Mercurial > cpdt > repo
comparison src/InductiveTypes.v @ 208:b9e9ff52913c
Port InductiveTypes
author | Adam Chlipala <adamc@hcoop.net> |
---|---|
date | Mon, 09 Nov 2009 11:09:50 -0500 |
parents | f05514cc6c0d |
children | b149a07b9b5b |
comparison
equal
deleted
inserted
replaced
207:a7be5d9a2fd4 | 208:b9e9ff52913c |
---|---|
33 | tt. | 33 | tt. |
34 | 34 |
35 (** This vernacular command defines a new inductive type [unit] whose only value is [tt], as we can see by checking the types of the two identifiers: *) | 35 (** This vernacular command defines a new inductive type [unit] whose only value is [tt], as we can see by checking the types of the two identifiers: *) |
36 | 36 |
37 Check unit. | 37 Check unit. |
38 (** [[ | 38 (** [unit : Set] *) |
39 | 39 |
40 unit : Set | |
41 ]] *) | |
42 Check tt. | 40 Check tt. |
43 (** [[ | 41 (** [tt : unit] *) |
44 | |
45 tt : unit | |
46 ]] *) | |
47 | 42 |
48 (** We can prove that [unit] is a genuine singleton type. *) | 43 (** We can prove that [unit] is a genuine singleton type. *) |
49 | 44 |
50 Theorem unit_singleton : forall x : unit, x = tt. | 45 Theorem unit_singleton : forall x : unit, x = tt. |
46 | |
51 (** The important thing about an inductive type is, unsurprisingly, that you can do induction over its values, and induction is the key to proving this theorem. We ask to proceed by induction on the variable [x]. *) | 47 (** The important thing about an inductive type is, unsurprisingly, that you can do induction over its values, and induction is the key to proving this theorem. We ask to proceed by induction on the variable [x]. *) |
48 | |
52 (* begin thide *) | 49 (* begin thide *) |
53 induction x. | 50 induction x. |
54 (** The goal changes to: [[ | 51 |
55 | 52 (** The goal changes to: |
53 [[ | |
56 tt = tt | 54 tt = tt |
57 ]] *) | 55 ]] *) |
56 | |
58 (** ...which we can discharge trivially. *) | 57 (** ...which we can discharge trivially. *) |
58 | |
59 reflexivity. | 59 reflexivity. |
60 Qed. | 60 Qed. |
61 (* end thide *) | 61 (* end thide *) |
62 | 62 |
63 (** It seems kind of odd to write a proof by induction with no inductive hypotheses. We could have arrived at the same result by beginning the proof with: [[ | 63 (** It seems kind of odd to write a proof by induction with no inductive hypotheses. We could have arrived at the same result by beginning the proof with: [[ |
64 | 64 |
65 destruct x. | 65 destruct x. |
66 | 66 |
67 ]] | 67 ]] |
68 | 68 |
69 ...which corresponds to "proof by case analysis" in classical math. For non-recursive inductive types, the two tactics will always have identical behavior. Often case analysis is sufficient, even in proofs about recursive types, and it is nice to avoid introducing unneeded induction hypotheses. | 69 %\noindent%...which corresponds to "proof by case analysis" in classical math. For non-recursive inductive types, the two tactics will always have identical behavior. Often case analysis is sufficient, even in proofs about recursive types, and it is nice to avoid introducing unneeded induction hypotheses. |
70 | 70 |
71 What exactly %\textit{%#<i>#is#</i>#%}% the induction principle for [unit]? We can ask Coq: *) | 71 What exactly %\textit{%#<i>#is#</i>#%}% the induction principle for [unit]? We can ask Coq: *) |
72 | 72 |
73 Check unit_ind. | 73 Check unit_ind. |
74 (** [[ | 74 (** [unit_ind : forall P : unit -> Prop, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u] *) |
75 | 75 |
76 unit_ind : forall P : unit -> Prop, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u | 76 (** Every [Inductive] command defining a type [T] also defines an induction principle named [T_ind]. Coq follows the Curry-Howard correspondence and includes the ingredients of programming and proving in the same single syntactic class. Thus, our type, operations over it, and principles for reasoning about it all live in the same language and are described by the same type system. The key to telling what is a program and what is a proof lies in the distinction between the type [Prop], which appears in our induction principle; and the type [Set], which we have seen a few times already. |
77 ]] | |
78 | |
79 Every [Inductive] command defining a type [T] also defines an induction principle named [T_ind]. Coq follows the Curry-Howard correspondence and includes the ingredients of programming and proving in the same single syntactic class. Thus, our type, operations over it, and principles for reasoning about it all live in the same language and are described by the same type system. The key to telling what is a program and what is a proof lies in the distinction between the type [Prop], which appears in our induction principle; and the type [Set], which we have seen a few times already. | |
80 | 77 |
81 The convention goes like this: [Set] is the type of normal types, and the values of such types are programs. [Prop] is the type of logical propositions, and the values of such types are proofs. Thus, an induction principle has a type that shows us that it is a function for building proofs. | 78 The convention goes like this: [Set] is the type of normal types, and the values of such types are programs. [Prop] is the type of logical propositions, and the values of such types are proofs. Thus, an induction principle has a type that shows us that it is a function for building proofs. |
82 | 79 |
83 Specifically, [unit_ind] quantifies over a predicate [P] over [unit] values. If we can present a proof that [P] holds of [tt], then we are rewarded with a proof that [P] holds for any value [u] of type [unit]. In our last proof, the predicate was [(fun u : unit => u = tt)]. | 80 Specifically, [unit_ind] quantifies over a predicate [P] over [unit] values. If we can present a proof that [P] holds of [tt], then we are rewarded with a proof that [P] holds for any value [u] of type [unit]. In our last proof, the predicate was [(fun u : unit => u = tt)]. |
84 | 81 |
99 (** Because [Empty_set] has no elements, the fact of having an element of this type implies anything. We use [destruct 1] instead of [destruct x] in the proof because unused quantified variables are relegated to being referred to by number. (There is a good reason for this, related to the unity of quantifiers and implication. An implication is just a quantification over a proof, where the quantified variable is never used. It generally makes more sense to refer to implication hypotheses by number than by name, and Coq treats our quantifier over an unused variable as an implication in determining the proper behavior.) | 96 (** Because [Empty_set] has no elements, the fact of having an element of this type implies anything. We use [destruct 1] instead of [destruct x] in the proof because unused quantified variables are relegated to being referred to by number. (There is a good reason for this, related to the unity of quantifiers and implication. An implication is just a quantification over a proof, where the quantified variable is never used. It generally makes more sense to refer to implication hypotheses by number than by name, and Coq treats our quantifier over an unused variable as an implication in determining the proper behavior.) |
100 | 97 |
101 We can see the induction principle that made this proof so easy: *) | 98 We can see the induction principle that made this proof so easy: *) |
102 | 99 |
103 Check Empty_set_ind. | 100 Check Empty_set_ind. |
104 (** [[ | 101 (** [Empty_set_ind : forall (P : Empty_set -> Prop) (e : Empty_set), P e] *) |
105 | 102 |
106 Empty_set_ind : forall (P : Empty_set -> Prop) (e : Empty_set), P e | 103 (** In other words, any predicate over values from the empty set holds vacuously of every such element. In the last proof, we chose the predicate [(fun _ : Empty_set => 2 + 2 = 5)]. |
107 ]] | |
108 | |
109 In other words, any predicate over values from the empty set holds vacuously of every such element. In the last proof, we chose the predicate [(fun _ : Empty_set => 2 + 2 = 5)]. | |
110 | 104 |
111 We can also apply this get-out-of-jail-free card programmatically. Here is a lazy way of converting values of [Empty_set] to values of [unit]: *) | 105 We can also apply this get-out-of-jail-free card programmatically. Here is a lazy way of converting values of [Empty_set] to values of [unit]: *) |
112 | 106 |
113 Definition e2u (e : Empty_set) : unit := match e with end. | 107 Definition e2u (e : Empty_set) : unit := match e with end. |
114 | 108 |
139 | 133 |
140 Theorem not_inverse : forall b : bool, not (not b) = b. | 134 Theorem not_inverse : forall b : bool, not (not b) = b. |
141 (* begin thide *) | 135 (* begin thide *) |
142 destruct b. | 136 destruct b. |
143 | 137 |
144 (** After we case analyze on [b], we are left with one subgoal for each constructor of [bool]. | 138 (** After we case-analyze on [b], we are left with one subgoal for each constructor of [bool]. |
145 | 139 |
146 [[ | 140 [[ |
147 | |
148 2 subgoals | 141 2 subgoals |
149 | 142 |
150 ============================ | 143 ============================ |
151 not (not true) = true | 144 not (not true) = true |
152 ]] | 145 ]] |
153 | 146 |
154 [[ | 147 [[ |
155 subgoal 2 is: | 148 subgoal 2 is: |
156 not (not false) = false | 149 not (not false) = false |
150 | |
157 ]] | 151 ]] |
158 | 152 |
159 The first subgoal follows by Coq's rules of computation, so we can dispatch it easily: *) | 153 The first subgoal follows by Coq's rules of computation, so we can dispatch it easily: *) |
160 | 154 |
161 reflexivity. | 155 reflexivity. |
178 (** [discriminate] is used to prove that two values of an inductive type are not equal, whenever the values are formed with different constructors. In this case, the different constructors are [true] and [false]. | 172 (** [discriminate] is used to prove that two values of an inductive type are not equal, whenever the values are formed with different constructors. In this case, the different constructors are [true] and [false]. |
179 | 173 |
180 At this point, it is probably not hard to guess what the underlying induction principle for [bool] is. *) | 174 At this point, it is probably not hard to guess what the underlying induction principle for [bool] is. *) |
181 | 175 |
182 Check bool_ind. | 176 Check bool_ind. |
183 (** [[ | 177 (** [bool_ind : forall P : bool -> Prop, P true -> P false -> forall b : bool, P b] *) |
184 | |
185 bool_ind : forall P : bool -> Prop, P true -> P false -> forall b : bool, P b | |
186 ]] *) | |
187 | 178 |
188 | 179 |
189 (** * Simple Recursive Types *) | 180 (** * Simple Recursive Types *) |
190 | 181 |
191 (** The natural numbers are the simplest common example of an inductive type that actually deserves the name. *) | 182 (** The natural numbers are the simplest common example of an inductive type that actually deserves the name. *) |
218 Qed. | 209 Qed. |
219 (* end thide *) | 210 (* end thide *) |
220 | 211 |
221 (** We can also now get into genuine inductive theorems. First, we will need a recursive function, to make things interesting. *) | 212 (** We can also now get into genuine inductive theorems. First, we will need a recursive function, to make things interesting. *) |
222 | 213 |
223 Fixpoint plus (n m : nat) {struct n} : nat := | 214 Fixpoint plus (n m : nat) : nat := |
224 match n with | 215 match n with |
225 | O => m | 216 | O => m |
226 | S n' => S (plus n' m) | 217 | S n' => S (plus n' m) |
227 end. | 218 end. |
228 | 219 |
229 (** Recall that [Fixpoint] is Coq's mechanism for recursive function definitions, and that the [{struct n}] annotation is noting which function argument decreases structurally at recursive calls. | 220 (** Recall that [Fixpoint] is Coq's mechanism for recursive function definitions. Some theorems about [plus] can be proved without induction. *) |
230 | |
231 Some theorems about [plus] can be proved without induction. *) | |
232 | 221 |
233 Theorem O_plus_n : forall n : nat, plus O n = n. | 222 Theorem O_plus_n : forall n : nat, plus O n = n. |
234 (* begin thide *) | 223 (* begin thide *) |
235 intro; reflexivity. | 224 intro; reflexivity. |
236 Qed. | 225 Qed. |
237 (* end thide *) | 226 (* end thide *) |
238 | 227 |
239 (** Coq's computation rules automatically simplify the application of [plus]. If we just reverse the order of the arguments, though, this no longer works, and we need induction. *) | 228 (** Coq's computation rules automatically simplify the application of [plus], because unfolding the definition of [plus] gives us a [match] expression where the branch to be taken is obvious from syntax alone. If we just reverse the order of the arguments, though, this no longer works, and we need induction. *) |
240 | 229 |
241 Theorem n_plus_O : forall n : nat, plus n O = n. | 230 Theorem n_plus_O : forall n : nat, plus n O = n. |
242 (* begin thide *) | 231 (* begin thide *) |
243 induction n. | 232 induction n. |
244 | 233 |
247 reflexivity. | 236 reflexivity. |
248 | 237 |
249 (** Our second subgoal is more work and also demonstrates our first inductive hypothesis. | 238 (** Our second subgoal is more work and also demonstrates our first inductive hypothesis. |
250 | 239 |
251 [[ | 240 [[ |
252 | |
253 n : nat | 241 n : nat |
254 IHn : plus n O = n | 242 IHn : plus n O = n |
255 ============================ | 243 ============================ |
256 plus (S n) O = S n | 244 plus (S n) O = S n |
245 | |
257 ]] | 246 ]] |
258 | 247 |
259 We can start out by using computation to simplify the goal as far as we can. *) | 248 We can start out by using computation to simplify the goal as far as we can. *) |
260 | 249 |
261 simpl. | 250 simpl. |
276 (* end thide *) | 265 (* end thide *) |
277 | 266 |
278 (** We can check out the induction principle at work here: *) | 267 (** We can check out the induction principle at work here: *) |
279 | 268 |
280 Check nat_ind. | 269 Check nat_ind. |
281 (** [[ | 270 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
282 | 271 nat_ind : forall P : nat -> Prop, |
283 nat_ind : forall P : nat -> Prop, | 272 P O -> (forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) -> forall n : nat, P n |
284 P O -> (forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) -> forall n : nat, P n | 273 |
285 ]] | 274 ]] |
286 | 275 |
287 Each of the two cases of our last proof came from the type of one of the arguments to [nat_ind]. We chose [P] to be [(fun n : nat => plus n O = n)]. The first proof case corresponded to [P O], and the second case to [(forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n))]. The free variable [n] and inductive hypothesis [IHn] came from the argument types given here. | 276 Each of the two cases of our last proof came from the type of one of the arguments to [nat_ind]. We chose [P] to be [(fun n : nat => plus n O = n)]. The first proof case corresponded to [P O] and the second case to [(forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n))]. The free variable [n] and inductive hypothesis [IHn] came from the argument types given here. |
288 | 277 |
289 Since [nat] has a constructor that takes an argument, we may sometimes need to know that that constructor is injective. *) | 278 Since [nat] has a constructor that takes an argument, we may sometimes need to know that that constructor is injective. *) |
290 | 279 |
291 Theorem S_inj : forall n m : nat, S n = S m -> n = m. | 280 Theorem S_inj : forall n m : nat, S n = S m -> n = m. |
292 (* begin thide *) | 281 (* begin thide *) |
312 match ls with | 301 match ls with |
313 | NNil => O | 302 | NNil => O |
314 | NCons _ ls' => S (nlength ls') | 303 | NCons _ ls' => S (nlength ls') |
315 end. | 304 end. |
316 | 305 |
317 Fixpoint napp (ls1 ls2 : nat_list) {struct ls1} : nat_list := | 306 Fixpoint napp (ls1 ls2 : nat_list) : nat_list := |
318 match ls1 with | 307 match ls1 with |
319 | NNil => ls2 | 308 | NNil => ls2 |
320 | NCons n ls1' => NCons n (napp ls1' ls2) | 309 | NCons n ls1' => NCons n (napp ls1' ls2) |
321 end. | 310 end. |
322 | 311 |
328 induction ls1; crush. | 317 induction ls1; crush. |
329 Qed. | 318 Qed. |
330 (* end thide *) | 319 (* end thide *) |
331 | 320 |
332 Check nat_list_ind. | 321 Check nat_list_ind. |
333 (** [[ | 322 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
334 | 323 nat_list_ind |
335 nat_list_ind | |
336 : forall P : nat_list -> Prop, | 324 : forall P : nat_list -> Prop, |
337 P NNil -> | 325 P NNil -> |
338 (forall (n : nat) (n0 : nat_list), P n0 -> P (NCons n n0)) -> | 326 (forall (n : nat) (n0 : nat_list), P n0 -> P (NCons n n0)) -> |
339 forall n : nat_list, P n | 327 forall n : nat_list, P n |
340 ]] | 328 ]] |
351 match tr with | 339 match tr with |
352 | NLeaf => S O | 340 | NLeaf => S O |
353 | NNode tr1 _ tr2 => plus (nsize tr1) (nsize tr2) | 341 | NNode tr1 _ tr2 => plus (nsize tr1) (nsize tr2) |
354 end. | 342 end. |
355 | 343 |
356 Fixpoint nsplice (tr1 tr2 : nat_btree) {struct tr1} : nat_btree := | 344 Fixpoint nsplice (tr1 tr2 : nat_btree) : nat_btree := |
357 match tr1 with | 345 match tr1 with |
358 | NLeaf => NNode tr2 O NLeaf | 346 | NLeaf => NNode tr2 O NLeaf |
359 | NNode tr1' n tr2' => NNode (nsplice tr1' tr2) n tr2' | 347 | NNode tr1' n tr2' => NNode (nsplice tr1' tr2) n tr2' |
360 end. | 348 end. |
361 | 349 |
373 induction tr1; crush. | 361 induction tr1; crush. |
374 Qed. | 362 Qed. |
375 (* end thide *) | 363 (* end thide *) |
376 | 364 |
377 Check nat_btree_ind. | 365 Check nat_btree_ind. |
378 (** [[ | 366 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
379 | 367 nat_btree_ind |
380 nat_btree_ind | |
381 : forall P : nat_btree -> Prop, | 368 : forall P : nat_btree -> Prop, |
382 P NLeaf -> | 369 P NLeaf -> |
383 (forall n : nat_btree, | 370 (forall n : nat_btree, |
384 P n -> forall (n0 : nat) (n1 : nat_btree), P n1 -> P (NNode n n0 n1)) -> | 371 P n -> forall (n0 : nat) (n1 : nat_btree), P n1 -> P (NNode n n0 n1)) -> |
385 forall n : nat_btree, P n | 372 forall n : nat_btree, P n |
398 match ls with | 385 match ls with |
399 | Nil => O | 386 | Nil => O |
400 | Cons _ ls' => S (length ls') | 387 | Cons _ ls' => S (length ls') |
401 end. | 388 end. |
402 | 389 |
403 Fixpoint app T (ls1 ls2 : list T) {struct ls1} : list T := | 390 Fixpoint app T (ls1 ls2 : list T) : list T := |
404 match ls1 with | 391 match ls1 with |
405 | Nil => ls2 | 392 | Nil => ls2 |
406 | Cons x ls1' => Cons x (app ls1' ls2) | 393 | Cons x ls1' => Cons x (app ls1' ls2) |
407 end. | 394 end. |
408 | 395 |
430 match ls with | 417 match ls with |
431 | Nil => O | 418 | Nil => O |
432 | Cons _ ls' => S (length ls') | 419 | Cons _ ls' => S (length ls') |
433 end. | 420 end. |
434 | 421 |
435 Fixpoint app (ls1 ls2 : list) {struct ls1} : list := | 422 Fixpoint app (ls1 ls2 : list) : list := |
436 match ls1 with | 423 match ls1 with |
437 | Nil => ls2 | 424 | Nil => ls2 |
438 | Cons x ls1' => Cons x (app ls1' ls2) | 425 | Cons x ls1' => Cons x (app ls1' ls2) |
439 end. | 426 end. |
440 | 427 |
451 (* end hide *) | 438 (* end hide *) |
452 | 439 |
453 (** After we end the section, the [Variable]s we used are added as extra function parameters for each defined identifier, as needed. *) | 440 (** After we end the section, the [Variable]s we used are added as extra function parameters for each defined identifier, as needed. *) |
454 | 441 |
455 Print list. | 442 Print list. |
456 (** [[ | 443 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
457 | 444 Inductive list (T : Set) : Set := |
458 | |
459 Inductive list (T : Set) : Set := | |
460 Nil : list T | Cons : T -> list T -> list Tlist | 445 Nil : list T | Cons : T -> list T -> list Tlist |
446 | |
461 ]] | 447 ]] |
462 | 448 |
463 The final definition is the same as what we wrote manually before. The other elements of the section are altered similarly, turning out exactly as they were before, though we managed to write their definitions more succinctly. *) | 449 The final definition is the same as what we wrote manually before. The other elements of the section are altered similarly, turning out exactly as they were before, though we managed to write their definitions more succinctly. *) |
464 | 450 |
465 Check length. | 451 Check length. |
466 (** [[ | 452 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
467 | 453 length |
468 length | |
469 : forall T : Set, list T -> nat | 454 : forall T : Set, list T -> nat |
470 ]] | 455 ]] |
471 | 456 |
472 The parameter [T] is treated as a new argument to the induction principle, too. *) | 457 The parameter [T] is treated as a new argument to the induction principle, too. *) |
473 | 458 |
474 Check list_ind. | 459 Check list_ind. |
475 (** [[ | 460 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
476 | 461 list_ind |
477 list_ind | |
478 : forall (T : Set) (P : list T -> Prop), | 462 : forall (T : Set) (P : list T -> Prop), |
479 P (Nil T) -> | 463 P (Nil T) -> |
480 (forall (t : T) (l : list T), P l -> P (Cons t l)) -> | 464 (forall (t : T) (l : list T), P l -> P (Cons t l)) -> |
481 forall l : list T, P l | 465 forall l : list T, P l |
482 ]] | 466 ]] |
504 with olength (ol : odd_list) : nat := | 488 with olength (ol : odd_list) : nat := |
505 match ol with | 489 match ol with |
506 | OCons _ el => S (elength el) | 490 | OCons _ el => S (elength el) |
507 end. | 491 end. |
508 | 492 |
509 Fixpoint eapp (el1 el2 : even_list) {struct el1} : even_list := | 493 Fixpoint eapp (el1 el2 : even_list) : even_list := |
510 match el1 with | 494 match el1 with |
511 | ENil => el2 | 495 | ENil => el2 |
512 | ECons n ol => ECons n (oapp ol el2) | 496 | ECons n ol => ECons n (oapp ol el2) |
513 end | 497 end |
514 | 498 |
515 with oapp (ol : odd_list) (el : even_list) {struct ol} : odd_list := | 499 with oapp (ol : odd_list) (el : even_list) : odd_list := |
516 match ol with | 500 match ol with |
517 | OCons n el' => OCons n (eapp el' el) | 501 | OCons n el' => OCons n (eapp el' el) |
518 end. | 502 end. |
519 | 503 |
520 (** Everything is going roughly the same as in past examples, until we try to prove a theorem similar to those that came before. *) | 504 (** Everything is going roughly the same as in past examples, until we try to prove a theorem similar to those that came before. *) |
535 | 519 |
536 We have no induction hypothesis, so we cannot prove this goal without starting another induction, which would reach a similar point, sending us into a futile infinite chain of inductions. The problem is that Coq's generation of [T_ind] principles is incomplete. We only get non-mutual induction principles generated by default. *) | 520 We have no induction hypothesis, so we cannot prove this goal without starting another induction, which would reach a similar point, sending us into a futile infinite chain of inductions. The problem is that Coq's generation of [T_ind] principles is incomplete. We only get non-mutual induction principles generated by default. *) |
537 | 521 |
538 Abort. | 522 Abort. |
539 Check even_list_ind. | 523 Check even_list_ind. |
540 (** [[ | 524 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
541 | 525 even_list_ind |
542 even_list_ind | |
543 : forall P : even_list -> Prop, | 526 : forall P : even_list -> Prop, |
544 P ENil -> | 527 P ENil -> |
545 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P (ECons n o)) -> | 528 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P (ECons n o)) -> |
546 forall e : even_list, P e | 529 forall e : even_list, P e |
530 | |
547 ]] | 531 ]] |
548 | 532 |
549 We see that no inductive hypotheses are included anywhere in the type. To get them, we must ask for mutual principles as we need them, using the [Scheme] command. *) | 533 We see that no inductive hypotheses are included anywhere in the type. To get them, we must ask for mutual principles as we need them, using the [Scheme] command. *) |
550 | 534 |
551 Scheme even_list_mut := Induction for even_list Sort Prop | 535 Scheme even_list_mut := Induction for even_list Sort Prop |
552 with odd_list_mut := Induction for odd_list Sort Prop. | 536 with odd_list_mut := Induction for odd_list Sort Prop. |
553 | 537 |
554 Check even_list_mut. | 538 Check even_list_mut. |
555 (** [[ | 539 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
556 | 540 even_list_mut |
557 even_list_mut | |
558 : forall (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop), | 541 : forall (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop), |
559 P ENil -> | 542 P ENil -> |
560 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) -> | 543 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) -> |
561 (forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) -> | 544 (forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) -> |
562 forall e : even_list, P e | 545 forall e : even_list, P e |
546 | |
563 ]] | 547 ]] |
564 | 548 |
565 This is the principle we wanted in the first place. There is one more wrinkle left in using it: the [induction] tactic will not apply it for us automatically. It will be helpful to look at how to prove one of our past examples without using [induction], so that we can then generalize the technique to mutual inductive types. *) | 549 This is the principle we wanted in the first place. There is one more wrinkle left in using it: the [induction] tactic will not apply it for us automatically. It will be helpful to look at how to prove one of our past examples without using [induction], so that we can then generalize the technique to mutual inductive types. *) |
566 | 550 |
567 Theorem n_plus_O' : forall n : nat, plus n O = n. | 551 Theorem n_plus_O' : forall n : nat, plus n O = n. |
626 (* end thide *) | 610 (* end thide *) |
627 | 611 |
628 (** We can take a look at the induction principle behind this proof. *) | 612 (** We can take a look at the induction principle behind this proof. *) |
629 | 613 |
630 Check formula_ind. | 614 Check formula_ind. |
631 (** [[ | 615 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
632 | 616 formula_ind |
633 formula_ind | |
634 : forall P : formula -> Prop, | 617 : forall P : formula -> Prop, |
635 (forall n n0 : nat, P (Eq n n0)) -> | 618 (forall n n0 : nat, P (Eq n n0)) -> |
636 (forall f0 : formula, | 619 (forall f0 : formula, |
637 P f0 -> forall f1 : formula, P f1 -> P (And f0 f1)) -> | 620 P f0 -> forall f1 : formula, P f1 -> P (And f0 f1)) -> |
638 (forall f1 : nat -> formula, | 621 (forall f1 : nat -> formula, |
639 (forall n : nat, P (f1 n)) -> P (Forall f1)) -> | 622 (forall n : nat, P (f1 n)) -> P (Forall f1)) -> |
640 forall f2 : formula, P f2 | 623 forall f2 : formula, P f2 |
641 ]] *) | 624 |
642 | 625 ]] |
643 (** Focusing on the [Forall] case, which comes third, we see that we are allowed to assume that the theorem holds %\textit{%#<i>#for any application of the argument function [f1]#</i>#%}%. That is, Coq induction principles do not follow a simple rule that the textual representations of induction variables must get shorter in appeals to induction hypotheses. Luckily for us, the people behind the metatheory of Coq have verified that this flexibility does not introduce unsoundness. | 626 |
627 Focusing on the [Forall] case, which comes third, we see that we are allowed to assume that the theorem holds %\textit{%#<i>#for any application of the argument function [f1]#</i>#%}%. That is, Coq induction principles do not follow a simple rule that the textual representations of induction variables must get shorter in appeals to induction hypotheses. Luckily for us, the people behind the metatheory of Coq have verified that this flexibility does not introduce unsoundness. | |
644 | 628 |
645 %\medskip% | 629 %\medskip% |
646 | 630 |
647 Up to this point, we have seen how to encode in Coq more and more of what is possible with algebraic datatypes in Haskell and ML. This may have given the inaccurate impression that inductive types are a strict extension of algebraic datatypes. In fact, Coq must rule out some types allowed by Haskell and ML, for reasons of soundness. Reflexive types provide our first good example of such a case. | 631 Up to this point, we have seen how to encode in Coq more and more of what is possible with algebraic datatypes in Haskell and ML. This may have given the inaccurate impression that inductive types are a strict extension of algebraic datatypes. In fact, Coq must rule out some types allowed by Haskell and ML, for reasons of soundness. Reflexive types provide our first good example of such a case. |
648 | 632 |
649 Given our last example of an inductive type, many readers are probably eager to try encoding the syntax of lambda calculus. Indeed, the function-based representation technique that we just used, called %\textit{%#<i>#higher-order abstract syntax (HOAS)#</i>#%}%, is the representation of choice for lambda calculi in Twelf and in many applications implemented in Haskell and ML. Let us try to import that choice to Coq: *) | 633 Given our last example of an inductive type, many readers are probably eager to try encoding the syntax of lambda calculus. Indeed, the function-based representation technique that we just used, called %\textit{%#<i>#higher-order abstract syntax (HOAS)#</i>#%}%, is the representation of choice for lambda calculi in Twelf and in many applications implemented in Haskell and ML. Let us try to import that choice to Coq: *) |
650 | 634 |
651 (** [[ | 635 (** [[ |
652 | |
653 Inductive term : Set := | 636 Inductive term : Set := |
654 | App : term -> term -> term | 637 | App : term -> term -> term |
655 | Abs : (term -> term) -> term. | 638 | Abs : (term -> term) -> term. |
656 | 639 |
657 [[ | |
658 Error: Non strictly positive occurrence of "term" in "(term -> term) -> term" | 640 Error: Non strictly positive occurrence of "term" in "(term -> term) -> term" |
641 | |
659 ]] | 642 ]] |
660 | 643 |
661 We have run afoul of the %\textit{%#<i>#strict positivity requirement#</i>#%}% for inductive definitions, which says that the type being defined may not occur to the left of an arrow in the type of a constructor argument. It is important that the type of a constructor is viewed in terms of a series of arguments and a result, since obviously we need recursive occurrences to the lefts of the outermost arrows if we are to have recursive occurrences at all. | 644 We have run afoul of the %\textit{%#<i>#strict positivity requirement#</i>#%}% for inductive definitions, which says that the type being defined may not occur to the left of an arrow in the type of a constructor argument. It is important that the type of a constructor is viewed in terms of a series of arguments and a result, since obviously we need recursive occurrences to the lefts of the outermost arrows if we are to have recursive occurrences at all. |
662 | 645 |
663 Why must Coq enforce this restriction? Imagine that our last definition had been accepted, allowing us to write this function: | 646 Why must Coq enforce this restriction? Imagine that our last definition had been accepted, allowing us to write this function: |
681 (** * An Interlude on Proof Terms *) | 664 (** * An Interlude on Proof Terms *) |
682 | 665 |
683 (** As we have emphasized a few times already, Coq proofs are actually programs, written in the same language we have been using in our examples all along. We can get a first sense of what this means by taking a look at the definitions of some of the induction principles we have used. *) | 666 (** As we have emphasized a few times already, Coq proofs are actually programs, written in the same language we have been using in our examples all along. We can get a first sense of what this means by taking a look at the definitions of some of the induction principles we have used. *) |
684 | 667 |
685 Print unit_ind. | 668 Print unit_ind. |
686 (** [[ | 669 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
687 | 670 unit_ind = |
688 unit_ind = | 671 fun P : unit -> Prop => unit_rect P |
689 fun P : unit -> Prop => unit_rect P | |
690 : forall P : unit -> Prop, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u | 672 : forall P : unit -> Prop, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u |
673 | |
691 ]] | 674 ]] |
692 | 675 |
693 We see that this induction principle is defined in terms of a more general principle, [unit_rect]. *) | 676 We see that this induction principle is defined in terms of a more general principle, [unit_rect]. *) |
694 | 677 |
695 Check unit_rect. | 678 Check unit_rect. |
696 (** [[ | 679 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
697 | 680 unit_rect |
698 unit_rect | |
699 : forall P : unit -> Type, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u | 681 : forall P : unit -> Type, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u |
682 | |
700 ]] | 683 ]] |
701 | 684 |
702 [unit_rect] gives [P] type [unit -> Type] instead of [unit -> Prop]. [Type] is another universe, like [Set] and [Prop]. In fact, it is a common supertype of both. Later on, we will discuss exactly what the significances of the different universes are. For now, it is just important that we can use [Type] as a sort of meta-universe that may turn out to be either [Set] or [Prop]. We can see the symmetry inherent in the subtyping relationship by printing the definition of another principle that was generated for [unit] automatically: *) | 685 [unit_rect] gives [P] type [unit -> Type] instead of [unit -> Prop]. [Type] is another universe, like [Set] and [Prop]. In fact, it is a common supertype of both. Later on, we will discuss exactly what the significances of the different universes are. For now, it is just important that we can use [Type] as a sort of meta-universe that may turn out to be either [Set] or [Prop]. We can see the symmetry inherent in the subtyping relationship by printing the definition of another principle that was generated for [unit] automatically: *) |
703 | 686 |
704 Print unit_rec. | 687 Print unit_rec. |
705 (** [[ | 688 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
706 | 689 unit_rec = |
707 unit_rec = | 690 fun P : unit -> Set => unit_rect P |
708 fun P : unit -> Set => unit_rect P | |
709 : forall P : unit -> Set, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u | 691 : forall P : unit -> Set, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u |
692 | |
710 ]] | 693 ]] |
711 | 694 |
712 This is identical to the definition for [unit_ind], except that we have substituted [Set] for [Prop]. For most inductive types [T], then, we get not just induction principles [T_ind], but also recursion principles [T_rec]. We can use [T_rec] to write recursive definitions without explicit [Fixpoint] recursion. For instance, the following two definitions are equivalent: *) | 695 This is identical to the definition for [unit_ind], except that we have substituted [Set] for [Prop]. For most inductive types [T], then, we get not just induction principles [T_ind], but also recursion principles [T_rec]. We can use [T_rec] to write recursive definitions without explicit [Fixpoint] recursion. For instance, the following two definitions are equivalent: *) |
713 | 696 |
714 Definition always_O (u : unit) : nat := | 697 Definition always_O (u : unit) : nat := |
720 unit_rec (fun _ : unit => nat) O u. | 703 unit_rec (fun _ : unit => nat) O u. |
721 | 704 |
722 (** Going even further down the rabbit hole, [unit_rect] itself is not even a primitive. It is a functional program that we can write manually. *) | 705 (** Going even further down the rabbit hole, [unit_rect] itself is not even a primitive. It is a functional program that we can write manually. *) |
723 | 706 |
724 Print unit_rect. | 707 Print unit_rect. |
725 | 708 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
726 (** [[ | 709 unit_rect = |
727 | 710 fun (P : unit -> Type) (f : P tt) (u : unit) => |
728 unit_rect = | 711 match u as u0 return (P u0) with |
729 fun (P : unit -> Type) (f : P tt) (u : unit) => | 712 | tt => f |
730 match u as u0 return (P u0) with | 713 end |
731 | tt => f | |
732 end | |
733 : forall P : unit -> Type, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u | 714 : forall P : unit -> Type, P tt -> forall u : unit, P u |
715 | |
734 ]] | 716 ]] |
735 | 717 |
736 The only new feature we see is an [as] clause for a [match], which is used in concert with the [return] clause that we saw in the introduction. Since the type of the [match] is dependent on the value of the object being analyzed, we must give that object a name so that we can refer to it in the [return] clause. | 718 The only new feature we see is an [as] clause for a [match], which is used in concert with the [return] clause that we saw in the introduction. Since the type of the [match] is dependent on the value of the object being analyzed, we must give that object a name so that we can refer to it in the [return] clause. |
737 | 719 |
738 To prove that [unit_rect] is nothing special, we can reimplement it manually. *) | 720 To prove that [unit_rect] is nothing special, we can reimplement it manually. *) |
739 | 721 |
740 Definition unit_rect' (P : unit -> Type) (f : P tt) (u : unit) := | 722 Definition unit_rect' (P : unit -> Type) (f : P tt) (u : unit) := |
741 match u return (P u) with | 723 match u with |
742 | tt => f | 724 | tt => f |
743 end. | 725 end. |
744 | 726 |
745 (** We use the handy shorthand that lets us omit an [as] annotation when matching on a variable, simply using that variable directly in the [return] clause. | 727 (** We rely on Coq's heuristics for inferring [match] annotations. |
746 | 728 |
747 We can check the implement of [nat_rect] as well: *) | 729 We can check the implementation of [nat_rect] as well: *) |
748 | 730 |
749 Print nat_rect. | 731 Print nat_rect. |
750 (** [[ | 732 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
751 | 733 nat_rect = |
752 nat_rect = | 734 fun (P : nat -> Type) (f : P O) (f0 : forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) => |
753 fun (P : nat -> Type) (f : P O) (f0 : forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) => | 735 fix F (n : nat) : P n := |
754 fix F (n : nat) : P n := | 736 match n as n0 return (P n0) with |
755 match n as n0 return (P n0) with | 737 | O => f |
756 | O => f | 738 | S n0 => f0 n0 (F n0) |
757 | S n0 => f0 n0 (F n0) | 739 end |
758 end | 740 : forall P : nat -> Type, |
759 : forall P : nat -> Type, | 741 P O -> (forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) -> forall n : nat, P n |
760 P O -> (forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) -> forall n : nat, P n | 742 ]] |
761 ]] | 743 |
762 | 744 Now we have an actual recursive definition. [fix] expressions are an anonymous form of [Fixpoint], just as [fun] expressions stand for anonymous non-recursive functions. Beyond that, the syntax of [fix] mirrors that of [Fixpoint]. We can understand the definition of [nat_rect] better by reimplementing [nat_ind] using sections. *) |
763 Now we have an actual recursive definition. [fix] expressions are an anonymous form of [Fixpoint], just as [fun] expressions stand for anonymous non-recursive functions. Beyond that, the syntax of [fix] mirrors that of [Fixpoint]. We can understand the definition of [nat_rect] better by reimplementing [nat_ind] using sections. *) | 745 |
764 | 746 Section nat_ind'. |
765 Section nat_ind'. | 747 (** First, we have the property of natural numbers that we aim to prove. *) |
766 (** First, we have the property of natural numbers that we aim to prove. *) | 748 |
767 Variable P : nat -> Prop. | 749 Variable P : nat -> Prop. |
768 | 750 |
769 (** Then we require a proof of the [O] case. *) | 751 (** Then we require a proof of the [O] case. *) |
770 Hypothesis O_case : P O. | 752 |
771 | 753 Hypothesis O_case : P O. |
772 (** Next is a proof of the [S] case, which may assume an inductive hypothesis. *) | 754 |
773 Hypothesis S_case : forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n). | 755 (** Next is a proof of the [S] case, which may assume an inductive hypothesis. *) |
774 | 756 |
775 (** Finally, we define a recursive function to tie the pieces together. *) | 757 Hypothesis S_case : forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n). |
776 Fixpoint nat_ind' (n : nat) : P n := | 758 |
777 match n return (P n) with | 759 (** Finally, we define a recursive function to tie the pieces together. *) |
778 | O => O_case | 760 |
779 | S n' => S_case (nat_ind' n') | 761 Fixpoint nat_ind' (n : nat) : P n := |
780 end. | 762 match n with |
781 End nat_ind'. | 763 | O => O_case |
782 | 764 | S n' => S_case (nat_ind' n') |
783 (** Closing the section adds the [Variable]s and [Hypothesis]es as new [fun]-bound arguments to [nat_ind'], and, modulo the use of [Prop] instead of [Type], we end up with the exact same definition that was generated automatically for [nat_rect]. | 765 end. |
784 | 766 End nat_ind'. |
785 %\medskip% | 767 |
786 | 768 (** Closing the section adds the [Variable]s and [Hypothesis]es as new [fun]-bound arguments to [nat_ind'], and, modulo the use of [Prop] instead of [Type], we end up with the exact same definition that was generated automatically for [nat_rect]. |
787 We can also examine the definition of [even_list_mut], which we generated with [Scheme] for a mutually-recursive type. *) | 769 |
788 | 770 %\medskip% |
789 Print even_list_mut. | 771 |
790 (** [[ | 772 We can also examine the definition of [even_list_mut], which we generated with [Scheme] for a mutually-recursive type. *) |
791 | 773 |
792 even_list_mut = | 774 Print even_list_mut. |
793 fun (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop) | 775 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
794 (f : P ENil) (f0 : forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) | 776 even_list_mut = |
795 (f1 : forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) => | 777 fun (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop) |
796 fix F (e : even_list) : P e := | 778 (f : P ENil) (f0 : forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) |
797 match e as e0 return (P e0) with | 779 (f1 : forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) => |
798 | ENil => f | 780 fix F (e : even_list) : P e := |
799 | ECons n o => f0 n o (F0 o) | 781 match e as e0 return (P e0) with |
800 end | 782 | ENil => f |
801 with F0 (o : odd_list) : P0 o := | 783 | ECons n o => f0 n o (F0 o) |
802 match o as o0 return (P0 o0) with | 784 end |
803 | OCons n e => f1 n e (F e) | 785 with F0 (o : odd_list) : P0 o := |
804 end | 786 match o as o0 return (P0 o0) with |
805 for F | 787 | OCons n e => f1 n e (F e) |
806 : forall (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop), | 788 end |
807 P ENil -> | 789 for F |
808 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) -> | 790 : forall (P : even_list -> Prop) (P0 : odd_list -> Prop), |
809 (forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) -> | 791 P ENil -> |
810 forall e : even_list, P e | 792 (forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), P0 o -> P (ECons n o)) -> |
811 ]] | 793 (forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), P e -> P0 (OCons n e)) -> |
812 | 794 forall e : even_list, P e |
813 We see a mutually-recursive [fix], with the different functions separated by [with] in the same way that they would be separated by [and] in ML. A final [for] clause identifies which of the mutually-recursive functions should be the final value of the [fix] expression. Using this definition as a template, we can reimplement [even_list_mut] directly. *) | 795 |
814 | 796 ]] |
815 Section even_list_mut'. | 797 |
816 (** First, we need the properties that we are proving. *) | 798 We see a mutually-recursive [fix], with the different functions separated by [with] in the same way that they would be separated by [and] in ML. A final [for] clause identifies which of the mutually-recursive functions should be the final value of the [fix] expression. Using this definition as a template, we can reimplement [even_list_mut] directly. *) |
817 Variable Peven : even_list -> Prop. | 799 |
818 Variable Podd : odd_list -> Prop. | 800 Section even_list_mut'. |
819 | 801 (** First, we need the properties that we are proving. *) |
820 (** Next, we need proofs of the three cases. *) | 802 |
821 Hypothesis ENil_case : Peven ENil. | 803 Variable Peven : even_list -> Prop. |
822 Hypothesis ECons_case : forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), Podd o -> Peven (ECons n o). | 804 Variable Podd : odd_list -> Prop. |
823 Hypothesis OCons_case : forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), Peven e -> Podd (OCons n e). | 805 |
824 | 806 (** Next, we need proofs of the three cases. *) |
825 (** Finally, we define the recursive functions. *) | 807 |
826 Fixpoint even_list_mut' (e : even_list) : Peven e := | 808 Hypothesis ENil_case : Peven ENil. |
827 match e return (Peven e) with | 809 Hypothesis ECons_case : forall (n : nat) (o : odd_list), Podd o -> Peven (ECons n o). |
828 | ENil => ENil_case | 810 Hypothesis OCons_case : forall (n : nat) (e : even_list), Peven e -> Podd (OCons n e). |
829 | ECons n o => ECons_case n (odd_list_mut' o) | 811 |
830 end | 812 (** Finally, we define the recursive functions. *) |
831 with odd_list_mut' (o : odd_list) : Podd o := | 813 |
832 match o return (Podd o) with | 814 Fixpoint even_list_mut' (e : even_list) : Peven e := |
833 | OCons n e => OCons_case n (even_list_mut' e) | 815 match e with |
834 end. | 816 | ENil => ENil_case |
817 | ECons n o => ECons_case n (odd_list_mut' o) | |
818 end | |
819 with odd_list_mut' (o : odd_list) : Podd o := | |
820 match o with | |
821 | OCons n e => OCons_case n (even_list_mut' e) | |
822 end. | |
835 End even_list_mut'. | 823 End even_list_mut'. |
836 | 824 |
837 (** Even induction principles for reflexive types are easy to implement directly. For our [formula] type, we can use a recursive definition much like those we wrote above. *) | 825 (** Even induction principles for reflexive types are easy to implement directly. For our [formula] type, we can use a recursive definition much like those we wrote above. *) |
838 | 826 |
839 Section formula_ind'. | 827 Section formula_ind'. |
843 P f1 -> P f2 -> P (And f1 f2). | 831 P f1 -> P f2 -> P (And f1 f2). |
844 Hypothesis Forall_case : forall f : nat -> formula, | 832 Hypothesis Forall_case : forall f : nat -> formula, |
845 (forall n : nat, P (f n)) -> P (Forall f). | 833 (forall n : nat, P (f n)) -> P (Forall f). |
846 | 834 |
847 Fixpoint formula_ind' (f : formula) : P f := | 835 Fixpoint formula_ind' (f : formula) : P f := |
848 match f return (P f) with | 836 match f with |
849 | Eq n1 n2 => Eq_case n1 n2 | 837 | Eq n1 n2 => Eq_case n1 n2 |
850 | And f1 f2 => And_case (formula_ind' f1) (formula_ind' f2) | 838 | And f1 f2 => And_case (formula_ind' f1) (formula_ind' f2) |
851 | Forall f' => Forall_case f' (fun n => formula_ind' (f' n)) | 839 | Forall f' => Forall_case f' (fun n => formula_ind' (f' n)) |
852 end. | 840 end. |
853 End formula_ind'. | 841 End formula_ind'. |
864 (** This is an example of a %\textit{%#<i>#nested#</i>#%}% inductive type definition, because we use the type we are defining as an argument to a parametrized type family. Coq will not allow all such definitions; it effectively pretends that we are defining [nat_tree] mutually with a version of [list] specialized to [nat_tree], checking that the resulting expanded definition satisfies the usual rules. For instance, if we replaced [list] with a type family that used its parameter as a function argument, then the definition would be rejected as violating the positivity restriction. | 852 (** This is an example of a %\textit{%#<i>#nested#</i>#%}% inductive type definition, because we use the type we are defining as an argument to a parametrized type family. Coq will not allow all such definitions; it effectively pretends that we are defining [nat_tree] mutually with a version of [list] specialized to [nat_tree], checking that the resulting expanded definition satisfies the usual rules. For instance, if we replaced [list] with a type family that used its parameter as a function argument, then the definition would be rejected as violating the positivity restriction. |
865 | 853 |
866 Like we encountered for mutual inductive types, we find that the automatically-generated induction principle for [nat_tree] is too weak. *) | 854 Like we encountered for mutual inductive types, we find that the automatically-generated induction principle for [nat_tree] is too weak. *) |
867 | 855 |
868 Check nat_tree_ind. | 856 Check nat_tree_ind. |
869 (** [[ | 857 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
870 | 858 nat_tree_ind |
871 nat_tree_ind | |
872 : forall P : nat_tree -> Prop, | 859 : forall P : nat_tree -> Prop, |
873 P NLeaf' -> | 860 P NLeaf' -> |
874 (forall (n : nat) (l : list nat_tree), P (NNode' n l)) -> | 861 (forall (n : nat) (l : list nat_tree), P (NNode' n l)) -> |
875 forall n : nat_tree, P n | 862 forall n : nat_tree, P n |
863 | |
876 ]] | 864 ]] |
877 | 865 |
878 There is no command like [Scheme] that will implement an improved principle for us. In general, it takes creativity to figure out how to incorporate nested uses to different type families. Now that we know how to implement induction principles manually, we are in a position to apply just such creativity to this problem. | 866 There is no command like [Scheme] that will implement an improved principle for us. In general, it takes creativity to figure out how to incorporate nested uses to different type families. Now that we know how to implement induction principles manually, we are in a position to apply just such creativity to this problem. |
879 | 867 |
880 First, we will need an auxiliary definition, characterizing what it means for a property to hold of every element of a list. *) | 868 First, we will need an auxiliary definition, characterizing what it means for a property to hold of every element of a list. *) |
891 End All. | 879 End All. |
892 | 880 |
893 (** It will be useful to look at the definitions of [True] and [/\], since we will want to write manual proofs of them below. *) | 881 (** It will be useful to look at the definitions of [True] and [/\], since we will want to write manual proofs of them below. *) |
894 | 882 |
895 Print True. | 883 Print True. |
896 (** [[ | 884 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
897 | 885 Inductive True : Prop := I : True |
898 Inductive True : Prop := I : True | 886 |
899 ]] | 887 ]] |
900 | 888 |
901 That is, [True] is a proposition with exactly one proof, [I], which we may always supply trivially. | 889 That is, [True] is a proposition with exactly one proof, [I], which we may always supply trivially. |
902 | 890 |
903 Finding the definition of [/\] takes a little more work. Coq supports user registration of arbitrary parsing rules, and it is such a rule that is letting us write [/\] instead of an application of some inductive type family. We can find the underlying inductive type with the [Locate] command. *) | 891 Finding the definition of [/\] takes a little more work. Coq supports user registration of arbitrary parsing rules, and it is such a rule that is letting us write [/\] instead of an application of some inductive type family. We can find the underlying inductive type with the [Locate] command. *) |
904 | 892 |
905 Locate "/\". | 893 Locate "/\". |
906 (** [[ | 894 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
907 | 895 Notation Scope |
908 Notation Scope | 896 "A /\ B" := and A B : type_scope |
909 "A /\ B" := and A B : type_scope | 897 (default interpretation) |
910 (default interpretation) | |
911 ]] *) | 898 ]] *) |
912 | 899 |
913 Print and. | 900 Print and. |
914 (** [[ | 901 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[ |
915 | 902 Inductive and (A : Prop) (B : Prop) : Prop := conj : A -> B -> A /\ B |
916 Inductive and (A : Prop) (B : Prop) : Prop := conj : A -> B -> A /\ B | 903 For conj: Arguments A, B are implicit |
917 For conj: Arguments A, B are implicit | 904 For and: Argument scopes are [type_scope type_scope] |
918 For and: Argument scopes are [type_scope type_scope] | 905 For conj: Argument scopes are [type_scope type_scope _ _] |
919 For conj: Argument scopes are [type_scope type_scope _ _] | 906 |
920 ]] | 907 ]] |
921 | 908 |
922 In addition to the definition of [and] itself, we get information on implicit arguments and parsing rules for [and] and its constructor [conj]. We will ignore the parsing information for now. The implicit argument information tells us that we build a proof of a conjunction by calling the constructor [conj] on proofs of the conjuncts, with no need to include the types of those proofs as explicit arguments. | 909 In addition to the definition of [and] itself, we get information on implicit arguments and parsing rules for [and] and its constructor [conj]. We will ignore the parsing information for now. The implicit argument information tells us that we build a proof of a conjunction by calling the constructor [conj] on proofs of the conjuncts, with no need to include the types of those proofs as explicit arguments. |
923 | 910 |
924 %\medskip% | 911 %\medskip% |
933 All P ls -> P (NNode' n ls). | 920 All P ls -> P (NNode' n ls). |
934 | 921 |
935 (** A first attempt at writing the induction principle itself follows the intuition that nested inductive type definitions are expanded into mutual inductive definitions. | 922 (** A first attempt at writing the induction principle itself follows the intuition that nested inductive type definitions are expanded into mutual inductive definitions. |
936 | 923 |
937 [[ | 924 [[ |
938 | |
939 Fixpoint nat_tree_ind' (tr : nat_tree) : P tr := | 925 Fixpoint nat_tree_ind' (tr : nat_tree) : P tr := |
940 match tr return (P tr) with | 926 match tr with |
941 | NLeaf' => NLeaf'_case | 927 | NLeaf' => NLeaf'_case |
942 | NNode' n ls => NNode'_case n ls (list_nat_tree_ind ls) | 928 | NNode' n ls => NNode'_case n ls (list_nat_tree_ind ls) |
943 end | 929 end |
944 | 930 |
945 with list_nat_tree_ind (ls : list nat_tree) : All P ls := | 931 with list_nat_tree_ind (ls : list nat_tree) : All P ls := |
946 match ls return (All P ls) with | 932 match ls with |
947 | Nil => I | 933 | Nil => I |
948 | Cons tr rest => conj (nat_tree_ind' tr) (list_nat_tree_ind rest) | 934 | Cons tr rest => conj (nat_tree_ind' tr) (list_nat_tree_ind rest) |
949 end. | 935 end. |
950 | 936 |
951 ]] | 937 ]] |
952 | 938 |
953 Coq rejects this definition, saying "Recursive call to nat_tree_ind' has principal argument equal to "tr" instead of rest." The term "nested inductive type" hints at the solution to the problem. Just like true mutually-inductive types require mutually-recursive induction principles, nested types require nested recursion. *) | 939 Coq rejects this definition, saying "Recursive call to nat_tree_ind' has principal argument equal to "tr" instead of rest." The term "nested inductive type" hints at the solution to the problem. Just like true mutually-inductive types require mutually-recursive induction principles, nested types require nested recursion. *) |
954 | 940 |
955 Fixpoint nat_tree_ind' (tr : nat_tree) : P tr := | 941 Fixpoint nat_tree_ind' (tr : nat_tree) : P tr := |
956 match tr return (P tr) with | 942 match tr with |
957 | NLeaf' => NLeaf'_case | 943 | NLeaf' => NLeaf'_case |
958 | NNode' n ls => NNode'_case n ls | 944 | NNode' n ls => NNode'_case n ls |
959 ((fix list_nat_tree_ind (ls : list nat_tree) : All P ls := | 945 ((fix list_nat_tree_ind (ls : list nat_tree) : All P ls := |
960 match ls return (All P ls) with | 946 match ls with |
961 | Nil => I | 947 | Nil => I |
962 | Cons tr rest => conj (nat_tree_ind' tr) (list_nat_tree_ind rest) | 948 | Cons tr rest => conj (nat_tree_ind' tr) (list_nat_tree_ind rest) |
963 end) ls) | 949 end) ls) |
964 end. | 950 end. |
965 | 951 |
994 | NNode' _ trs => S (sum (map ntsize trs)) | 980 | NNode' _ trs => S (sum (map ntsize trs)) |
995 end. | 981 end. |
996 | 982 |
997 (** Notice that Coq was smart enough to expand the definition of [map] to verify that we are using proper nested recursion, even through a use of a higher-order function. *) | 983 (** Notice that Coq was smart enough to expand the definition of [map] to verify that we are using proper nested recursion, even through a use of a higher-order function. *) |
998 | 984 |
999 Fixpoint ntsplice (tr1 tr2 : nat_tree) {struct tr1} : nat_tree := | 985 Fixpoint ntsplice (tr1 tr2 : nat_tree) : nat_tree := |
1000 match tr1 with | 986 match tr1 with |
1001 | NLeaf' => NNode' O (Cons tr2 Nil) | 987 | NLeaf' => NNode' O (Cons tr2 Nil) |
1002 | NNode' n Nil => NNode' n (Cons tr2 Nil) | 988 | NNode' n Nil => NNode' n (Cons tr2 Nil) |
1003 | NNode' n (Cons tr trs) => NNode' n (Cons (ntsplice tr tr2) trs) | 989 | NNode' n (Cons tr trs) => NNode' n (Cons (ntsplice tr tr2) trs) |
1004 end. | 990 end. |
1018 = plus (ntsize tr2) (ntsize tr1). | 1004 = plus (ntsize tr2) (ntsize tr1). |
1019 (* begin thide *) | 1005 (* begin thide *) |
1020 Hint Rewrite plus_S : cpdt. | 1006 Hint Rewrite plus_S : cpdt. |
1021 | 1007 |
1022 (** We know that the standard induction principle is insufficient for the task, so we need to provide a [using] clause for the [induction] tactic to specify our alternate principle. *) | 1008 (** We know that the standard induction principle is insufficient for the task, so we need to provide a [using] clause for the [induction] tactic to specify our alternate principle. *) |
1009 | |
1023 induction tr1 using nat_tree_ind'; crush. | 1010 induction tr1 using nat_tree_ind'; crush. |
1024 | 1011 |
1025 (** One subgoal remains: [[ | 1012 (** One subgoal remains: [[ |
1026 | |
1027 n : nat | 1013 n : nat |
1028 ls : list nat_tree | 1014 ls : list nat_tree |
1029 H : All | 1015 H : All |
1030 (fun tr1 : nat_tree => | 1016 (fun tr1 : nat_tree => |
1031 forall tr2 : nat_tree, | 1017 forall tr2 : nat_tree, |
1035 ntsize | 1021 ntsize |
1036 match ls with | 1022 match ls with |
1037 | Nil => NNode' n (Cons tr2 Nil) | 1023 | Nil => NNode' n (Cons tr2 Nil) |
1038 | Cons tr trs => NNode' n (Cons (ntsplice tr tr2) trs) | 1024 | Cons tr trs => NNode' n (Cons (ntsplice tr tr2) trs) |
1039 end = S (plus (ntsize tr2) (sum (map ntsize ls))) | 1025 end = S (plus (ntsize tr2) (sum (map ntsize ls))) |
1026 | |
1040 ]] | 1027 ]] |
1041 | 1028 |
1042 After a few moments of squinting at this goal, it becomes apparent that we need to do a case analysis on the structure of [ls]. The rest is routine. *) | 1029 After a few moments of squinting at this goal, it becomes apparent that we need to do a case analysis on the structure of [ls]. The rest is routine. *) |
1043 | 1030 |
1044 destruct ls; crush. | 1031 destruct ls; crush. |
1060 (** * Manual Proofs About Constructors *) | 1047 (** * Manual Proofs About Constructors *) |
1061 | 1048 |
1062 (** It can be useful to understand how tactics like [discriminate] and [injection] work, so it is worth stepping through a manual proof of each kind. We will start with a proof fit for [discriminate]. *) | 1049 (** It can be useful to understand how tactics like [discriminate] and [injection] work, so it is worth stepping through a manual proof of each kind. We will start with a proof fit for [discriminate]. *) |
1063 | 1050 |
1064 Theorem true_neq_false : true <> false. | 1051 Theorem true_neq_false : true <> false. |
1052 | |
1065 (* begin thide *) | 1053 (* begin thide *) |
1066 (** We begin with the tactic [red], which is short for "one step of reduction," to unfold the definition of logical negation. *) | 1054 (** We begin with the tactic [red], which is short for "one step of reduction," to unfold the definition of logical negation. *) |
1067 | 1055 |
1068 red. | 1056 red. |
1069 (** [[ | 1057 (** [[ |
1070 | |
1071 ============================ | 1058 ============================ |
1072 true = false -> False | 1059 true = false -> False |
1060 | |
1073 ]] | 1061 ]] |
1074 | 1062 |
1075 The negation is replaced with an implication of falsehood. We use the tactic [intro H] to change the assumption of the implication into a hypothesis named [H]. *) | 1063 The negation is replaced with an implication of falsehood. We use the tactic [intro H] to change the assumption of the implication into a hypothesis named [H]. *) |
1076 | 1064 |
1077 intro H. | 1065 intro H. |
1078 (** [[ | 1066 (** [[ |
1079 | |
1080 H : true = false | 1067 H : true = false |
1081 ============================ | 1068 ============================ |
1082 False | 1069 False |
1070 | |
1083 ]] | 1071 ]] |
1084 | 1072 |
1085 This is the point in the proof where we apply some creativity. We define a function whose utility will become clear soon. *) | 1073 This is the point in the proof where we apply some creativity. We define a function whose utility will become clear soon. *) |
1086 | 1074 |
1087 Definition f (b : bool) := if b then True else False. | 1075 Definition f (b : bool) := if b then True else False. |
1088 | 1076 |
1089 (** It is worth recalling the difference between the lowercase and uppercase versions of truth and falsehood: [True] and [False] are logical propositions, while [true] and [false] are boolean values that we can case-analyze. We have defined [f] such that our conclusion of [False] is computationally equivalent to [f false]. Thus, the [change] tactic will let us change the conclusion to [f false]. *) | 1077 (** It is worth recalling the difference between the lowercase and uppercase versions of truth and falsehood: [True] and [False] are logical propositions, while [true] and [false] are boolean values that we can case-analyze. We have defined [f] such that our conclusion of [False] is computationally equivalent to [f false]. Thus, the [change] tactic will let us change the conclusion to [f false]. *) |
1090 | 1078 |
1091 change (f false). | 1079 change (f false). |
1092 (** [[ | 1080 (** [[ |
1093 | |
1094 H : true = false | 1081 H : true = false |
1095 ============================ | 1082 ============================ |
1096 f false | 1083 f false |
1084 | |
1097 ]] | 1085 ]] |
1098 | 1086 |
1099 Now the righthand side of [H]'s equality appears in the conclusion, so we can rewrite, using the notation [<-] to request to replace the righthand side the equality with the lefthand side. *) | 1087 Now the righthand side of [H]'s equality appears in the conclusion, so we can rewrite, using the notation [<-] to request to replace the righthand side the equality with the lefthand side. *) |
1100 | 1088 |
1101 rewrite <- H. | 1089 rewrite <- H. |
1102 (** [[ | 1090 (** [[ |
1103 | |
1104 H : true = false | 1091 H : true = false |
1105 ============================ | 1092 ============================ |
1106 f true | 1093 f true |
1094 | |
1107 ]] | 1095 ]] |
1108 | 1096 |
1109 We are almost done. Just how close we are to done is revealed by computational simplification. *) | 1097 We are almost done. Just how close we are to done is revealed by computational simplification. *) |
1110 | 1098 |
1111 simpl. | 1099 simpl. |
1112 (** [[ | 1100 (** [[ |
1113 | |
1114 H : true = false | 1101 H : true = false |
1115 ============================ | 1102 ============================ |
1116 True | 1103 True |
1104 | |
1117 ]] *) | 1105 ]] *) |
1118 | 1106 |
1119 trivial. | 1107 trivial. |
1120 Qed. | 1108 Qed. |
1121 (* end thide *) | 1109 (* end thide *) |