Mercurial > cpdt > repo
diff src/InductiveTypes.v @ 28:0543bbd62843
nat
author | Adam Chlipala <adamc@hcoop.net> |
---|---|
date | Mon, 08 Sep 2008 15:02:18 -0400 |
parents | 8788249c7d3a |
children | add8215ec72a |
line wrap: on
line diff
--- a/src/InductiveTypes.v Mon Sep 08 14:28:55 2008 -0400 +++ b/src/InductiveTypes.v Mon Sep 08 15:02:18 2008 -0400 @@ -171,3 +171,108 @@ bool_ind : forall P : bool -> Prop, P true -> P false -> forall b : bool, P b ]] *) + + +(** * Simple Recursive Types *) + +(** The natural numbers are the simplest common example of an inductive type that actually deserves the name. *) + +Inductive nat : Set := +| O : nat +| S : nat -> nat. + +(** [O] is zero, and [S] is the successor function, so that [0] is syntactic sugar for [O], [1] for [S O], [2] for [S (S O)], and so on. + +Pattern matching works as we demonstrated in the last chapter: *) + +Definition isZero (n : nat) : bool := + match n with + | O => true + | S _ => false + end. + +Definition pred (n : nat) : nat := + match n with + | O => O + | S n' => n' + end. + +(** We can prove theorems by case analysis: *) + +Theorem S_isZero : forall n : nat, isZero (pred (S (S n))) = false. + destruct n; reflexivity. +Qed. + +(** We can also now get into genuine inductive theorems. First, we will need a recursive function, to make things interesting. *) + +Fixpoint plus (n m : nat) {struct n} : nat := + match n with + | O => m + | S n' => S (plus n' m) + end. + +(** Recall that [Fixpoint] is Coq's mechanism for recursive function definitions, and that the [{struct n}] annotation is noting which function argument decreases structurally at recursive calls. + +Some theorems about [plus] can be proved without induction. *) + +Theorem O_plus_n : forall n : nat, plus O n = n. + intro; reflexivity. +Qed. + +(** Coq's computation rules automatically simplify the application of [plus]. If we just reverse the order of the arguments, though, this no longer works, and we need induction. *) + +Theorem n_plus_O : forall n : nat, plus n O = n. + induction n. + +(** Our first subgoal is [plus O O = O], which %\textit{%#<i>#is#</i>#%}% trivial by computation. *) + + reflexivity. + +(** Our second subgoal is more work and also demonstrates our first inductive hypothesis. + +[[ + + n : nat + IHn : plus n O = n + ============================ + plus (S n) O = S n +]] + +We can start out by using computation to simplify the goal as far as we can. *) + + simpl. + +(** Now the conclusion is [S (plus n O) = S n]. Using our inductive hypothesis: *) + + rewrite IHn. + +(** ...we get a trivial conclusion [S n = S n]. *) + + reflexivity. + +(** Not much really went on in this proof, so the [crush] tactic from the [Tactics] module can prove this theorem automatically. *) + +Restart. + induction n; crush. +Qed. + +(** We can check out the induction principle at work here: *) + +Check nat_ind. +(** [[ + +nat_ind : forall P : nat -> Prop, + P O -> (forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n)) -> forall n : nat, P n +]] + +Each of the two cases of our last proof came from the type of one of the arguments to [nat_ind]. We chose [P] to be [(fun n : nat => plus n O = n)]. The first proof case corresponded to [P O], and the second case to [(forall n : nat, P n -> P (S n))]. The free variable [n] and inductive hypothesis [IHn] came from the argument types given here. + +Since [nat] has a constructor that takes an argument, we may sometimes need to know that that constructor is injective. *) + +Theorem S_inj : forall n m : nat, S n = S m -> n = m. + injection 1; trivial. +Qed. + +(** [injection] refers to a premise by number, adding new equalities between the corresponding arguments of equated terms that are formed with the same constructor. We end up needing to prove [n = m -> n = m], so it is unsurprising that a tactic named [trivial] is able to finish the proof. + +There is also a very useful tactic called [congruence] that can prove this theorem immediately. [congruence] generalizes [discriminate] and [injection], and it also adds reasoning about the general properties of equality, such as that a function returns equal results on equal arguments. That is, [congruence] is a %\textit{%#<i>#complete decision procedure for the theory of equality and uninterpreted functions#</i>#%}%, plus some smarts about inductive types. *) \ No newline at end of file