adam@287
|
1 (* Copyright (c) 2009-2010, Adam Chlipala
|
adamc@227
|
2 *
|
adamc@227
|
3 * This work is licensed under a
|
adamc@227
|
4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
|
adamc@227
|
5 * Unported License.
|
adamc@227
|
6 * The license text is available at:
|
adamc@227
|
7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
|
adamc@227
|
8 *)
|
adamc@227
|
9
|
adamc@227
|
10 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@230
|
11 Require Import DepList Tactics.
|
adamc@227
|
12
|
adamc@227
|
13 Set Implicit Arguments.
|
adamc@227
|
14 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@227
|
15
|
adamc@227
|
16
|
adamc@227
|
17 (** %\chapter{Universes and Axioms}% *)
|
adamc@227
|
18
|
adamc@228
|
19 (** Many traditional theorems can be proved in Coq without special knowledge of CIC, the logic behind the prover. A development just seems to be using a particular ASCII notation for standard formulas based on set theory. Nonetheless, as we saw in Chapter 4, CIC differs from set theory in starting from fewer orthogonal primitives. It is possible to define the usual logical connectives as derived notions. The foundation of it all is a dependently-typed functional programming language, based on dependent function types and inductive type families. By using the facilities of this language directly, we can accomplish some things much more easily than in mainstream math.
|
adamc@227
|
20
|
adamc@227
|
21 Gallina, which adds features to the more theoretical CIC, is the logic implemented in Coq. It has a relatively simple foundation that can be defined rigorously in a page or two of formal proof rules. Still, there are some important subtleties that have practical ramifications. This chapter focuses on those subtleties, avoiding formal metatheory in favor of example code. *)
|
adamc@227
|
22
|
adamc@227
|
23
|
adamc@227
|
24 (** * The [Type] Hierarchy *)
|
adamc@227
|
25
|
adamc@227
|
26 (** Every object in Gallina has a type. *)
|
adamc@227
|
27
|
adamc@227
|
28 Check 0.
|
adamc@227
|
29 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
30 0
|
adamc@227
|
31 : nat
|
adamc@227
|
32
|
adamc@227
|
33 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
34
|
adamc@227
|
35 It is natural enough that zero be considered as a natural number. *)
|
adamc@227
|
36
|
adamc@227
|
37 Check nat.
|
adamc@227
|
38 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
39 nat
|
adamc@227
|
40 : Set
|
adamc@227
|
41
|
adamc@227
|
42 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
43
|
adam@287
|
44 From a set theory perspective, it is unsurprising to consider the natural numbers as a %``%#"#set.#"#%''% *)
|
adamc@227
|
45
|
adamc@227
|
46 Check Set.
|
adamc@227
|
47 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
48 Set
|
adamc@227
|
49 : Type
|
adamc@227
|
50
|
adamc@227
|
51 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
52
|
adamc@227
|
53 The type [Set] may be considered as the set of all sets, a concept that set theory handles in terms of %\textit{%#<i>#classes#</i>#%}%. In Coq, this more general notion is [Type]. *)
|
adamc@227
|
54
|
adamc@227
|
55 Check Type.
|
adamc@227
|
56 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
57 Type
|
adamc@227
|
58 : Type
|
adamc@227
|
59
|
adamc@227
|
60 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
61
|
adam@287
|
62 Strangely enough, [Type] appears to be its own type. It is known that polymorphic languages with this property are inconsistent. That is, using such a language to encode proofs is unwise, because it is possible to %``%#"#prove#"#%''% any proposition. What is really going on here?
|
adamc@227
|
63
|
adamc@227
|
64 Let us repeat some of our queries after toggling a flag related to Coq's printing behavior. *)
|
adamc@227
|
65
|
adamc@227
|
66 Set Printing Universes.
|
adamc@227
|
67
|
adamc@227
|
68 Check nat.
|
adamc@227
|
69 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
70 nat
|
adamc@227
|
71 : Set
|
adam@302
|
72 ]]
|
adam@302
|
73 *)
|
adamc@227
|
74
|
adamc@227
|
75 (** printing $ %({}*% #(<a/>*# *)
|
adamc@227
|
76 (** printing ^ %*{})% #*<a/>)# *)
|
adamc@227
|
77
|
adamc@227
|
78 Check Set.
|
adamc@227
|
79 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
80 Set
|
adamc@227
|
81 : Type $ (0)+1 ^
|
adamc@227
|
82
|
adam@302
|
83 ]]
|
adam@302
|
84 *)
|
adamc@227
|
85
|
adamc@227
|
86 Check Type.
|
adamc@227
|
87 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
88 Type $ Top.3 ^
|
adamc@227
|
89 : Type $ (Top.3)+1 ^
|
adamc@227
|
90
|
adamc@227
|
91 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
92
|
adam@287
|
93 Occurrences of [Type] are annotated with some additional information, inside comments. These annotations have to do with the secret behind [Type]: it really stands for an infinite hierarchy of types. The type of [Set] is [Type(0)], the type of [Type(0)] is [Type(1)], the type of [Type(1)] is [Type(2)], and so on. This is how we avoid the %``%#"#[Type : Type]#"#%''% paradox. As a convenience, the universe hierarchy drives Coq's one variety of subtyping. Any term whose type is [Type] at level [i] is automatically also described by [Type] at level [j] when [j > i].
|
adamc@227
|
94
|
adamc@227
|
95 In the outputs of our first [Check] query, we see that the type level of [Set]'s type is [(0)+1]. Here [0] stands for the level of [Set], and we increment it to arrive at the level that %\textit{%#<i>#classifies#</i>#%}% [Set].
|
adamc@227
|
96
|
adamc@227
|
97 In the second query's output, we see that the occurrence of [Type] that we check is assigned a fresh %\textit{%#<i>#universe variable#</i>#%}% [Top.3]. The output type increments [Top.3] to move up a level in the universe hierarchy. As we write code that uses definitions whose types mention universe variables, unification may refine the values of those variables. Luckily, the user rarely has to worry about the details.
|
adamc@227
|
98
|
adamc@227
|
99 Another crucial concept in CIC is %\textit{%#<i>#predicativity#</i>#%}%. Consider these queries. *)
|
adamc@227
|
100
|
adamc@227
|
101 Check forall T : nat, fin T.
|
adamc@227
|
102 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
103 forall T : nat, fin T
|
adamc@227
|
104 : Set
|
adam@302
|
105 ]]
|
adam@302
|
106 *)
|
adamc@227
|
107
|
adamc@227
|
108 Check forall T : Set, T.
|
adamc@227
|
109 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
110 forall T : Set, T
|
adamc@227
|
111 : Type $ max(0, (0)+1) ^
|
adam@302
|
112 ]]
|
adam@302
|
113 *)
|
adamc@227
|
114
|
adamc@227
|
115 Check forall T : Type, T.
|
adamc@227
|
116 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
117 forall T : Type $ Top.9 ^ , T
|
adamc@227
|
118 : Type $ max(Top.9, (Top.9)+1) ^
|
adamc@227
|
119
|
adamc@227
|
120 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
121
|
adamc@227
|
122 These outputs demonstrate the rule for determining which universe a [forall] type lives in. In particular, for a type [forall x : T1, T2], we take the maximum of the universes of [T1] and [T2]. In the first example query, both [T1] ([nat]) and [T2] ([fin T]) are in [Set], so the [forall] type is in [Set], too. In the second query, [T1] is [Set], which is at level [(0)+1]; and [T2] is [T], which is at level [0]. Thus, the [forall] exists at the maximum of these two levels. The third example illustrates the same outcome, where we replace [Set] with an occurrence of [Type] that is assigned universe variable [Top.9]. This universe variable appears in the places where [0] appeared in the previous query.
|
adamc@227
|
123
|
adam@287
|
124 The behind-the-scenes manipulation of universe variables gives us predicativity. Consider this simple definition of a polymorphic identity function, where the first argument [T] will automatically be marked as implicit, since it can be inferred from the type of the second argument [x]. *)
|
adamc@227
|
125
|
adamc@227
|
126 Definition id (T : Set) (x : T) : T := x.
|
adamc@227
|
127
|
adamc@227
|
128 Check id 0.
|
adamc@227
|
129 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
130 id 0
|
adamc@227
|
131 : nat
|
adamc@227
|
132
|
adamc@227
|
133 Check id Set.
|
adamc@227
|
134
|
adamc@227
|
135 Error: Illegal application (Type Error):
|
adamc@227
|
136 ...
|
adamc@228
|
137 The 1st term has type "Type $ (Top.15)+1 ^" which should be coercible to "Set".
|
adamc@227
|
138
|
adamc@227
|
139 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
140
|
adamc@227
|
141 The parameter [T] of [id] must be instantiated with a [Set]. [nat] is a [Set], but [Set] is not. We can try fixing the problem by generalizing our definition of [id]. *)
|
adamc@227
|
142
|
adamc@227
|
143 Reset id.
|
adamc@227
|
144 Definition id (T : Type) (x : T) : T := x.
|
adamc@227
|
145 Check id 0.
|
adamc@227
|
146 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
147 id 0
|
adamc@227
|
148 : nat
|
adam@302
|
149 ]]
|
adam@302
|
150 *)
|
adamc@227
|
151
|
adamc@227
|
152 Check id Set.
|
adamc@227
|
153 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
154 id Set
|
adamc@227
|
155 : Type $ Top.17 ^
|
adam@302
|
156 ]]
|
adam@302
|
157 *)
|
adamc@227
|
158
|
adamc@227
|
159 Check id Type.
|
adamc@227
|
160 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
161 id Type $ Top.18 ^
|
adamc@227
|
162 : Type $ Top.19 ^
|
adam@302
|
163 ]]
|
adam@302
|
164 *)
|
adamc@227
|
165
|
adamc@227
|
166 (** So far so good. As we apply [id] to different [T] values, the inferred index for [T]'s [Type] occurrence automatically moves higher up the type hierarchy.
|
adamc@227
|
167
|
adamc@227
|
168 [[
|
adamc@227
|
169 Check id id.
|
adamc@227
|
170
|
adamc@227
|
171 Error: Universe inconsistency (cannot enforce Top.16 < Top.16).
|
adamc@227
|
172
|
adamc@227
|
173 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
174
|
adam@287
|
175 This error message reminds us that the universe variable for [T] still exists, even though it is usually hidden. To apply [id] to itself, that variable would need to be less than itself in the type hierarchy. Universe inconsistency error messages announce cases like this one where a term could only type-check by violating an implied constraint over universe variables. Such errors demonstrate that [Type] is %\textit{%#<i>#predicative#</i>#%}%, where this word has a CIC meaning closely related to its usual mathematical meaning. A predicative system enforces the constraint that, for any object of quantified type, none of those quantifiers may ever be instantiated with the object itself. Impredicativity is associated with popular paradoxes in set theory, involving inconsistent constructions like %``%#"#the set of all sets that do not contain themselves.#"#%''% Similar paradoxes would result from uncontrolled impredicativity in Coq. *)
|
adamc@227
|
176
|
adamc@227
|
177
|
adamc@227
|
178 (** ** Inductive Definitions *)
|
adamc@227
|
179
|
adamc@227
|
180 (** Predicativity restrictions also apply to inductive definitions. As an example, let us consider a type of expression trees that allows injection of any native Coq value. The idea is that an [exp T] stands for a reflected expression of type [T].
|
adamc@227
|
181
|
adamc@227
|
182 [[
|
adamc@227
|
183 Inductive exp : Set -> Set :=
|
adamc@227
|
184 | Const : forall T : Set, T -> exp T
|
adamc@227
|
185 | Pair : forall T1 T2, exp T1 -> exp T2 -> exp (T1 * T2)
|
adamc@227
|
186 | Eq : forall T, exp T -> exp T -> exp bool.
|
adamc@227
|
187
|
adamc@227
|
188 Error: Large non-propositional inductive types must be in Type.
|
adamc@227
|
189
|
adamc@227
|
190 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
191
|
adamc@227
|
192 This definition is %\textit{%#<i>#large#</i>#%}% in the sense that at least one of its constructors takes an argument whose type has type [Type]. Coq would be inconsistent if we allowed definitions like this one in their full generality. Instead, we must change [exp] to live in [Type]. We will go even further and move [exp]'s index to [Type] as well. *)
|
adamc@227
|
193
|
adamc@227
|
194 Inductive exp : Type -> Type :=
|
adamc@227
|
195 | Const : forall T, T -> exp T
|
adamc@227
|
196 | Pair : forall T1 T2, exp T1 -> exp T2 -> exp (T1 * T2)
|
adamc@227
|
197 | Eq : forall T, exp T -> exp T -> exp bool.
|
adamc@227
|
198
|
adamc@228
|
199 (** Note that before we had to include an annotation [: Set] for the variable [T] in [Const]'s type, but we need no annotation now. When the type of a variable is not known, and when that variable is used in a context where only types are allowed, Coq infers that the variable is of type [Type]. That is the right behavior here, but it was wrong for the [Set] version of [exp].
|
adamc@228
|
200
|
adamc@228
|
201 Our new definition is accepted. We can build some sample expressions. *)
|
adamc@227
|
202
|
adamc@227
|
203 Check Const 0.
|
adamc@227
|
204 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
205 Const 0
|
adamc@227
|
206 : exp nat
|
adam@302
|
207 ]]
|
adam@302
|
208 *)
|
adamc@227
|
209
|
adamc@227
|
210 Check Pair (Const 0) (Const tt).
|
adamc@227
|
211 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
212 Pair (Const 0) (Const tt)
|
adamc@227
|
213 : exp (nat * unit)
|
adam@302
|
214 ]]
|
adam@302
|
215 *)
|
adamc@227
|
216
|
adamc@227
|
217 Check Eq (Const Set) (Const Type).
|
adamc@227
|
218 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@228
|
219 Eq (Const Set) (Const Type $ Top.59 ^ )
|
adamc@227
|
220 : exp bool
|
adamc@227
|
221
|
adamc@227
|
222 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
223
|
adamc@227
|
224 We can check many expressions, including fancy expressions that include types. However, it is not hard to hit a type-checking wall.
|
adamc@227
|
225
|
adamc@227
|
226 [[
|
adamc@227
|
227 Check Const (Const O).
|
adamc@227
|
228
|
adamc@227
|
229 Error: Universe inconsistency (cannot enforce Top.42 < Top.42).
|
adamc@227
|
230
|
adamc@227
|
231 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
232
|
adamc@227
|
233 We are unable to instantiate the parameter [T] of [Const] with an [exp] type. To see why, it is helpful to print the annotated version of [exp]'s inductive definition. *)
|
adamc@227
|
234
|
adamc@227
|
235 Print exp.
|
adamc@227
|
236 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
237 Inductive exp
|
adamc@227
|
238 : Type $ Top.8 ^ ->
|
adamc@227
|
239 Type
|
adamc@227
|
240 $ max(0, (Top.11)+1, (Top.14)+1, (Top.15)+1, (Top.19)+1) ^ :=
|
adamc@227
|
241 Const : forall T : Type $ Top.11 ^ , T -> exp T
|
adamc@227
|
242 | Pair : forall (T1 : Type $ Top.14 ^ ) (T2 : Type $ Top.15 ^ ),
|
adamc@227
|
243 exp T1 -> exp T2 -> exp (T1 * T2)
|
adamc@227
|
244 | Eq : forall T : Type $ Top.19 ^ , exp T -> exp T -> exp bool
|
adamc@227
|
245
|
adamc@227
|
246 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
247
|
adamc@227
|
248 We see that the index type of [exp] has been assigned to universe level [Top.8]. In addition, each of the four occurrences of [Type] in the types of the constructors gets its own universe variable. Each of these variables appears explicitly in the type of [exp]. In particular, any type [exp T] lives at a universe level found by incrementing by one the maximum of the four argument variables. A consequence of this is that [exp] %\textit{%#<i>#must#</i>#%}% live at a higher universe level than any type which may be passed to one of its constructors. This consequence led to the universe inconsistency.
|
adamc@227
|
249
|
adam@287
|
250 Strangely, the universe variable [Top.8] only appears in one place. Is there no restriction imposed on which types are valid arguments to [exp]? In fact, there is a restriction, but it only appears in a global set of universe constraints that are maintained %``%#"#off to the side,#"#%''% not appearing explicitly in types. We can print the current database. *)
|
adamc@227
|
251
|
adamc@227
|
252 Print Universes.
|
adamc@227
|
253 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
254 Top.19 < Top.9 <= Top.8
|
adamc@227
|
255 Top.15 < Top.9 <= Top.8 <= Coq.Init.Datatypes.38
|
adamc@227
|
256 Top.14 < Top.9 <= Top.8 <= Coq.Init.Datatypes.37
|
adamc@227
|
257 Top.11 < Top.9 <= Top.8
|
adamc@227
|
258
|
adamc@227
|
259 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
260
|
adamc@227
|
261 [Print Universes] outputs many more constraints, but we have collected only those that mention [Top] variables. We see one constraint for each universe variable associated with a constructor argument from [exp]'s definition. [Top.19] is the type argument to [Eq]. The constraint for [Top.19] effectively says that [Top.19] must be less than [Top.8], the universe of [exp]'s indices; an intermediate variable [Top.9] appears as an artifact of the way the constraint was generated.
|
adamc@227
|
262
|
adamc@227
|
263 The next constraint, for [Top.15], is more complicated. This is the universe of the second argument to the [Pair] constructor. Not only must [Top.15] be less than [Top.8], but it also comes out that [Top.8] must be less than [Coq.Init.Datatypes.38]. What is this new universe variable? It is from the definition of the [prod] inductive family, to which types of the form [A * B] are desugared. *)
|
adamc@227
|
264
|
adamc@227
|
265 Print prod.
|
adamc@227
|
266 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
267 Inductive prod (A : Type $ Coq.Init.Datatypes.37 ^ )
|
adamc@227
|
268 (B : Type $ Coq.Init.Datatypes.38 ^ )
|
adamc@227
|
269 : Type $ max(Coq.Init.Datatypes.37, Coq.Init.Datatypes.38) ^ :=
|
adamc@227
|
270 pair : A -> B -> A * B
|
adamc@227
|
271
|
adamc@227
|
272 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
273
|
adamc@227
|
274 We see that the constraint is enforcing that indices to [exp] must not live in a higher universe level than [B]-indices to [prod]. The next constraint above establishes a symmetric condition for [A].
|
adamc@227
|
275
|
adamc@227
|
276 Thus it is apparent that Coq maintains a tortuous set of universe variable inequalities behind the scenes. It may look like some functions are polymorphic in the universe levels of their arguments, but what is really happening is imperative updating of a system of constraints, such that all uses of a function are consistent with a global set of universe levels. When the constraint system may not be evolved soundly, we get a universe inconsistency error.
|
adamc@227
|
277
|
adamc@227
|
278 %\medskip%
|
adamc@227
|
279
|
adamc@227
|
280 Something interesting is revealed in the annotated definition of [prod]. A type [prod A B] lives at a universe that is the maximum of the universes of [A] and [B]. From our earlier experiments, we might expect that [prod]'s universe would in fact need to be %\textit{%#<i>#one higher#</i>#%}% than the maximum. The critical difference is that, in the definition of [prod], [A] and [B] are defined as %\textit{%#<i>#parameters#</i>#%}%; that is, they appear named to the left of the main colon, rather than appearing (possibly unnamed) to the right.
|
adamc@227
|
281
|
adamc@231
|
282 Parameters are not as flexible as normal inductive type arguments. The range types of all of the constructors of a parameterized type must share the same parameters. Nonetheless, when it is possible to define a polymorphic type in this way, we gain the ability to use the new type family in more ways, without triggering universe inconsistencies. For instance, nested pairs of types are perfectly legal. *)
|
adamc@227
|
283
|
adamc@227
|
284 Check (nat, (Type, Set)).
|
adamc@227
|
285 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
286 (nat, (Type $ Top.44 ^ , Set))
|
adamc@227
|
287 : Set * (Type $ Top.45 ^ * Type $ Top.46 ^ )
|
adamc@227
|
288
|
adamc@227
|
289 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
290
|
adamc@227
|
291 The same cannot be done with a counterpart to [prod] that does not use parameters. *)
|
adamc@227
|
292
|
adamc@227
|
293 Inductive prod' : Type -> Type -> Type :=
|
adamc@227
|
294 | pair' : forall A B : Type, A -> B -> prod' A B.
|
adamc@227
|
295
|
adamc@227
|
296 (** [[
|
adamc@227
|
297 Check (pair' nat (pair' Type Set)).
|
adamc@227
|
298
|
adamc@227
|
299 Error: Universe inconsistency (cannot enforce Top.51 < Top.51).
|
adamc@227
|
300
|
adamc@227
|
301 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
302
|
adamc@233
|
303 The key benefit parameters bring us is the ability to avoid quantifying over types in the types of constructors. Such quantification induces less-than constraints, while parameters only introduce less-than-or-equal-to constraints.
|
adamc@233
|
304
|
adamc@233
|
305 Coq includes one more (potentially confusing) feature related to parameters. While Gallina does not support real universe polymorphism, there is a convenience facility that mimics universe polymorphism in some cases. We can illustrate what this means with a simple example. *)
|
adamc@233
|
306
|
adamc@233
|
307 Inductive foo (A : Type) : Type :=
|
adamc@233
|
308 | Foo : A -> foo A.
|
adamc@229
|
309
|
adamc@229
|
310 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@229
|
311 Unset Printing Universes.
|
adamc@229
|
312 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@229
|
313
|
adamc@233
|
314 Check foo nat.
|
adamc@233
|
315 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@233
|
316 foo nat
|
adamc@233
|
317 : Set
|
adam@302
|
318 ]]
|
adam@302
|
319 *)
|
adamc@233
|
320
|
adamc@233
|
321 Check foo Set.
|
adamc@233
|
322 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@233
|
323 foo Set
|
adamc@233
|
324 : Type
|
adam@302
|
325 ]]
|
adam@302
|
326 *)
|
adamc@233
|
327
|
adamc@233
|
328 Check foo True.
|
adamc@233
|
329 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@233
|
330 foo True
|
adamc@233
|
331 : Prop
|
adamc@233
|
332
|
adamc@233
|
333 ]]
|
adamc@233
|
334
|
adam@287
|
335 The basic pattern here is that Coq is willing to automatically build a %``%#"#copied-and-pasted#"#%''% version of an inductive definition, where some occurrences of [Type] have been replaced by [Set] or [Prop]. In each context, the type-checker tries to find the valid replacements that are lowest in the type hierarchy. Automatic cloning of definitions can be much more convenient than manual cloning. We have already taken advantage of the fact that we may re-use the same families of tuple and list types to form values in [Set] and [Type].
|
adamc@233
|
336
|
adamc@233
|
337 Imitation polymorphism can be confusing in some contexts. For instance, it is what is responsible for this weird behavior. *)
|
adamc@233
|
338
|
adamc@233
|
339 Inductive bar : Type := Bar : bar.
|
adamc@233
|
340
|
adamc@233
|
341 Check bar.
|
adamc@233
|
342 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@233
|
343 bar
|
adamc@233
|
344 : Prop
|
adamc@233
|
345
|
adamc@233
|
346 ]]
|
adamc@233
|
347
|
adamc@233
|
348 The type that Coq comes up with may be used in strictly more contexts than the type one might have expected. *)
|
adamc@233
|
349
|
adamc@229
|
350
|
adamc@229
|
351 (** * The [Prop] Universe *)
|
adamc@229
|
352
|
adam@287
|
353 (** In Chapter 4, we saw parallel versions of useful datatypes for %``%#"#programs#"#%''% and %``%#"#proofs.#"#%''% The convention was that programs live in [Set], and proofs live in [Prop]. We gave little explanation for why it is useful to maintain this distinction. There is certainly documentation value from separating programs from proofs; in practice, different concerns apply to building the two types of objects. It turns out, however, that these concerns motivate formal differences between the two universes in Coq.
|
adamc@229
|
354
|
adamc@229
|
355 Recall the types [sig] and [ex], which are the program and proof versions of existential quantification. Their definitions differ only in one place, where [sig] uses [Type] and [ex] uses [Prop]. *)
|
adamc@229
|
356
|
adamc@229
|
357 Print sig.
|
adamc@229
|
358 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@229
|
359 Inductive sig (A : Type) (P : A -> Prop) : Type :=
|
adamc@229
|
360 exist : forall x : A, P x -> sig P
|
adam@302
|
361 ]]
|
adam@302
|
362 *)
|
adamc@229
|
363
|
adamc@229
|
364 Print ex.
|
adamc@229
|
365 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@229
|
366 Inductive ex (A : Type) (P : A -> Prop) : Prop :=
|
adamc@229
|
367 ex_intro : forall x : A, P x -> ex P
|
adamc@229
|
368
|
adamc@229
|
369 ]]
|
adamc@229
|
370
|
adamc@229
|
371 It is natural to want a function to extract the first components of data structures like these. Doing so is easy enough for [sig]. *)
|
adamc@229
|
372
|
adamc@229
|
373 Definition projS A (P : A -> Prop) (x : sig P) : A :=
|
adamc@229
|
374 match x with
|
adamc@229
|
375 | exist v _ => v
|
adamc@229
|
376 end.
|
adamc@229
|
377
|
adamc@229
|
378 (** We run into trouble with a version that has been changed to work with [ex].
|
adamc@229
|
379
|
adamc@229
|
380 [[
|
adamc@229
|
381 Definition projE A (P : A -> Prop) (x : ex P) : A :=
|
adamc@229
|
382 match x with
|
adamc@229
|
383 | ex_intro v _ => v
|
adamc@229
|
384 end.
|
adamc@229
|
385
|
adamc@229
|
386 Error:
|
adamc@229
|
387 Incorrect elimination of "x" in the inductive type "ex":
|
adamc@229
|
388 the return type has sort "Type" while it should be "Prop".
|
adamc@229
|
389 Elimination of an inductive object of sort Prop
|
adamc@229
|
390 is not allowed on a predicate in sort Type
|
adamc@229
|
391 because proofs can be eliminated only to build proofs.
|
adamc@229
|
392
|
adamc@229
|
393 ]]
|
adamc@229
|
394
|
adam@287
|
395 In formal Coq parlance, %``%#"#limination#"#%''% means %``%#"#pattern-matching.#"#%''% The typing rules of Gallina forbid us from pattern-matching on a discriminee whose type belongs to [Prop], whenever the result type of the [match] has a type besides [Prop]. This is a sort of %``%#"#information flow#"#%''% policy, where the type system ensures that the details of proofs can never have any effect on parts of a development that are not also marked as proofs.
|
adamc@229
|
396
|
adamc@229
|
397 This restriction matches informal practice. We think of programs and proofs as clearly separated, and, outside of constructive logic, the idea of computing with proofs is ill-formed. The distinction also has practical importance in Coq, where it affects the behavior of extraction.
|
adamc@229
|
398
|
adamc@229
|
399 Recall that extraction is Coq's facility for translating Coq developments into programs in general-purpose programming languages like OCaml. Extraction %\textit{%#<i>#erases#</i>#%}% proofs and leaves programs intact. A simple example with [sig] and [ex] demonstrates the distinction. *)
|
adamc@229
|
400
|
adamc@229
|
401 Definition sym_sig (x : sig (fun n => n = 0)) : sig (fun n => 0 = n) :=
|
adamc@229
|
402 match x with
|
adamc@229
|
403 | exist n pf => exist _ n (sym_eq pf)
|
adamc@229
|
404 end.
|
adamc@229
|
405
|
adamc@229
|
406 Extraction sym_sig.
|
adamc@229
|
407 (** <<
|
adamc@229
|
408 (** val sym_sig : nat -> nat **)
|
adamc@229
|
409
|
adamc@229
|
410 let sym_sig x = x
|
adamc@229
|
411 >>
|
adamc@229
|
412
|
adamc@229
|
413 Since extraction erases proofs, the second components of [sig] values are elided, making [sig] a simple identity type family. The [sym_sig] operation is thus an identity function. *)
|
adamc@229
|
414
|
adamc@229
|
415 Definition sym_ex (x : ex (fun n => n = 0)) : ex (fun n => 0 = n) :=
|
adamc@229
|
416 match x with
|
adamc@229
|
417 | ex_intro n pf => ex_intro _ n (sym_eq pf)
|
adamc@229
|
418 end.
|
adamc@229
|
419
|
adamc@229
|
420 Extraction sym_ex.
|
adamc@229
|
421 (** <<
|
adamc@229
|
422 (** val sym_ex : __ **)
|
adamc@229
|
423
|
adamc@229
|
424 let sym_ex = __
|
adamc@229
|
425 >>
|
adamc@229
|
426
|
adam@302
|
427 In this example, the [ex] type itself is in [Prop], so whole [ex] packages are erased. Coq extracts every proposition as the (Coq-specific) type %\texttt{\_\_}%#<tt>__</tt>#, whose single constructor is %\texttt{\_\_}%#<tt>__</tt>#. Not only are proofs replaced by [__], but proof arguments to functions are also removed completely, as we see here.
|
adamc@229
|
428
|
adamc@229
|
429 Extraction is very helpful as an optimization over programs that contain proofs. In languages like Haskell, advanced features make it possible to program with proofs, as a way of convincing the type checker to accept particular definitions. Unfortunately, when proofs are encoded as values in GADTs, these proofs exist at runtime and consume resources. In contrast, with Coq, as long as you keep all of your proofs within [Prop], extraction is guaranteed to erase them.
|
adamc@229
|
430
|
adamc@229
|
431 Many fans of the Curry-Howard correspondence support the idea of %\textit{%#<i>#extracting programs from proofs#</i>#%}%. In reality, few users of Coq and related tools do any such thing. Instead, extraction is better thought of as an optimization that reduces the runtime costs of expressive typing.
|
adamc@229
|
432
|
adamc@229
|
433 %\medskip%
|
adamc@229
|
434
|
adamc@229
|
435 We have seen two of the differences between proofs and programs: proofs are subject to an elimination restriction and are elided by extraction. The remaining difference is that [Prop] is %\textit{%#<i>#impredicative#</i>#%}%, as this example shows. *)
|
adamc@229
|
436
|
adamc@229
|
437 Check forall P Q : Prop, P \/ Q -> Q \/ P.
|
adamc@229
|
438 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@229
|
439 forall P Q : Prop, P \/ Q -> Q \/ P
|
adamc@229
|
440 : Prop
|
adamc@229
|
441
|
adamc@229
|
442 ]]
|
adamc@229
|
443
|
adamc@230
|
444 We see that it is possible to define a [Prop] that quantifies over other [Prop]s. This is fortunate, as we start wanting that ability even for such basic purposes as stating propositional tautologies. In the next section of this chapter, we will see some reasons why unrestricted impredicativity is undesirable. The impredicativity of [Prop] interacts crucially with the elimination restriction to avoid those pitfalls.
|
adamc@230
|
445
|
adamc@230
|
446 Impredicativity also allows us to implement a version of our earlier [exp] type that does not suffer from the weakness that we found. *)
|
adamc@230
|
447
|
adamc@230
|
448 Inductive expP : Type -> Prop :=
|
adamc@230
|
449 | ConstP : forall T, T -> expP T
|
adamc@230
|
450 | PairP : forall T1 T2, expP T1 -> expP T2 -> expP (T1 * T2)
|
adamc@230
|
451 | EqP : forall T, expP T -> expP T -> expP bool.
|
adamc@230
|
452
|
adamc@230
|
453 Check ConstP 0.
|
adamc@230
|
454 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
455 ConstP 0
|
adamc@230
|
456 : expP nat
|
adam@302
|
457 ]]
|
adam@302
|
458 *)
|
adamc@230
|
459
|
adamc@230
|
460 Check PairP (ConstP 0) (ConstP tt).
|
adamc@230
|
461 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
462 PairP (ConstP 0) (ConstP tt)
|
adamc@230
|
463 : expP (nat * unit)
|
adam@302
|
464 ]]
|
adam@302
|
465 *)
|
adamc@230
|
466
|
adamc@230
|
467 Check EqP (ConstP Set) (ConstP Type).
|
adamc@230
|
468 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
469 EqP (ConstP Set) (ConstP Type)
|
adamc@230
|
470 : expP bool
|
adam@302
|
471 ]]
|
adam@302
|
472 *)
|
adamc@230
|
473
|
adamc@230
|
474 Check ConstP (ConstP O).
|
adamc@230
|
475 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
476 ConstP (ConstP 0)
|
adamc@230
|
477 : expP (expP nat)
|
adamc@230
|
478
|
adamc@230
|
479 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
480
|
adam@287
|
481 In this case, our victory is really a shallow one. As we have marked [expP] as a family of proofs, we cannot deconstruct our expressions in the usual programmatic ways, which makes them almost useless for the usual purposes. Impredicative quantification is much more useful in defining inductive families that we really think of as judgments. For instance, this code defines a notion of equality that is strictly more permissive than the base equality [=]. *)
|
adamc@230
|
482
|
adamc@230
|
483 Inductive eqPlus : forall T, T -> T -> Prop :=
|
adamc@230
|
484 | Base : forall T (x : T), eqPlus x x
|
adamc@230
|
485 | Func : forall dom ran (f1 f2 : dom -> ran),
|
adamc@230
|
486 (forall x : dom, eqPlus (f1 x) (f2 x))
|
adamc@230
|
487 -> eqPlus f1 f2.
|
adamc@230
|
488
|
adamc@230
|
489 Check (Base 0).
|
adamc@230
|
490 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
491 Base 0
|
adamc@230
|
492 : eqPlus 0 0
|
adam@302
|
493 ]]
|
adam@302
|
494 *)
|
adamc@230
|
495
|
adamc@230
|
496 Check (Func (fun n => n) (fun n => 0 + n) (fun n => Base n)).
|
adamc@230
|
497 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
498 Func (fun n : nat => n) (fun n : nat => 0 + n) (fun n : nat => Base n)
|
adamc@230
|
499 : eqPlus (fun n : nat => n) (fun n : nat => 0 + n)
|
adam@302
|
500 ]]
|
adam@302
|
501 *)
|
adamc@230
|
502
|
adamc@230
|
503 Check (Base (Base 1)).
|
adamc@230
|
504 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
505 Base (Base 1)
|
adamc@230
|
506 : eqPlus (Base 1) (Base 1)
|
adam@302
|
507 ]]
|
adam@302
|
508 *)
|
adamc@230
|
509
|
adamc@230
|
510
|
adamc@230
|
511 (** * Axioms *)
|
adamc@230
|
512
|
adamc@230
|
513 (** While the specific logic Gallina is hardcoded into Coq's implementation, it is possible to add certain logical rules in a controlled way. In other words, Coq may be used to reason about many different refinements of Gallina where strictly more theorems are provable. We achieve this by asserting %\textit{%#<i>#axioms#</i>#%}% without proof.
|
adamc@230
|
514
|
adamc@230
|
515 We will motivate the idea by touring through some standard axioms, as enumerated in Coq's online FAQ. I will add additional commentary as appropriate. *)
|
adamc@230
|
516
|
adamc@230
|
517 (** ** The Basics *)
|
adamc@230
|
518
|
adamc@231
|
519 (** One simple example of a useful axiom is the law of the excluded middle. *)
|
adamc@230
|
520
|
adamc@230
|
521 Require Import Classical_Prop.
|
adamc@230
|
522 Print classic.
|
adamc@230
|
523 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
524 *** [ classic : forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P ]
|
adamc@230
|
525
|
adamc@230
|
526 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
527
|
adamc@230
|
528 In the implementation of module [Classical_Prop], this axiom was defined with the command *)
|
adamc@230
|
529
|
adamc@230
|
530 Axiom classic : forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P.
|
adamc@230
|
531
|
adamc@230
|
532 (** An [Axiom] may be declared with any type, in any of the universes. There is a synonym [Parameter] for [Axiom], and that synonym is often clearer for assertions not of type [Prop]. For instance, we can assert the existence of objects with certain properties. *)
|
adamc@230
|
533
|
adamc@230
|
534 Parameter n : nat.
|
adamc@230
|
535 Axiom positive : n > 0.
|
adamc@230
|
536 Reset n.
|
adamc@230
|
537
|
adam@287
|
538 (** This kind of %``%#"#axiomatic presentation#"#%''% of a theory is very common outside of higher-order logic. However, in Coq, it is almost always preferable to stick to defining your objects, functions, and predicates via inductive definitions and functional programming.
|
adamc@230
|
539
|
adamc@230
|
540 In general, there is a significant burden associated with any use of axioms. It is easy to assert a set of axioms that together is %\textit{%#<i>#inconsistent#</i>#%}%. That is, a set of axioms may imply [False], which allows any theorem to proved, which defeats the purpose of a proof assistant. For example, we could assert the following axiom, which is consistent by itself but inconsistent when combined with [classic]. *)
|
adamc@230
|
541
|
adam@287
|
542 Axiom not_classic : ~ forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P.
|
adamc@230
|
543
|
adamc@230
|
544 Theorem uhoh : False.
|
adam@287
|
545 generalize classic not_classic; tauto.
|
adamc@230
|
546 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
547
|
adamc@230
|
548 Theorem uhoh_again : 1 + 1 = 3.
|
adamc@230
|
549 destruct uhoh.
|
adamc@230
|
550 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
551
|
adamc@230
|
552 Reset not_classic.
|
adamc@230
|
553
|
adam@287
|
554 (** On the subject of the law of the excluded middle itself, this axiom is usually quite harmless, and many practical Coq developments assume it. It has been proved metatheoretically to be consistent with CIC. Here, %``%#"#proved metatheoretically#"#%''% means that someone proved on paper that excluded middle holds in a %\textit{%#<i>#model#</i>#%}% of CIC in set theory. All of the other axioms that we will survey in this section hold in the same model, so they are all consistent together.
|
adamc@230
|
555
|
adamc@230
|
556 Recall that Coq implements %\textit{%#<i>#constructive#</i>#%}% logic by default, where excluded middle is not provable. Proofs in constructive logic can be thought of as programs. A [forall] quantifier denotes a dependent function type, and a disjunction denotes a variant type. In such a setting, excluded middle could be interpreted as a decision procedure for arbitrary propositions, which computability theory tells us cannot exist. Thus, constructive logic with excluded middle can no longer be associated with our usual notion of programming.
|
adamc@230
|
557
|
adamc@231
|
558 Given all this, why is it all right to assert excluded middle as an axiom? The intuitive justification is that the elimination restriction for [Prop] prevents us from treating proofs as programs. An excluded middle axiom that quantified over [Set] instead of [Prop] %\textit{%#<i>#would#</i>#%}% be problematic. If a development used that axiom, we would not be able to extract the code to OCaml (soundly) without implementing a genuine universal decision procedure. In contrast, values whose types belong to [Prop] are always erased by extraction, so we sidestep the axiom's algorithmic consequences.
|
adamc@230
|
559
|
adamc@230
|
560 Because the proper use of axioms is so precarious, there are helpful commands for determining which axioms a theorem relies on. *)
|
adamc@230
|
561
|
adamc@230
|
562 Theorem t1 : forall P : Prop, P -> ~ ~ P.
|
adamc@230
|
563 tauto.
|
adamc@230
|
564 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
565
|
adamc@230
|
566 Print Assumptions t1.
|
adamc@230
|
567 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
568 Closed under the global context
|
adam@302
|
569 ]]
|
adam@302
|
570 *)
|
adamc@230
|
571
|
adamc@230
|
572 Theorem t2 : forall P : Prop, ~ ~ P -> P.
|
adamc@230
|
573 (** [[
|
adamc@230
|
574 tauto.
|
adamc@230
|
575
|
adamc@230
|
576 Error: tauto failed.
|
adamc@230
|
577
|
adam@302
|
578 ]]
|
adam@302
|
579 *)
|
adamc@230
|
580
|
adamc@230
|
581 intro P; destruct (classic P); tauto.
|
adamc@230
|
582 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
583
|
adamc@230
|
584 Print Assumptions t2.
|
adamc@230
|
585 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
586 Axioms:
|
adamc@230
|
587 classic : forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P
|
adamc@230
|
588
|
adamc@230
|
589 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
590
|
adamc@231
|
591 It is possible to avoid this dependence in some specific cases, where excluded middle %\textit{%#<i>#is#</i>#%}% provable, for decidable families of propositions. *)
|
adamc@230
|
592
|
adam@287
|
593 Theorem nat_eq_dec : forall n m : nat, n = m \/ n <> m.
|
adamc@230
|
594 induction n; destruct m; intuition; generalize (IHn m); intuition.
|
adamc@230
|
595 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
596
|
adamc@230
|
597 Theorem t2' : forall n m : nat, ~ ~ (n = m) -> n = m.
|
adam@287
|
598 intros n m; destruct (nat_eq_dec n m); tauto.
|
adamc@230
|
599 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
600
|
adamc@230
|
601 Print Assumptions t2'.
|
adamc@230
|
602 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
603 Closed under the global context
|
adamc@230
|
604 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
605
|
adamc@230
|
606 %\bigskip%
|
adamc@230
|
607
|
adamc@230
|
608 Mainstream mathematical practice assumes excluded middle, so it can be useful to have it available in Coq developments, though it is also nice to know that a theorem is proved in a simpler formal system than classical logic. There is a similar story for %\textit{%#<i>#proof irrelevance#</i>#%}%, which simplifies proof issues that would not even arise in mainstream math. *)
|
adamc@230
|
609
|
adamc@230
|
610 Require Import ProofIrrelevance.
|
adamc@230
|
611 Print proof_irrelevance.
|
adamc@230
|
612 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
613 *** [ proof_irrelevance : forall (P : Prop) (p1 p2 : P), p1 = p2 ]
|
adamc@230
|
614
|
adamc@230
|
615 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
616
|
adamc@231
|
617 This axiom asserts that any two proofs of the same proposition are equal. If we replaced [p1 = p2] by [p1 <-> p2], then the statement would be provable. However, equality is a stronger notion than logical equivalence. Recall this example function from Chapter 6. *)
|
adamc@230
|
618
|
adamc@230
|
619 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@230
|
620 Lemma zgtz : 0 > 0 -> False.
|
adamc@230
|
621 crush.
|
adamc@230
|
622 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
623 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@230
|
624
|
adamc@230
|
625 Definition pred_strong1 (n : nat) : n > 0 -> nat :=
|
adamc@230
|
626 match n with
|
adamc@230
|
627 | O => fun pf : 0 > 0 => match zgtz pf with end
|
adamc@230
|
628 | S n' => fun _ => n'
|
adamc@230
|
629 end.
|
adamc@230
|
630
|
adamc@230
|
631 (** We might want to prove that different proofs of [n > 0] do not lead to different results from our richly-typed predecessor function. *)
|
adamc@230
|
632
|
adamc@230
|
633 Theorem pred_strong1_irrel : forall n (pf1 pf2 : n > 0), pred_strong1 pf1 = pred_strong1 pf2.
|
adamc@230
|
634 destruct n; crush.
|
adamc@230
|
635 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
636
|
adamc@230
|
637 (** The proof script is simple, but it involved peeking into the definition of [pred_strong1]. For more complicated function definitions, it can be considerably more work to prove that they do not discriminate on details of proof arguments. This can seem like a shame, since the [Prop] elimination restriction makes it impossible to write any function that does otherwise. Unfortunately, this fact is only true metatheoretically, unless we assert an axiom like [proof_irrelevance]. With that axiom, we can prove our theorem without consulting the definition of [pred_strong1]. *)
|
adamc@230
|
638
|
adamc@230
|
639 Theorem pred_strong1_irrel' : forall n (pf1 pf2 : n > 0), pred_strong1 pf1 = pred_strong1 pf2.
|
adamc@230
|
640 intros; f_equal; apply proof_irrelevance.
|
adamc@230
|
641 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
642
|
adamc@230
|
643
|
adamc@230
|
644 (** %\bigskip%
|
adamc@230
|
645
|
adamc@230
|
646 In the chapter on equality, we already discussed some axioms that are related to proof irrelevance. In particular, Coq's standard library includes this axiom: *)
|
adamc@230
|
647
|
adamc@230
|
648 Require Import Eqdep.
|
adamc@230
|
649 Import Eq_rect_eq.
|
adamc@230
|
650 Print eq_rect_eq.
|
adamc@230
|
651 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
652 *** [ eq_rect_eq :
|
adamc@230
|
653 forall (U : Type) (p : U) (Q : U -> Type) (x : Q p) (h : p = p),
|
adamc@230
|
654 x = eq_rect p Q x p h ]
|
adamc@230
|
655
|
adamc@230
|
656 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
657
|
adamc@230
|
658 This axiom says that it is permissible to simplify pattern matches over proofs of equalities like [e = e]. The axiom is logically equivalent to some simpler corollaries. *)
|
adamc@230
|
659
|
adamc@230
|
660 Corollary UIP_refl : forall A (x : A) (pf : x = x), pf = refl_equal x.
|
adamc@230
|
661 intros; replace pf with (eq_rect x (eq x) (refl_equal x) x pf); [
|
adamc@230
|
662 symmetry; apply eq_rect_eq
|
adamc@230
|
663 | exact (match pf as pf' return match pf' in _ = y return x = y with
|
adamc@230
|
664 | refl_equal => refl_equal x
|
adamc@230
|
665 end = pf' with
|
adamc@230
|
666 | refl_equal => refl_equal _
|
adamc@230
|
667 end) ].
|
adamc@230
|
668 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
669
|
adamc@230
|
670 Corollary UIP : forall A (x y : A) (pf1 pf2 : x = y), pf1 = pf2.
|
adamc@230
|
671 intros; generalize pf1 pf2; subst; intros;
|
adamc@230
|
672 match goal with
|
adamc@230
|
673 | [ |- ?pf1 = ?pf2 ] => rewrite (UIP_refl pf1); rewrite (UIP_refl pf2); reflexivity
|
adamc@230
|
674 end.
|
adamc@230
|
675 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
676
|
adamc@231
|
677 (** These corollaries are special cases of proof irrelevance. In developments that only need proof irrelevance for equality, there is no need to assert full irrelevance.
|
adamc@230
|
678
|
adamc@230
|
679 Another facet of proof irrelevance is that, like excluded middle, it is often provable for specific propositions. For instance, [UIP] is provable whenever the type [A] has a decidable equality operation. The module [Eqdep_dec] of the standard library contains a proof. A similar phenomenon applies to other notable cases, including less-than proofs. Thus, it is often possible to use proof irrelevance without asserting axioms.
|
adamc@230
|
680
|
adamc@230
|
681 %\bigskip%
|
adamc@230
|
682
|
adamc@230
|
683 There are two more basic axioms that are often assumed, to avoid complications that do not arise in set theory. *)
|
adamc@230
|
684
|
adamc@230
|
685 Require Import FunctionalExtensionality.
|
adamc@230
|
686 Print functional_extensionality_dep.
|
adamc@230
|
687 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
688 *** [ functional_extensionality_dep :
|
adamc@230
|
689 forall (A : Type) (B : A -> Type) (f g : forall x : A, B x),
|
adamc@230
|
690 (forall x : A, f x = g x) -> f = g ]
|
adamc@230
|
691
|
adamc@230
|
692 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
693
|
adamc@230
|
694 This axiom says that two functions are equal if they map equal inputs to equal outputs. Such facts are not provable in general in CIC, but it is consistent to assume that they are.
|
adamc@230
|
695
|
adamc@230
|
696 A simple corollary shows that the same property applies to predicates. In some cases, one might prefer to assert this corollary as the axiom, to restrict the consequences to proofs and not programs. *)
|
adamc@230
|
697
|
adamc@230
|
698 Corollary predicate_extensionality : forall (A : Type) (B : A -> Prop) (f g : forall x : A, B x),
|
adamc@230
|
699 (forall x : A, f x = g x) -> f = g.
|
adamc@230
|
700 intros; apply functional_extensionality_dep; assumption.
|
adamc@230
|
701 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
702
|
adamc@230
|
703
|
adamc@230
|
704 (** ** Axioms of Choice *)
|
adamc@230
|
705
|
adamc@230
|
706 (** Some Coq axioms are also points of contention in mainstream math. The most prominent example is the axiom of choice. In fact, there are multiple versions that we might consider, and, considered in isolation, none of these versions means quite what it means in classical set theory.
|
adamc@230
|
707
|
adamc@230
|
708 First, it is possible to implement a choice operator %\textit{%#<i>#without#</i>#%}% axioms in some potentially surprising cases. *)
|
adamc@230
|
709
|
adamc@230
|
710 Require Import ConstructiveEpsilon.
|
adamc@230
|
711 Check constructive_definite_description.
|
adamc@230
|
712 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
713 constructive_definite_description
|
adamc@230
|
714 : forall (A : Set) (f : A -> nat) (g : nat -> A),
|
adamc@230
|
715 (forall x : A, g (f x) = x) ->
|
adamc@230
|
716 forall P : A -> Prop,
|
adamc@230
|
717 (forall x : A, {P x} + {~ P x}) ->
|
adamc@230
|
718 (exists! x : A, P x) -> {x : A | P x}
|
adam@302
|
719 ]]
|
adam@302
|
720 *)
|
adamc@230
|
721
|
adamc@230
|
722 Print Assumptions constructive_definite_description.
|
adamc@230
|
723 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
724 Closed under the global context
|
adamc@230
|
725
|
adamc@230
|
726 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
727
|
adamc@231
|
728 This function transforms a decidable predicate [P] into a function that produces an element satisfying [P] from a proof that such an element exists. The functions [f] and [g], in conjunction with an associated injectivity property, are used to express the idea that the set [A] is countable. Under these conditions, a simple brute force algorithm gets the job done: we just enumerate all elements of [A], stopping when we find one satisfying [P]. The existence proof, specified in terms of %\textit{%#<i>#unique#</i>#%}% existence [exists!], guarantees termination. The definition of this operator in Coq uses some interesting techniques, as seen in the implementation of the [ConstructiveEpsilon] module.
|
adamc@230
|
729
|
adamc@230
|
730 Countable choice is provable in set theory without appealing to the general axiom of choice. To support the more general principle in Coq, we must also add an axiom. Here is a functional version of the axiom of unique choice. *)
|
adamc@230
|
731
|
adamc@230
|
732 Require Import ClassicalUniqueChoice.
|
adamc@230
|
733 Check dependent_unique_choice.
|
adamc@230
|
734 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
735 dependent_unique_choice
|
adamc@230
|
736 : forall (A : Type) (B : A -> Type) (R : forall x : A, B x -> Prop),
|
adamc@230
|
737 (forall x : A, exists! y : B x, R x y) ->
|
adamc@230
|
738 exists f : forall x : A, B x, forall x : A, R x (f x)
|
adamc@230
|
739
|
adamc@230
|
740 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
741
|
adamc@230
|
742 This axiom lets us convert a relational specification [R] into a function implementing that specification. We need only prove that [R] is truly a function. An alternate, stronger formulation applies to cases where [R] maps each input to one or more outputs. We also simplify the statement of the theorem by considering only non-dependent function types. *)
|
adamc@230
|
743
|
adamc@230
|
744 Require Import ClassicalChoice.
|
adamc@230
|
745 Check choice.
|
adamc@230
|
746 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
747 choice
|
adamc@230
|
748 : forall (A B : Type) (R : A -> B -> Prop),
|
adamc@230
|
749 (forall x : A, exists y : B, R x y) ->
|
adamc@230
|
750 exists f : A -> B, forall x : A, R x (f x)
|
adamc@230
|
751
|
adamc@230
|
752 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
753
|
adamc@230
|
754 This principle is proved as a theorem, based on the unique choice axiom and an additional axiom of relational choice from the [RelationalChoice] module.
|
adamc@230
|
755
|
adamc@230
|
756 In set theory, the axiom of choice is a fundamental philosophical commitment one makes about the universe of sets. In Coq, the choice axioms say something weaker. For instance, consider the simple restatement of the [choice] axiom where we replace existential quantification by its Curry-Howard analogue, subset types. *)
|
adamc@230
|
757
|
adamc@230
|
758 Definition choice_Set (A B : Type) (R : A -> B -> Prop) (H : forall x : A, {y : B | R x y})
|
adamc@230
|
759 : {f : A -> B | forall x : A, R x (f x)} :=
|
adamc@230
|
760 exist (fun f => forall x : A, R x (f x))
|
adamc@230
|
761 (fun x => proj1_sig (H x)) (fun x => proj2_sig (H x)).
|
adamc@230
|
762
|
adam@287
|
763 (** Via the Curry-Howard correspondence, this %``%#"#axiom#"#%''% can be taken to have the same meaning as the original. It is implemented trivially as a transformation not much deeper than uncurrying. Thus, we see that the utility of the axioms that we mentioned earlier comes in their usage to build programs from proofs. Normal set theory has no explicit proofs, so the meaning of the usual axiom of choice is subtlely different. In Gallina, the axioms implement a controlled relaxation of the restrictions on information flow from proofs to programs.
|
adamc@230
|
764
|
adam@287
|
765 However, when we combine an axiom of choice with the law of the excluded middle, the idea of %``%#"#choice#"#%''% becomes more interesting. Excluded middle gives us a highly non-computational way of constructing proofs, but it does not change the computational nature of programs. Thus, the axiom of choice is still giving us a way of translating between two different sorts of %``%#"#programs,#"#%''% but the input programs (which are proofs) may be written in a rich language that goes beyond normal computability. This truly is more than repackaging a function with a different type.
|
adamc@230
|
766
|
adamc@230
|
767 %\bigskip%
|
adamc@230
|
768
|
adamc@230
|
769 The Coq tools support a command-line flag %\texttt{%#<tt>#-impredicative-set#</tt>#%}%, which modifies Gallina in a more fundamental way by making [Set] impredicative. A term like [forall T : Set, T] has type [Set], and inductive definitions in [Set] may have constructors that quantify over arguments of any types. To maintain consistency, an elimination restriction must be imposed, similarly to the restriction for [Prop]. The restriction only applies to large inductive types, where some constructor quantifies over a type of type [Type]. In such cases, a value in this inductive type may only be pattern-matched over to yield a result type whose type is [Set] or [Prop]. This contrasts with [Prop], where the restriction applies even to non-large inductive types, and where the result type may only have type [Prop].
|
adamc@230
|
770
|
adamc@230
|
771 In old versions of Coq, [Set] was impredicative by default. Later versions make [Set] predicative to avoid inconsistency with some classical axioms. In particular, one should watch out when using impredicative [Set] with axioms of choice. In combination with excluded middle or predicate extensionality, this can lead to inconsistency. Impredicative [Set] can be useful for modeling inherently impredicative mathematical concepts, but almost all Coq developments get by fine without it. *)
|
adamc@230
|
772
|
adamc@230
|
773 (** ** Axioms and Computation *)
|
adamc@230
|
774
|
adamc@230
|
775 (** One additional axiom-related wrinkle arises from an aspect of Gallina that is very different from set theory: a notion of %\textit{%#<i>#computational equivalence#</i>#%}% is central to the definition of the formal system. Axioms tend not to play well with computation. Consider this example. We start by implementing a function that uses a type equality proof to perform a safe type-cast. *)
|
adamc@230
|
776
|
adamc@230
|
777 Definition cast (x y : Set) (pf : x = y) (v : x) : y :=
|
adamc@230
|
778 match pf with
|
adamc@230
|
779 | refl_equal => v
|
adamc@230
|
780 end.
|
adamc@230
|
781
|
adamc@230
|
782 (** Computation over programs that use [cast] can proceed smoothly. *)
|
adamc@230
|
783
|
adamc@230
|
784 Eval compute in (cast (refl_equal (nat -> nat)) (fun n => S n)) 12.
|
adamc@230
|
785 (** [[
|
adamc@230
|
786 = 13
|
adamc@230
|
787 : nat
|
adam@302
|
788 ]]
|
adam@302
|
789 *)
|
adamc@230
|
790
|
adamc@230
|
791 (** Things do not go as smoothly when we use [cast] with proofs that rely on axioms. *)
|
adamc@230
|
792
|
adamc@230
|
793 Theorem t3 : (forall n : nat, fin (S n)) = (forall n : nat, fin (n + 1)).
|
adamc@230
|
794 change ((forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (S n)) n) = (forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (n + 1)) n));
|
adamc@230
|
795 rewrite (functional_extensionality (fun n => fin (n + 1)) (fun n => fin (S n))); crush.
|
adamc@230
|
796 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
797
|
adamc@230
|
798 Eval compute in (cast t3 (fun _ => First)) 12.
|
adamc@230
|
799 (** [[
|
adamc@230
|
800 = match t3 in (_ = P) return P with
|
adamc@230
|
801 | refl_equal => fun n : nat => First
|
adamc@230
|
802 end 12
|
adamc@230
|
803 : fin (12 + 1)
|
adamc@230
|
804
|
adamc@230
|
805 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
806
|
adamc@230
|
807 Computation gets stuck in a pattern-match on the proof [t3]. The structure of [t3] is not known, so the match cannot proceed. It turns out a more basic problem leads to this particular situation. We ended the proof of [t3] with [Qed], so the definition of [t3] is not available to computation. That is easily fixed. *)
|
adamc@230
|
808
|
adamc@230
|
809 Reset t3.
|
adamc@230
|
810
|
adamc@230
|
811 Theorem t3 : (forall n : nat, fin (S n)) = (forall n : nat, fin (n + 1)).
|
adamc@230
|
812 change ((forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (S n)) n) = (forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (n + 1)) n));
|
adamc@230
|
813 rewrite (functional_extensionality (fun n => fin (n + 1)) (fun n => fin (S n))); crush.
|
adamc@230
|
814 Defined.
|
adamc@230
|
815
|
adamc@230
|
816 Eval compute in (cast t3 (fun _ => First)) 12.
|
adamc@230
|
817 (** [[
|
adamc@230
|
818 = match
|
adamc@230
|
819 match
|
adamc@230
|
820 match
|
adamc@230
|
821 functional_extensionality
|
adamc@230
|
822 ....
|
adamc@230
|
823
|
adamc@230
|
824 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
825
|
adamc@230
|
826 We elide most of the details. A very unwieldy tree of nested matches on equality proofs appears. This time evaluation really %\textit{%#<i>#is#</i>#%}% stuck on a use of an axiom.
|
adamc@230
|
827
|
adamc@230
|
828 If we are careful in using tactics to prove an equality, we can still compute with casts over the proof. *)
|
adamc@230
|
829
|
adamc@230
|
830 Lemma plus1 : forall n, S n = n + 1.
|
adamc@230
|
831 induction n; simpl; intuition.
|
adamc@230
|
832 Defined.
|
adamc@230
|
833
|
adamc@230
|
834 Theorem t4 : forall n, fin (S n) = fin (n + 1).
|
adamc@230
|
835 intro; f_equal; apply plus1.
|
adamc@230
|
836 Defined.
|
adamc@230
|
837
|
adamc@230
|
838 Eval compute in cast (t4 13) First.
|
adamc@230
|
839 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
840 = First
|
adamc@230
|
841 : fin (13 + 1)
|
adam@302
|
842 ]]
|
adam@302
|
843 *)
|