
623 1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.2.1.3 depth=0 eapply trans_eq
|
adamc@241
|
624 ]]
|
adamc@241
|
625
|
adam@367
|
626 The first choice [eauto] makes is to apply [H3], since [H3] has the fewest hypotheses of all of the hypotheses and hints that match. However, it turns out that the single hypothesis generated is unprovable. That does not stop [eauto] from trying to prove it with an exponentially sized tree of applications of transitivity, reflexivity, and symmetry of equality. It is the children of the initial [apply H3] that account for all of the noticeable time in proof execution. In a more realistic development, we might use this output of [debug] to realize that adding transitivity as a hint was a bad idea. *)
|
adamc@241
|
627
|
adamc@239
|
628 Qed.
|
adam@368
|
629 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@239
|
630 End slow.
|
adamc@239
|
631
|
adam@367
|
632 (** It is also easy to end up with a proof script that uses too much memory. As tactics run, they avoid generating proof terms, since serious proof search will consider many possible avenues, and we do not want to build proof terms for subproofs that end up unused. Instead, tactic execution maintains %\index{thunks}\textit{%#<i>#thunks#</i>#%}% (suspended computations, represented with closures), such that a tactic's proof-producing thunk is only executed when we run [Qed]. These thunks can use up large amounts of space, such that a proof script exhausts available memory, even when we know that we could have used much less memory by forcing some thunks earlier.
|
adamc@241
|
633
|
adam@367
|
634 The %\index{tactics!abstract}%[abstract] tactical helps us force thunks by proving some subgoals as their own lemmas. For instance, a proof [induction x; crush] can in many cases be made to use significantly less peak memory by changing it to [induction x; abstract crush]. The main limitation of [abstract] is that it can only be applied to subgoals that are proved completely, with no undetermined unification variables remaining. Still, many large automated proofs can realize vast memory savings via [abstract]. *)
|
adamc@241
|
635
|
adamc@238
|
636
|
adamc@235
|
637 (** * Modules *)
|
adamc@235
|
638
|
adam@367
|
639 (** Last chapter's examples of proof by reflection demonstrate opportunities for implementing abstract proof strategies with stronger formal guarantees than can be had with Ltac scripting. Coq's %\textit{%#<i>#module system#</i>#%}% provides another tool for more rigorous development of generic theorems. This feature is inspired by the module systems found in Standard ML%~\cite{modules}% and Objective Caml, and the discussion that follows assumes familiarity with the basics of one of those systems.
|
adamc@242
|
640
|
adam@367
|
641 ML modules facilitate the grouping of %\index{abstract type}%abstract types with operations over those types. Moreover, there is support for %\index{functor}\textit{%#<i>#functors#</i>#%}%, which are functions from modules to modules. A canonical example of a functor is one that builds a data structure implementation from a module that describes a domain of keys and its associated comparison operations.
|
adamc@242
|
642
|
adam@367
|
643 When we add modules to a base language with dependent types, it becomes possible to use modules and functors to formalize kinds of reasoning that are common in algebra. For instance, this module signature captures the essence of the algebraic structure known as a group. A group consists of a carrier set [G], an associative binary operation [f], a left identity element [e] for [f], and an operation [i] that is a left inverse for [f].%\index{Vernacular commands!Module Type}% *)
|
adamc@242
|
644
|
adamc@235
|
645 Module Type GROUP.
|
adamc@235
|
646 Parameter G : Set.
|
adamc@235
|
647 Parameter f : G -> G -> G.
|
adamc@235
|
648 Parameter e : G.
|
adamc@235
|
649 Parameter i : G -> G.
|
adamc@235
|
650
|
adamc@235
|
651 Axiom assoc : forall a b c, f (f a b) c = f a (f b c).
|
adamc@235
|
652 Axiom ident : forall a, f e a = a.
|
adamc@235
|
653 Axiom inverse : forall a, f (i a) a = e.
|
adamc@235
|
654 End GROUP.
|
adamc@235
|
655
|
adam@367
|
656 (** Many useful theorems hold of arbitrary groups. We capture some such theorem statements in another module signature.%\index{Vernacular commands!Declare Module}% *)
|
adamc@242
|
657
|
adamc@235
|
658 Module Type GROUP_THEOREMS.
|
adamc@235
|
659 Declare Module M : GROUP.
|
adamc@235
|
660
|
adamc@235
|
661 Axiom ident' : forall a, M.f a M.e = a.
|
adamc@235
|
662
|
adamc@235
|
663 Axiom inverse' : forall a, M.f a (M.i a) = M.e.
|
adamc@235
|
664
|
adamc@235
|
665 Axiom unique_ident : forall e', (forall a, M.f e' a = a) -> e' = M.e.
|
adamc@235
|
666 End GROUP_THEOREMS.
|
adamc@235
|
667
|
adam@367
|
668 (** We implement generic proofs of these theorems with a functor, whose input is an arbitrary group [M]. The proofs are completely manual, since it would take some effort to build suitable generic automation; rather, these theorems can serve as a basis for an automated procedure for simplifying group expressions, along the lines of the procedure for monoids from the last chapter. We take the proofs from the Wikipedia page on elementary group theory.%\index{Vernacular commands!Module}% *)
|
adamc@242
|
669
|
adamc@239
|
670 Module Group (M : GROUP) : GROUP_THEOREMS with Module M := M.
|
adamc@235
|
671 Module M := M.
|
adamc@235
|
672
|
adamc@235
|
673 Import M.
|
adamc@235
|
674
|
adamc@235
|
675 Theorem inverse' : forall a, f a (i a) = e.
|
adamc@235
|
676 intro.
|
adamc@235
|
677 rewrite <- (ident (f a (i a))).
|
adamc@235
|
678 rewrite <- (inverse (f a (i a))) at 1.
|
adamc@235
|
679 rewrite assoc.
|
adamc@235
|
680 rewrite assoc.
|
adamc@235
|
681 rewrite <- (assoc (i a) a (i a)).
|
adamc@235
|
682 rewrite inverse.
|
adamc@235
|
683 rewrite ident.
|
adamc@235
|
684 apply inverse.
|
adamc@235
|
685 Qed.
|
adamc@235
|
686
|
adamc@235
|
687 Theorem ident' : forall a, f a e = a.
|
adamc@235
|
688 intro.
|
adamc@235
|
689 rewrite <- (inverse a).
|
adamc@235
|
690 rewrite <- assoc.
|
adamc@235
|
691 rewrite inverse'.
|
adamc@235
|
692 apply ident.
|
adamc@235
|
693 Qed.
|
adamc@235
|
694
|
adamc@235
|
695 Theorem unique_ident : forall e', (forall a, M.f e' a = a) -> e' = M.e.
|
adamc@235
|
696 intros.
|
adamc@235
|
697 rewrite <- (H e).
|
adamc@235
|
698 symmetry.
|
adamc@235
|
699 apply ident'.
|
adamc@235
|
700 Qed.
|
adamc@235
|
701 End Group.
|
adamc@239
|
702
|
adamc@242
|
703 (** We can show that the integers with [+] form a group. *)
|
adamc@242
|
704
|
adamc@239
|
705 Require Import ZArith.
|
adamc@239
|
706 Open Scope Z_scope.
|
adamc@239
|
707
|
adamc@239
|
708 Module Int.
|
adamc@239
|
709 Definition G := Z.
|
adamc@239
|
710 Definition f x y := x + y.
|
adamc@239
|
711 Definition e := 0.
|
adamc@239
|
712 Definition i x := -x.
|
adamc@239
|
713
|
adamc@239
|
714 Theorem assoc : forall a b c, f (f a b) c = f a (f b c).
|
adamc@239
|
715 unfold f; crush.
|
adamc@239
|
716 Qed.
|
adamc@239
|
717 Theorem ident : forall a, f e a = a.
|
adamc@239
|
718 unfold f, e; crush.
|
adamc@239
|
719 Qed.
|
adamc@239
|
720 Theorem inverse : forall a, f (i a) a = e.
|
adamc@239
|
721 unfold f, i, e; crush.
|
adamc@239
|
722 Qed.
|
adamc@239
|
723 End Int.
|
adamc@239
|
724
|
adamc@242
|
725 (** Next, we can produce integer-specific versions of the generic group theorems. *)
|
adamc@242
|
726
|
adamc@239
|
727 Module IntTheorems := Group(Int).
|
adamc@239
|
728
|
adamc@239
|
729 Check IntTheorems.unique_ident.
|
adamc@242
|
730 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@242
|
731 IntTheorems.unique_ident
|
adamc@242
|
732 : forall e' : Int.G, (forall a : Int.G, Int.f e' a = a) -> e' = Int.e
|
adam@302
|
733 ]]
|
adam@367
|
734
|
adam@367
|
735 Projections like [Int.G] are known to be definitionally equal to the concrete values we have assigned to them, so the above theorem yields as a trivial corollary the following more natural restatement: *)
|
adamc@239
|
736
|
adamc@239
|
737 Theorem unique_ident : forall e', (forall a, e' + a = a) -> e' = 0.
|
adam@368
|
738 (* begin thide *)
|
adamc@239
|
739 exact IntTheorems.unique_ident.
|
adamc@239
|
740 Qed.
|
adam@368
|
741 (* end thide *)
|
adamc@242
|
742
|
adam@367
|
743 (** As in ML, the module system provides an effective way to structure large developments. Unlike in ML, Coq modules add no expressiveness; we can implement any module as an inhabitant of a dependent record type. It is the second-class nature of modules that makes them easier to use than dependent records in many case. Because modules may only be used in quite restricted ways, it is easier to support convenient module coding through special commands and editing modes, as the above example demonstrates. An isomorphic implementation with records would have suffered from lack of such conveniences as module subtyping and importation of the fields of a module. On the other hand, all module values must be determined statically, so modules may not be computed, e.g., within the defintions of normal functions, based on particular function parameters. *)
|
adamc@243
|
744
|
adamc@243
|
745
|
adamc@243
|
746 (** * Build Processes *)
|
adamc@243
|
747
|
adamc@243
|
748 (** As in software development, large Coq projects are much more manageable when split across multiple files and when decomposed into libraries. Coq and Proof General provide very good support for these activities.
|
adamc@243
|
749
|
adam@367
|
750 Consider a library that we will name [Lib], housed in directory %\texttt{%#<tt>#LIB#</tt>#%}% and split between files %\texttt{%#<tt>#A.v#</tt>#%}%, %\texttt{%#<tt>#B.v#</tt>#%}%, and %\texttt{%#<tt>#C.v#</tt>#%}%. A simple %\index{Makefile}%Makefile will compile the library, relying on the standard Coq tool %\index{coq\_makefile}\texttt{%#<tt>#coq_makefile#</tt>#%}% to do the hard work.
|
adamc@243
|
751
|
adamc@243
|
752 <<
|
adamc@243
|
753 MODULES := A B C
|
adamc@243
|
754 VS := $(MODULES:%=%.v)
|
adamc@243
|
755
|
adamc@243
|
756 .PHONY: coq clean
|
adamc@243
|
757
|
adamc@243
|
758 coq: Makefile.coq
|
adamc@243
|
759 make -f Makefile.coq
|
adamc@243
|
760
|
adamc@243
|
761 Makefile.coq: Makefile $(VS)
|
adamc@243
|
762 coq_makefile -R . Lib $(VS) -o Makefile.coq
|
adamc@243
|
763
|
adamc@243
|
764 clean:: Makefile.coq
|
adamc@243
|
765 make -f Makefile.coq clean
|
adamc@243
|
766 rm -f Makefile.coq
|
adamc@243
|
767 >>
|
adamc@243
|
768
|
adamc@243
|
769 The Makefile begins by defining a variable %\texttt{%#<tt>#VS#</tt>#%}% holding the list of filenames to be included in the project. The primary target is %\texttt{%#<tt>#coq#</tt>#%}%, which depends on the construction of an auxiliary Makefile called %\texttt{%#<tt>#Makefile.coq#</tt>#%}%. Another rule explains how to build that file. We call %\texttt{%#<tt>#coq_makefile#</tt>#%}%, using the %\texttt{%#<tt>#-R#</tt>#%}% flag to specify that files in the current directory should be considered to belong to the library [Lib]. This Makefile will build a compiled version of each module, such that %\texttt{%#<tt>#X.v#</tt>#%}% is compiled into %\texttt{%#<tt>#X.vo#</tt>#%}%.
|
adamc@243
|
770
|
adamc@243
|
771 Now code in %\texttt{%#<tt>#B.v#</tt>#%}% may refer to definitions in %\texttt{%#<tt>#A.v#</tt>#%}% after running
|
adamc@243
|
772 [[
|
adamc@243
|
773 Require Import Lib.A.
|
adam@367
|
774 ]]
|
adam@367
|
775 %\vspace{-.15in}%Library [Lib] is presented as a module, containing a submodule [A], which contains the definitions from %\texttt{%#<tt>#A.v#</tt>#%}%. These are genuine modules in the sense of Coq's module system, and they may be passed to functors and so on.
|
adamc@243
|
776
|
adam@367
|
777 The command [Require Import] is a convenient combination of two more primitive commands. The %\index{Vernacular commands!Require}%[Require] command finds the %\texttt{%#<tt>#.vo#</tt>#%}% file containing the named module, ensuring that the module is loaded into memory. The %\index{Vernacular commands!Import}%[Import] command loads all top-level definitions of the named module into the current namespace, and it may be used with local modules that do not have corresponding %\texttt{%#<tt>#.vo#</tt>#%}% files. Another command, %\index{Vernacular commands!Load}%[Load], is for inserting the contents of a named file verbatim. It is generally better to use the module-based commands, since they avoid rerunning proof scripts, and they facilitate reorganization of directory structure without the need to change code.
|
adamc@243
|
778
|
adamc@243
|
779 Now we would like to use our library from a different development, called [Client] and found in directory %\texttt{%#<tt>#CLIENT#</tt>#%}%, which has its own Makefile.
|
adamc@243
|
780
|
adamc@243
|
781 <<
|
adamc@243
|
782 MODULES := D E
|
adamc@243
|
783 VS := $(MODULES:%=%.v)
|
adamc@243
|
784
|
adamc@243
|
785 .PHONY: coq clean
|
adamc@243
|
786
|
adamc@243
|
787 coq: Makefile.coq
|
adamc@243
|
788 make -f Makefile.coq
|
adamc@243
|
789
|
adamc@243
|
790 Makefile.coq: Makefile $(VS)
|
adamc@243
|
791 coq_makefile -R LIB Lib -R . Client $(VS) -o Makefile.coq
|
adamc@243
|
792
|
adamc@243
|
793 clean:: Makefile.coq
|
adamc@243
|
794 make -f Makefile.coq clean
|
adamc@243
|
795 rm -f Makefile.coq
|
adamc@243
|
796 >>
|
adamc@243
|
797
|
adamc@243
|
798 We change the %\texttt{%#<tt>#coq_makefile#</tt>#%}% call to indicate where the library [Lib] is found. Now %\texttt{%#<tt>#D.v#</tt>#%}% and %\texttt{%#<tt>#E.v#</tt>#%}% can refer to definitions from [Lib] module [A] after running
|
adamc@243
|
799 [[
|
adamc@243
|
800 Require Import Lib.A.
|
adamc@243
|
801 ]]
|
adam@367
|
802 %\vspace{-.15in}\noindent{}%and %\texttt{%#<tt>#E.v#</tt>#%}% can refer to definitions from %\texttt{%#<tt>#D.v#</tt>#%}% by running
|
adamc@243
|
803 [[
|
adamc@243
|
804 Require Import Client.D.
|
adamc@243
|
805 ]]
|
adam@367
|
806 %\vspace{-.15in}%It can be useful to split a library into several files, but it is also inconvenient for client code to import library modules individually. We can get the best of both worlds by, for example, adding an extra source file %\texttt{%#<tt>#Lib.v#</tt>#%}% to [Lib]'s directory and Makefile, where that file contains just this line:%\index{Vernacular commands!Require Export}%
|
adamc@243
|
807 [[
|
adamc@243
|
808 Require Export Lib.A Lib.B Lib.C.
|
adamc@243
|
809 ]]
|
adam@367
|
810 %\vspace{-.15in}%Now client code can import all definitions from all of [Lib]'s modules simply by running
|
adamc@243
|
811 [[
|
adamc@243
|
812 Require Import Lib.
|
adamc@243
|
813 ]]
|
adam@367
|
814 %\vspace{-.15in}%The two Makefiles above share a lot of code, so, in practice, it is useful to define a common Makefile that is included by multiple library-specific Makefiles.
|
adamc@243
|
815
|
adamc@243
|
816 %\medskip%
|
adamc@243
|
817
|
adamc@243
|
818 The remaining ingredient is the proper way of editing library code files in Proof General. Recall this snippet of %\texttt{%#<tt>#.emacs#</tt>#%}% code from Chapter 2, which tells Proof General where to find the library associated with this book.
|
adamc@243
|
819
|
adamc@243
|
820 <<
|
adamc@243
|
821 (custom-set-variables
|
adamc@243
|
822 ...
|
adamc@243
|
823 '(coq-prog-args '("-I" "/path/to/cpdt/src"))
|
adamc@243
|
824 ...
|
adamc@243
|
825 )
|
adamc@243
|
826 >>
|
adamc@243
|
827
|
adamc@243
|
828 To do interactive editing of our current example, we just need to change the flags to point to the right places.
|
adamc@243
|
829
|
adamc@243
|
830 <<
|
adamc@243
|
831 (custom-set-variables
|
adamc@243
|
832 ...
|
adamc@243
|
833 ; '(coq-prog-args '("-I" "/path/to/cpdt/src"))
|
adamc@243
|
834 '(coq-prog-args '("-R" "LIB" "Lib" "-R" "CLIENT" "Client"))
|
adamc@243
|
835 ...
|
adamc@243
|
836 )
|
adamc@243
|
837 >>
|
adamc@243
|
838
|
adamc@243
|
839 When working on multiple projects, it is useful to leave multiple versions of this setting in your %\texttt{%#<tt>#.emacs#</tt>#%}% file, commenting out all but one of them at any moment in time. To switch between projects, change the commenting structure and restart Emacs. *)
|