annotate src/Universes.v @ 231:bc0f515a929f

New release
author Adam Chlipala <adamc@hcoop.net>
date Mon, 23 Nov 2009 12:41:14 -0500
parents 9dbcd6bad488
children f15f7c4eebfe
rev   line source
adamc@227 1 (* Copyright (c) 2009, Adam Chlipala
adamc@227 2 *
adamc@227 3 * This work is licensed under a
adamc@227 4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
adamc@227 5 * Unported License.
adamc@227 6 * The license text is available at:
adamc@227 7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
adamc@227 8 *)
adamc@227 9
adamc@227 10 (* begin hide *)
adamc@230 11 Require Import DepList Tactics.
adamc@227 12
adamc@227 13 Set Implicit Arguments.
adamc@227 14 (* end hide *)
adamc@227 15
adamc@227 16
adamc@227 17 (** %\chapter{Universes and Axioms}% *)
adamc@227 18
adamc@228 19 (** Many traditional theorems can be proved in Coq without special knowledge of CIC, the logic behind the prover. A development just seems to be using a particular ASCII notation for standard formulas based on set theory. Nonetheless, as we saw in Chapter 4, CIC differs from set theory in starting from fewer orthogonal primitives. It is possible to define the usual logical connectives as derived notions. The foundation of it all is a dependently-typed functional programming language, based on dependent function types and inductive type families. By using the facilities of this language directly, we can accomplish some things much more easily than in mainstream math.
adamc@227 20
adamc@227 21 Gallina, which adds features to the more theoretical CIC, is the logic implemented in Coq. It has a relatively simple foundation that can be defined rigorously in a page or two of formal proof rules. Still, there are some important subtleties that have practical ramifications. This chapter focuses on those subtleties, avoiding formal metatheory in favor of example code. *)
adamc@227 22
adamc@227 23
adamc@227 24 (** * The [Type] Hierarchy *)
adamc@227 25
adamc@227 26 (** Every object in Gallina has a type. *)
adamc@227 27
adamc@227 28 Check 0.
adamc@227 29 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 30 0
adamc@227 31 : nat
adamc@227 32
adamc@227 33 ]]
adamc@227 34
adamc@227 35 It is natural enough that zero be considered as a natural number. *)
adamc@227 36
adamc@227 37 Check nat.
adamc@227 38 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 39 nat
adamc@227 40 : Set
adamc@227 41
adamc@227 42 ]]
adamc@227 43
adamc@227 44 From a set theory perspective, it is unsurprising to consider the natural numbers as a "set." *)
adamc@227 45
adamc@227 46 Check Set.
adamc@227 47 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 48 Set
adamc@227 49 : Type
adamc@227 50
adamc@227 51 ]]
adamc@227 52
adamc@227 53 The type [Set] may be considered as the set of all sets, a concept that set theory handles in terms of %\textit{%#<i>#classes#</i>#%}%. In Coq, this more general notion is [Type]. *)
adamc@227 54
adamc@227 55 Check Type.
adamc@227 56 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 57 Type
adamc@227 58 : Type
adamc@227 59
adamc@227 60 ]]
adamc@227 61
adamc@228 62 Strangely enough, [Type] appears to be its own type. It is known that polymorphic languages with this property are inconsistent. That is, using such a language to encode proofs is unwise, because it is possible to "prove" any proposition. What is really going on here?
adamc@227 63
adamc@227 64 Let us repeat some of our queries after toggling a flag related to Coq's printing behavior. *)
adamc@227 65
adamc@227 66 Set Printing Universes.
adamc@227 67
adamc@227 68 Check nat.
adamc@227 69 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 70 nat
adamc@227 71 : Set
adamc@227 72 ]] *)
adamc@227 73
adamc@227 74 (** printing $ %({}*% #(<a/>*# *)
adamc@227 75 (** printing ^ %*{})% #*<a/>)# *)
adamc@227 76
adamc@227 77 Check Set.
adamc@227 78 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 79 Set
adamc@227 80 : Type $ (0)+1 ^
adamc@227 81
adamc@227 82 ]] *)
adamc@227 83
adamc@227 84 Check Type.
adamc@227 85 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 86 Type $ Top.3 ^
adamc@227 87 : Type $ (Top.3)+1 ^
adamc@227 88
adamc@227 89 ]]
adamc@227 90
adamc@231 91 Occurrences of [Type] are annotated with some additional information, inside comments. These annotations have to do with the secret behind [Type]: it really stands for an infinite hierarchy of types. The type of [Set] is [Type(0)], the type of [Type(0)] is [Type(1)], the type of [Type(1)] is [Type(2)], and so on. This is how we avoid the "[Type : Type]" paradox. As a convenience, the universe hierarchy drives Coq's one variety of subtyping. Any term whose type is [Type] at level [i] is automatically also described by [Type] at level [j] when [j > i].
adamc@227 92
adamc@227 93 In the outputs of our first [Check] query, we see that the type level of [Set]'s type is [(0)+1]. Here [0] stands for the level of [Set], and we increment it to arrive at the level that %\textit{%#<i>#classifies#</i>#%}% [Set].
adamc@227 94
adamc@227 95 In the second query's output, we see that the occurrence of [Type] that we check is assigned a fresh %\textit{%#<i>#universe variable#</i>#%}% [Top.3]. The output type increments [Top.3] to move up a level in the universe hierarchy. As we write code that uses definitions whose types mention universe variables, unification may refine the values of those variables. Luckily, the user rarely has to worry about the details.
adamc@227 96
adamc@227 97 Another crucial concept in CIC is %\textit{%#<i>#predicativity#</i>#%}%. Consider these queries. *)
adamc@227 98
adamc@227 99 Check forall T : nat, fin T.
adamc@227 100 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 101 forall T : nat, fin T
adamc@227 102 : Set
adamc@227 103 ]] *)
adamc@227 104
adamc@227 105 Check forall T : Set, T.
adamc@227 106 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 107 forall T : Set, T
adamc@227 108 : Type $ max(0, (0)+1) ^
adamc@227 109 ]] *)
adamc@227 110
adamc@227 111 Check forall T : Type, T.
adamc@227 112 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 113 forall T : Type $ Top.9 ^ , T
adamc@227 114 : Type $ max(Top.9, (Top.9)+1) ^
adamc@227 115
adamc@227 116 ]]
adamc@227 117
adamc@227 118 These outputs demonstrate the rule for determining which universe a [forall] type lives in. In particular, for a type [forall x : T1, T2], we take the maximum of the universes of [T1] and [T2]. In the first example query, both [T1] ([nat]) and [T2] ([fin T]) are in [Set], so the [forall] type is in [Set], too. In the second query, [T1] is [Set], which is at level [(0)+1]; and [T2] is [T], which is at level [0]. Thus, the [forall] exists at the maximum of these two levels. The third example illustrates the same outcome, where we replace [Set] with an occurrence of [Type] that is assigned universe variable [Top.9]. This universe variable appears in the places where [0] appeared in the previous query.
adamc@227 119
adamc@227 120 The behind-the-scenes manipulation of universe variables gives us predicativity. Consider this simple definition of a polymorphic identity function. *)
adamc@227 121
adamc@227 122 Definition id (T : Set) (x : T) : T := x.
adamc@227 123
adamc@227 124 Check id 0.
adamc@227 125 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 126 id 0
adamc@227 127 : nat
adamc@227 128
adamc@227 129 Check id Set.
adamc@227 130
adamc@227 131 Error: Illegal application (Type Error):
adamc@227 132 ...
adamc@228 133 The 1st term has type "Type $ (Top.15)+1 ^" which should be coercible to "Set".
adamc@227 134
adamc@227 135 ]]
adamc@227 136
adamc@227 137 The parameter [T] of [id] must be instantiated with a [Set]. [nat] is a [Set], but [Set] is not. We can try fixing the problem by generalizing our definition of [id]. *)
adamc@227 138
adamc@227 139 Reset id.
adamc@227 140 Definition id (T : Type) (x : T) : T := x.
adamc@227 141 Check id 0.
adamc@227 142 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 143 id 0
adamc@227 144 : nat
adamc@227 145 ]] *)
adamc@227 146
adamc@227 147 Check id Set.
adamc@227 148 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 149 id Set
adamc@227 150 : Type $ Top.17 ^
adamc@227 151 ]] *)
adamc@227 152
adamc@227 153 Check id Type.
adamc@227 154 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 155 id Type $ Top.18 ^
adamc@227 156 : Type $ Top.19 ^
adamc@227 157 ]] *)
adamc@227 158
adamc@227 159 (** So far so good. As we apply [id] to different [T] values, the inferred index for [T]'s [Type] occurrence automatically moves higher up the type hierarchy.
adamc@227 160
adamc@227 161 [[
adamc@227 162 Check id id.
adamc@227 163
adamc@227 164 Error: Universe inconsistency (cannot enforce Top.16 < Top.16).
adamc@227 165
adamc@227 166 ]]
adamc@227 167
adamc@228 168 This error message reminds us that the universe variable for [T] still exists, even though it is usually hidden. To apply [id] to itself, that variable would need to be less than itself in the type hierarchy. Universe inconsistency error messages announce cases like this one where a term could only type-check by violating an implied constraint over universe variables. Such errors demonstrate that [Type] is %\textit{%#<i>#predicative#</i>#%}%, where this word has a CIC meaning closely related to its usual mathematical meaning. A predicative system enforces the constraint that, for any object of quantified type, none of those quantifiers may ever be instantiated with the object itself. Impredicativity is associated with popular paradoxes in set theory, involving inconsistent constructions like "the set of all sets that do not contain themselves." Similar paradoxes result from uncontrolled impredicativity in Coq. *)
adamc@227 169
adamc@227 170
adamc@227 171 (** ** Inductive Definitions *)
adamc@227 172
adamc@227 173 (** Predicativity restrictions also apply to inductive definitions. As an example, let us consider a type of expression trees that allows injection of any native Coq value. The idea is that an [exp T] stands for a reflected expression of type [T].
adamc@227 174
adamc@227 175 [[
adamc@227 176 Inductive exp : Set -> Set :=
adamc@227 177 | Const : forall T : Set, T -> exp T
adamc@227 178 | Pair : forall T1 T2, exp T1 -> exp T2 -> exp (T1 * T2)
adamc@227 179 | Eq : forall T, exp T -> exp T -> exp bool.
adamc@227 180
adamc@227 181 Error: Large non-propositional inductive types must be in Type.
adamc@227 182
adamc@227 183 ]]
adamc@227 184
adamc@227 185 This definition is %\textit{%#<i>#large#</i>#%}% in the sense that at least one of its constructors takes an argument whose type has type [Type]. Coq would be inconsistent if we allowed definitions like this one in their full generality. Instead, we must change [exp] to live in [Type]. We will go even further and move [exp]'s index to [Type] as well. *)
adamc@227 186
adamc@227 187 Inductive exp : Type -> Type :=
adamc@227 188 | Const : forall T, T -> exp T
adamc@227 189 | Pair : forall T1 T2, exp T1 -> exp T2 -> exp (T1 * T2)
adamc@227 190 | Eq : forall T, exp T -> exp T -> exp bool.
adamc@227 191
adamc@228 192 (** Note that before we had to include an annotation [: Set] for the variable [T] in [Const]'s type, but we need no annotation now. When the type of a variable is not known, and when that variable is used in a context where only types are allowed, Coq infers that the variable is of type [Type]. That is the right behavior here, but it was wrong for the [Set] version of [exp].
adamc@228 193
adamc@228 194 Our new definition is accepted. We can build some sample expressions. *)
adamc@227 195
adamc@227 196 Check Const 0.
adamc@227 197 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 198 Const 0
adamc@227 199 : exp nat
adamc@227 200 ]] *)
adamc@227 201
adamc@227 202 Check Pair (Const 0) (Const tt).
adamc@227 203 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 204 Pair (Const 0) (Const tt)
adamc@227 205 : exp (nat * unit)
adamc@227 206 ]] *)
adamc@227 207
adamc@227 208 Check Eq (Const Set) (Const Type).
adamc@227 209 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@228 210 Eq (Const Set) (Const Type $ Top.59 ^ )
adamc@227 211 : exp bool
adamc@227 212
adamc@227 213 ]]
adamc@227 214
adamc@227 215 We can check many expressions, including fancy expressions that include types. However, it is not hard to hit a type-checking wall.
adamc@227 216
adamc@227 217 [[
adamc@227 218 Check Const (Const O).
adamc@227 219
adamc@227 220 Error: Universe inconsistency (cannot enforce Top.42 < Top.42).
adamc@227 221
adamc@227 222 ]]
adamc@227 223
adamc@227 224 We are unable to instantiate the parameter [T] of [Const] with an [exp] type. To see why, it is helpful to print the annotated version of [exp]'s inductive definition. *)
adamc@227 225
adamc@227 226 Print exp.
adamc@227 227 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 228 Inductive exp
adamc@227 229 : Type $ Top.8 ^ ->
adamc@227 230 Type
adamc@227 231 $ max(0, (Top.11)+1, (Top.14)+1, (Top.15)+1, (Top.19)+1) ^ :=
adamc@227 232 Const : forall T : Type $ Top.11 ^ , T -> exp T
adamc@227 233 | Pair : forall (T1 : Type $ Top.14 ^ ) (T2 : Type $ Top.15 ^ ),
adamc@227 234 exp T1 -> exp T2 -> exp (T1 * T2)
adamc@227 235 | Eq : forall T : Type $ Top.19 ^ , exp T -> exp T -> exp bool
adamc@227 236
adamc@227 237 ]]
adamc@227 238
adamc@227 239 We see that the index type of [exp] has been assigned to universe level [Top.8]. In addition, each of the four occurrences of [Type] in the types of the constructors gets its own universe variable. Each of these variables appears explicitly in the type of [exp]. In particular, any type [exp T] lives at a universe level found by incrementing by one the maximum of the four argument variables. A consequence of this is that [exp] %\textit{%#<i>#must#</i>#%}% live at a higher universe level than any type which may be passed to one of its constructors. This consequence led to the universe inconsistency.
adamc@227 240
adamc@227 241 Strangely, the universe variable [Top.8] only appears in one place. Is there no restriction imposed on which types are valid arguments to [exp]? In fact, there is a restriction, but it only appears in a global set of universe constraints that are maintained "off to the side," not appearing explicitly in types. We can print the current database. *)
adamc@227 242
adamc@227 243 Print Universes.
adamc@227 244 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 245 Top.19 < Top.9 <= Top.8
adamc@227 246 Top.15 < Top.9 <= Top.8 <= Coq.Init.Datatypes.38
adamc@227 247 Top.14 < Top.9 <= Top.8 <= Coq.Init.Datatypes.37
adamc@227 248 Top.11 < Top.9 <= Top.8
adamc@227 249
adamc@227 250 ]]
adamc@227 251
adamc@227 252 [Print Universes] outputs many more constraints, but we have collected only those that mention [Top] variables. We see one constraint for each universe variable associated with a constructor argument from [exp]'s definition. [Top.19] is the type argument to [Eq]. The constraint for [Top.19] effectively says that [Top.19] must be less than [Top.8], the universe of [exp]'s indices; an intermediate variable [Top.9] appears as an artifact of the way the constraint was generated.
adamc@227 253
adamc@227 254 The next constraint, for [Top.15], is more complicated. This is the universe of the second argument to the [Pair] constructor. Not only must [Top.15] be less than [Top.8], but it also comes out that [Top.8] must be less than [Coq.Init.Datatypes.38]. What is this new universe variable? It is from the definition of the [prod] inductive family, to which types of the form [A * B] are desugared. *)
adamc@227 255
adamc@227 256 Print prod.
adamc@227 257 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 258 Inductive prod (A : Type $ Coq.Init.Datatypes.37 ^ )
adamc@227 259 (B : Type $ Coq.Init.Datatypes.38 ^ )
adamc@227 260 : Type $ max(Coq.Init.Datatypes.37, Coq.Init.Datatypes.38) ^ :=
adamc@227 261 pair : A -> B -> A * B
adamc@227 262
adamc@227 263 ]]
adamc@227 264
adamc@227 265 We see that the constraint is enforcing that indices to [exp] must not live in a higher universe level than [B]-indices to [prod]. The next constraint above establishes a symmetric condition for [A].
adamc@227 266
adamc@227 267 Thus it is apparent that Coq maintains a tortuous set of universe variable inequalities behind the scenes. It may look like some functions are polymorphic in the universe levels of their arguments, but what is really happening is imperative updating of a system of constraints, such that all uses of a function are consistent with a global set of universe levels. When the constraint system may not be evolved soundly, we get a universe inconsistency error.
adamc@227 268
adamc@227 269 %\medskip%
adamc@227 270
adamc@227 271 Something interesting is revealed in the annotated definition of [prod]. A type [prod A B] lives at a universe that is the maximum of the universes of [A] and [B]. From our earlier experiments, we might expect that [prod]'s universe would in fact need to be %\textit{%#<i>#one higher#</i>#%}% than the maximum. The critical difference is that, in the definition of [prod], [A] and [B] are defined as %\textit{%#<i>#parameters#</i>#%}%; that is, they appear named to the left of the main colon, rather than appearing (possibly unnamed) to the right.
adamc@227 272
adamc@231 273 Parameters are not as flexible as normal inductive type arguments. The range types of all of the constructors of a parameterized type must share the same parameters. Nonetheless, when it is possible to define a polymorphic type in this way, we gain the ability to use the new type family in more ways, without triggering universe inconsistencies. For instance, nested pairs of types are perfectly legal. *)
adamc@227 274
adamc@227 275 Check (nat, (Type, Set)).
adamc@227 276 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@227 277 (nat, (Type $ Top.44 ^ , Set))
adamc@227 278 : Set * (Type $ Top.45 ^ * Type $ Top.46 ^ )
adamc@227 279
adamc@227 280 ]]
adamc@227 281
adamc@227 282 The same cannot be done with a counterpart to [prod] that does not use parameters. *)
adamc@227 283
adamc@227 284 Inductive prod' : Type -> Type -> Type :=
adamc@227 285 | pair' : forall A B : Type, A -> B -> prod' A B.
adamc@227 286
adamc@227 287 (** [[
adamc@227 288 Check (pair' nat (pair' Type Set)).
adamc@227 289
adamc@227 290 Error: Universe inconsistency (cannot enforce Top.51 < Top.51).
adamc@227 291
adamc@227 292 ]]
adamc@227 293
adamc@227 294 The key benefit parameters bring us is the ability to avoid quantifying over types in the types of constructors. Such quantification induces less-than constraints, while parameters only introduce less-than-or-equal-to constraints. *)
adamc@229 295
adamc@229 296 (* begin hide *)
adamc@229 297 Unset Printing Universes.
adamc@229 298 (* end hide *)
adamc@229 299
adamc@229 300
adamc@229 301 (** * The [Prop] Universe *)
adamc@229 302
adamc@229 303 (** In Chapter 4, we saw parallel versions of useful datatypes for "programs" and "proofs." The convention was that programs live in [Set], and proofs live in [Prop]. We gave little explanation for why it is useful to maintain this distinction. There is certainly documentation value from separating programs from proofs; in practice, different concerns apply to building the two types of objects. It turns out, however, that these concerns motivate formal differences between the two universes in Coq.
adamc@229 304
adamc@229 305 Recall the types [sig] and [ex], which are the program and proof versions of existential quantification. Their definitions differ only in one place, where [sig] uses [Type] and [ex] uses [Prop]. *)
adamc@229 306
adamc@229 307 Print sig.
adamc@229 308 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@229 309 Inductive sig (A : Type) (P : A -> Prop) : Type :=
adamc@229 310 exist : forall x : A, P x -> sig P
adamc@229 311 ]] *)
adamc@229 312
adamc@229 313 Print ex.
adamc@229 314 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@229 315 Inductive ex (A : Type) (P : A -> Prop) : Prop :=
adamc@229 316 ex_intro : forall x : A, P x -> ex P
adamc@229 317
adamc@229 318 ]]
adamc@229 319
adamc@229 320 It is natural to want a function to extract the first components of data structures like these. Doing so is easy enough for [sig]. *)
adamc@229 321
adamc@229 322 Definition projS A (P : A -> Prop) (x : sig P) : A :=
adamc@229 323 match x with
adamc@229 324 | exist v _ => v
adamc@229 325 end.
adamc@229 326
adamc@229 327 (** We run into trouble with a version that has been changed to work with [ex].
adamc@229 328
adamc@229 329 [[
adamc@229 330 Definition projE A (P : A -> Prop) (x : ex P) : A :=
adamc@229 331 match x with
adamc@229 332 | ex_intro v _ => v
adamc@229 333 end.
adamc@229 334
adamc@229 335 Error:
adamc@229 336 Incorrect elimination of "x" in the inductive type "ex":
adamc@229 337 the return type has sort "Type" while it should be "Prop".
adamc@229 338 Elimination of an inductive object of sort Prop
adamc@229 339 is not allowed on a predicate in sort Type
adamc@229 340 because proofs can be eliminated only to build proofs.
adamc@229 341
adamc@229 342 ]]
adamc@229 343
adamc@230 344 In formal Coq parlance, "elimination" means "pattern-matching." The typing rules of Gallina forbid us from pattern-matching on a discriminee whose type belongs to [Prop], whenever the result type of the [match] has a type besides [Prop]. This is a sort of "information flow" policy, where the type system ensures that the details of proofs can never have any effect on parts of a development that are not also marked as proofs.
adamc@229 345
adamc@229 346 This restriction matches informal practice. We think of programs and proofs as clearly separated, and, outside of constructive logic, the idea of computing with proofs is ill-formed. The distinction also has practical importance in Coq, where it affects the behavior of extraction.
adamc@229 347
adamc@229 348 Recall that extraction is Coq's facility for translating Coq developments into programs in general-purpose programming languages like OCaml. Extraction %\textit{%#<i>#erases#</i>#%}% proofs and leaves programs intact. A simple example with [sig] and [ex] demonstrates the distinction. *)
adamc@229 349
adamc@229 350 Definition sym_sig (x : sig (fun n => n = 0)) : sig (fun n => 0 = n) :=
adamc@229 351 match x with
adamc@229 352 | exist n pf => exist _ n (sym_eq pf)
adamc@229 353 end.
adamc@229 354
adamc@229 355 Extraction sym_sig.
adamc@229 356 (** <<
adamc@229 357 (** val sym_sig : nat -> nat **)
adamc@229 358
adamc@229 359 let sym_sig x = x
adamc@229 360 >>
adamc@229 361
adamc@229 362 Since extraction erases proofs, the second components of [sig] values are elided, making [sig] a simple identity type family. The [sym_sig] operation is thus an identity function. *)
adamc@229 363
adamc@229 364 Definition sym_ex (x : ex (fun n => n = 0)) : ex (fun n => 0 = n) :=
adamc@229 365 match x with
adamc@229 366 | ex_intro n pf => ex_intro _ n (sym_eq pf)
adamc@229 367 end.
adamc@229 368
adamc@229 369 Extraction sym_ex.
adamc@229 370 (** <<
adamc@229 371 (** val sym_ex : __ **)
adamc@229 372
adamc@229 373 let sym_ex = __
adamc@229 374 >>
adamc@229 375
adamc@229 376 In this example, the [ex] type itself is in [Prop], so whole [ex] packages are erased. Coq extracts every proposition as the type %\texttt{%#<tt>#__#</tt>#%}%, whose single constructor is %\texttt{%#<tt>#__#</tt>#%}%. Not only are proofs replaced by [__], but proof arguments to functions are also removed completely, as we see here.
adamc@229 377
adamc@229 378 Extraction is very helpful as an optimization over programs that contain proofs. In languages like Haskell, advanced features make it possible to program with proofs, as a way of convincing the type checker to accept particular definitions. Unfortunately, when proofs are encoded as values in GADTs, these proofs exist at runtime and consume resources. In contrast, with Coq, as long as you keep all of your proofs within [Prop], extraction is guaranteed to erase them.
adamc@229 379
adamc@229 380 Many fans of the Curry-Howard correspondence support the idea of %\textit{%#<i>#extracting programs from proofs#</i>#%}%. In reality, few users of Coq and related tools do any such thing. Instead, extraction is better thought of as an optimization that reduces the runtime costs of expressive typing.
adamc@229 381
adamc@229 382 %\medskip%
adamc@229 383
adamc@229 384 We have seen two of the differences between proofs and programs: proofs are subject to an elimination restriction and are elided by extraction. The remaining difference is that [Prop] is %\textit{%#<i>#impredicative#</i>#%}%, as this example shows. *)
adamc@229 385
adamc@229 386 Check forall P Q : Prop, P \/ Q -> Q \/ P.
adamc@229 387 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@229 388 forall P Q : Prop, P \/ Q -> Q \/ P
adamc@229 389 : Prop
adamc@229 390
adamc@229 391 ]]
adamc@229 392
adamc@230 393 We see that it is possible to define a [Prop] that quantifies over other [Prop]s. This is fortunate, as we start wanting that ability even for such basic purposes as stating propositional tautologies. In the next section of this chapter, we will see some reasons why unrestricted impredicativity is undesirable. The impredicativity of [Prop] interacts crucially with the elimination restriction to avoid those pitfalls.
adamc@230 394
adamc@230 395 Impredicativity also allows us to implement a version of our earlier [exp] type that does not suffer from the weakness that we found. *)
adamc@230 396
adamc@230 397 Inductive expP : Type -> Prop :=
adamc@230 398 | ConstP : forall T, T -> expP T
adamc@230 399 | PairP : forall T1 T2, expP T1 -> expP T2 -> expP (T1 * T2)
adamc@230 400 | EqP : forall T, expP T -> expP T -> expP bool.
adamc@230 401
adamc@230 402 Check ConstP 0.
adamc@230 403 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 404 ConstP 0
adamc@230 405 : expP nat
adamc@230 406 ]] *)
adamc@230 407
adamc@230 408 Check PairP (ConstP 0) (ConstP tt).
adamc@230 409 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 410 PairP (ConstP 0) (ConstP tt)
adamc@230 411 : expP (nat * unit)
adamc@230 412 ]] *)
adamc@230 413
adamc@230 414 Check EqP (ConstP Set) (ConstP Type).
adamc@230 415 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 416 EqP (ConstP Set) (ConstP Type)
adamc@230 417 : expP bool
adamc@230 418 ]] *)
adamc@230 419
adamc@230 420 Check ConstP (ConstP O).
adamc@230 421 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 422 ConstP (ConstP 0)
adamc@230 423 : expP (expP nat)
adamc@230 424
adamc@230 425 ]]
adamc@230 426
adamc@230 427 In this case, our victory is really a shallow one. As we have marked [expP] as a family of proofs, we cannot deconstruct our expressions in the usual programmatic ways, which makes them almost useless for the usual purposes. Impredicative quantification is much more useful in defining inductive families that we really think of as judgments. For instance, this code defines a notion of equality that is strictly stronger than the base equality [=]. *)
adamc@230 428
adamc@230 429 Inductive eqPlus : forall T, T -> T -> Prop :=
adamc@230 430 | Base : forall T (x : T), eqPlus x x
adamc@230 431 | Func : forall dom ran (f1 f2 : dom -> ran),
adamc@230 432 (forall x : dom, eqPlus (f1 x) (f2 x))
adamc@230 433 -> eqPlus f1 f2.
adamc@230 434
adamc@230 435 Check (Base 0).
adamc@230 436 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 437 Base 0
adamc@230 438 : eqPlus 0 0
adamc@230 439 ]] *)
adamc@230 440
adamc@230 441 Check (Func (fun n => n) (fun n => 0 + n) (fun n => Base n)).
adamc@230 442 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 443 Func (fun n : nat => n) (fun n : nat => 0 + n) (fun n : nat => Base n)
adamc@230 444 : eqPlus (fun n : nat => n) (fun n : nat => 0 + n)
adamc@230 445 ]] *)
adamc@230 446
adamc@230 447 Check (Base (Base 1)).
adamc@230 448 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 449 Base (Base 1)
adamc@230 450 : eqPlus (Base 1) (Base 1)
adamc@230 451 ]] *)
adamc@230 452
adamc@230 453
adamc@230 454 (** * Axioms *)
adamc@230 455
adamc@230 456 (** While the specific logic Gallina is hardcoded into Coq's implementation, it is possible to add certain logical rules in a controlled way. In other words, Coq may be used to reason about many different refinements of Gallina where strictly more theorems are provable. We achieve this by asserting %\textit{%#<i>#axioms#</i>#%}% without proof.
adamc@230 457
adamc@230 458 We will motivate the idea by touring through some standard axioms, as enumerated in Coq's online FAQ. I will add additional commentary as appropriate. *)
adamc@230 459
adamc@230 460 (** ** The Basics *)
adamc@230 461
adamc@231 462 (** One simple example of a useful axiom is the law of the excluded middle. *)
adamc@230 463
adamc@230 464 Require Import Classical_Prop.
adamc@230 465 Print classic.
adamc@230 466 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 467 *** [ classic : forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P ]
adamc@230 468
adamc@230 469 ]]
adamc@230 470
adamc@230 471 In the implementation of module [Classical_Prop], this axiom was defined with the command *)
adamc@230 472
adamc@230 473 Axiom classic : forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P.
adamc@230 474
adamc@230 475 (** An [Axiom] may be declared with any type, in any of the universes. There is a synonym [Parameter] for [Axiom], and that synonym is often clearer for assertions not of type [Prop]. For instance, we can assert the existence of objects with certain properties. *)
adamc@230 476
adamc@230 477 Parameter n : nat.
adamc@230 478 Axiom positive : n > 0.
adamc@230 479 Reset n.
adamc@230 480
adamc@230 481 (** This kind of "axiomatic presentation" of a theory is very common outside of higher-order logic. However, in Coq, it is almost always preferable to stick to defining your objects, functions, and predicates via inductive definitions and functional programming.
adamc@230 482
adamc@230 483 In general, there is a significant burden associated with any use of axioms. It is easy to assert a set of axioms that together is %\textit{%#<i>#inconsistent#</i>#%}%. That is, a set of axioms may imply [False], which allows any theorem to proved, which defeats the purpose of a proof assistant. For example, we could assert the following axiom, which is consistent by itself but inconsistent when combined with [classic]. *)
adamc@230 484
adamc@230 485 Axiom not_classic : exists P : Prop, ~ (P \/ ~ P).
adamc@230 486
adamc@230 487 Theorem uhoh : False.
adamc@230 488 generalize classic not_classic; firstorder.
adamc@230 489 Qed.
adamc@230 490
adamc@230 491 Theorem uhoh_again : 1 + 1 = 3.
adamc@230 492 destruct uhoh.
adamc@230 493 Qed.
adamc@230 494
adamc@230 495 Reset not_classic.
adamc@230 496
adamc@230 497 (** On the subject of the law of the excluded middle itself, this axiom is usually quite harmless, and many practical Coq developments assume it. It has been proved metatheoretically to be consistent with CIC. Here, "proved metatheoretically" means that someone proved on paper that excluded middle holds in a %\textit{%#<i>#model#</i>#%}% of CIC in set theory. All of the other axioms that we will survey in this section hold in the same model, so they are all consistent together.
adamc@230 498
adamc@230 499 Recall that Coq implements %\textit{%#<i>#constructive#</i>#%}% logic by default, where excluded middle is not provable. Proofs in constructive logic can be thought of as programs. A [forall] quantifier denotes a dependent function type, and a disjunction denotes a variant type. In such a setting, excluded middle could be interpreted as a decision procedure for arbitrary propositions, which computability theory tells us cannot exist. Thus, constructive logic with excluded middle can no longer be associated with our usual notion of programming.
adamc@230 500
adamc@231 501 Given all this, why is it all right to assert excluded middle as an axiom? The intuitive justification is that the elimination restriction for [Prop] prevents us from treating proofs as programs. An excluded middle axiom that quantified over [Set] instead of [Prop] %\textit{%#<i>#would#</i>#%}% be problematic. If a development used that axiom, we would not be able to extract the code to OCaml (soundly) without implementing a genuine universal decision procedure. In contrast, values whose types belong to [Prop] are always erased by extraction, so we sidestep the axiom's algorithmic consequences.
adamc@230 502
adamc@230 503 Because the proper use of axioms is so precarious, there are helpful commands for determining which axioms a theorem relies on. *)
adamc@230 504
adamc@230 505 Theorem t1 : forall P : Prop, P -> ~ ~ P.
adamc@230 506 tauto.
adamc@230 507 Qed.
adamc@230 508
adamc@230 509 Print Assumptions t1.
adamc@230 510 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 511 Closed under the global context
adamc@230 512 ]] *)
adamc@230 513
adamc@230 514 Theorem t2 : forall P : Prop, ~ ~ P -> P.
adamc@230 515 (** [[
adamc@230 516 tauto.
adamc@230 517
adamc@230 518 Error: tauto failed.
adamc@230 519
adamc@230 520 ]] *)
adamc@230 521
adamc@230 522 intro P; destruct (classic P); tauto.
adamc@230 523 Qed.
adamc@230 524
adamc@230 525 Print Assumptions t2.
adamc@230 526 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 527 Axioms:
adamc@230 528 classic : forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P
adamc@230 529
adamc@230 530 ]]
adamc@230 531
adamc@231 532 It is possible to avoid this dependence in some specific cases, where excluded middle %\textit{%#<i>#is#</i>#%}% provable, for decidable families of propositions. *)
adamc@230 533
adamc@230 534 Theorem classic_nat_eq : forall n m : nat, n = m \/ n <> m.
adamc@230 535 induction n; destruct m; intuition; generalize (IHn m); intuition.
adamc@230 536 Qed.
adamc@230 537
adamc@230 538 Theorem t2' : forall n m : nat, ~ ~ (n = m) -> n = m.
adamc@230 539 intros n m; destruct (classic_nat_eq n m); tauto.
adamc@230 540 Qed.
adamc@230 541
adamc@230 542 Print Assumptions t2'.
adamc@230 543 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 544 Closed under the global context
adamc@230 545 ]]
adamc@230 546
adamc@230 547 %\bigskip%
adamc@230 548
adamc@230 549 Mainstream mathematical practice assumes excluded middle, so it can be useful to have it available in Coq developments, though it is also nice to know that a theorem is proved in a simpler formal system than classical logic. There is a similar story for %\textit{%#<i>#proof irrelevance#</i>#%}%, which simplifies proof issues that would not even arise in mainstream math. *)
adamc@230 550
adamc@230 551 Require Import ProofIrrelevance.
adamc@230 552 Print proof_irrelevance.
adamc@230 553 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 554 *** [ proof_irrelevance : forall (P : Prop) (p1 p2 : P), p1 = p2 ]
adamc@230 555
adamc@230 556 ]]
adamc@230 557
adamc@231 558 This axiom asserts that any two proofs of the same proposition are equal. If we replaced [p1 = p2] by [p1 <-> p2], then the statement would be provable. However, equality is a stronger notion than logical equivalence. Recall this example function from Chapter 6. *)
adamc@230 559
adamc@230 560 (* begin hide *)
adamc@230 561 Lemma zgtz : 0 > 0 -> False.
adamc@230 562 crush.
adamc@230 563 Qed.
adamc@230 564 (* end hide *)
adamc@230 565
adamc@230 566 Definition pred_strong1 (n : nat) : n > 0 -> nat :=
adamc@230 567 match n with
adamc@230 568 | O => fun pf : 0 > 0 => match zgtz pf with end
adamc@230 569 | S n' => fun _ => n'
adamc@230 570 end.
adamc@230 571
adamc@230 572 (** We might want to prove that different proofs of [n > 0] do not lead to different results from our richly-typed predecessor function. *)
adamc@230 573
adamc@230 574 Theorem pred_strong1_irrel : forall n (pf1 pf2 : n > 0), pred_strong1 pf1 = pred_strong1 pf2.
adamc@230 575 destruct n; crush.
adamc@230 576 Qed.
adamc@230 577
adamc@230 578 (** The proof script is simple, but it involved peeking into the definition of [pred_strong1]. For more complicated function definitions, it can be considerably more work to prove that they do not discriminate on details of proof arguments. This can seem like a shame, since the [Prop] elimination restriction makes it impossible to write any function that does otherwise. Unfortunately, this fact is only true metatheoretically, unless we assert an axiom like [proof_irrelevance]. With that axiom, we can prove our theorem without consulting the definition of [pred_strong1]. *)
adamc@230 579
adamc@230 580 Theorem pred_strong1_irrel' : forall n (pf1 pf2 : n > 0), pred_strong1 pf1 = pred_strong1 pf2.
adamc@230 581 intros; f_equal; apply proof_irrelevance.
adamc@230 582 Qed.
adamc@230 583
adamc@230 584
adamc@230 585 (** %\bigskip%
adamc@230 586
adamc@230 587 In the chapter on equality, we already discussed some axioms that are related to proof irrelevance. In particular, Coq's standard library includes this axiom: *)
adamc@230 588
adamc@230 589 Require Import Eqdep.
adamc@230 590 Import Eq_rect_eq.
adamc@230 591 Print eq_rect_eq.
adamc@230 592 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 593 *** [ eq_rect_eq :
adamc@230 594 forall (U : Type) (p : U) (Q : U -> Type) (x : Q p) (h : p = p),
adamc@230 595 x = eq_rect p Q x p h ]
adamc@230 596
adamc@230 597 ]]
adamc@230 598
adamc@230 599 This axiom says that it is permissible to simplify pattern matches over proofs of equalities like [e = e]. The axiom is logically equivalent to some simpler corollaries. *)
adamc@230 600
adamc@230 601 Corollary UIP_refl : forall A (x : A) (pf : x = x), pf = refl_equal x.
adamc@230 602 intros; replace pf with (eq_rect x (eq x) (refl_equal x) x pf); [
adamc@230 603 symmetry; apply eq_rect_eq
adamc@230 604 | exact (match pf as pf' return match pf' in _ = y return x = y with
adamc@230 605 | refl_equal => refl_equal x
adamc@230 606 end = pf' with
adamc@230 607 | refl_equal => refl_equal _
adamc@230 608 end) ].
adamc@230 609 Qed.
adamc@230 610
adamc@230 611 Corollary UIP : forall A (x y : A) (pf1 pf2 : x = y), pf1 = pf2.
adamc@230 612 intros; generalize pf1 pf2; subst; intros;
adamc@230 613 match goal with
adamc@230 614 | [ |- ?pf1 = ?pf2 ] => rewrite (UIP_refl pf1); rewrite (UIP_refl pf2); reflexivity
adamc@230 615 end.
adamc@230 616 Qed.
adamc@230 617
adamc@231 618 (** These corollaries are special cases of proof irrelevance. In developments that only need proof irrelevance for equality, there is no need to assert full irrelevance.
adamc@230 619
adamc@230 620 Another facet of proof irrelevance is that, like excluded middle, it is often provable for specific propositions. For instance, [UIP] is provable whenever the type [A] has a decidable equality operation. The module [Eqdep_dec] of the standard library contains a proof. A similar phenomenon applies to other notable cases, including less-than proofs. Thus, it is often possible to use proof irrelevance without asserting axioms.
adamc@230 621
adamc@230 622 %\bigskip%
adamc@230 623
adamc@230 624 There are two more basic axioms that are often assumed, to avoid complications that do not arise in set theory. *)
adamc@230 625
adamc@230 626 Require Import FunctionalExtensionality.
adamc@230 627 Print functional_extensionality_dep.
adamc@230 628 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 629 *** [ functional_extensionality_dep :
adamc@230 630 forall (A : Type) (B : A -> Type) (f g : forall x : A, B x),
adamc@230 631 (forall x : A, f x = g x) -> f = g ]
adamc@230 632
adamc@230 633 ]]
adamc@230 634
adamc@230 635 This axiom says that two functions are equal if they map equal inputs to equal outputs. Such facts are not provable in general in CIC, but it is consistent to assume that they are.
adamc@230 636
adamc@230 637 A simple corollary shows that the same property applies to predicates. In some cases, one might prefer to assert this corollary as the axiom, to restrict the consequences to proofs and not programs. *)
adamc@230 638
adamc@230 639 Corollary predicate_extensionality : forall (A : Type) (B : A -> Prop) (f g : forall x : A, B x),
adamc@230 640 (forall x : A, f x = g x) -> f = g.
adamc@230 641 intros; apply functional_extensionality_dep; assumption.
adamc@230 642 Qed.
adamc@230 643
adamc@230 644
adamc@230 645 (** ** Axioms of Choice *)
adamc@230 646
adamc@230 647 (** Some Coq axioms are also points of contention in mainstream math. The most prominent example is the axiom of choice. In fact, there are multiple versions that we might consider, and, considered in isolation, none of these versions means quite what it means in classical set theory.
adamc@230 648
adamc@230 649 First, it is possible to implement a choice operator %\textit{%#<i>#without#</i>#%}% axioms in some potentially surprising cases. *)
adamc@230 650
adamc@230 651 Require Import ConstructiveEpsilon.
adamc@230 652 Check constructive_definite_description.
adamc@230 653 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 654 constructive_definite_description
adamc@230 655 : forall (A : Set) (f : A -> nat) (g : nat -> A),
adamc@230 656 (forall x : A, g (f x) = x) ->
adamc@230 657 forall P : A -> Prop,
adamc@230 658 (forall x : A, {P x} + {~ P x}) ->
adamc@230 659 (exists! x : A, P x) -> {x : A | P x}
adamc@230 660 ]] *)
adamc@230 661
adamc@230 662 Print Assumptions constructive_definite_description.
adamc@230 663 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 664 Closed under the global context
adamc@230 665
adamc@230 666 ]]
adamc@230 667
adamc@231 668 This function transforms a decidable predicate [P] into a function that produces an element satisfying [P] from a proof that such an element exists. The functions [f] and [g], in conjunction with an associated injectivity property, are used to express the idea that the set [A] is countable. Under these conditions, a simple brute force algorithm gets the job done: we just enumerate all elements of [A], stopping when we find one satisfying [P]. The existence proof, specified in terms of %\textit{%#<i>#unique#</i>#%}% existence [exists!], guarantees termination. The definition of this operator in Coq uses some interesting techniques, as seen in the implementation of the [ConstructiveEpsilon] module.
adamc@230 669
adamc@230 670 Countable choice is provable in set theory without appealing to the general axiom of choice. To support the more general principle in Coq, we must also add an axiom. Here is a functional version of the axiom of unique choice. *)
adamc@230 671
adamc@230 672 Require Import ClassicalUniqueChoice.
adamc@230 673 Check dependent_unique_choice.
adamc@230 674 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 675 dependent_unique_choice
adamc@230 676 : forall (A : Type) (B : A -> Type) (R : forall x : A, B x -> Prop),
adamc@230 677 (forall x : A, exists! y : B x, R x y) ->
adamc@230 678 exists f : forall x : A, B x, forall x : A, R x (f x)
adamc@230 679
adamc@230 680 ]]
adamc@230 681
adamc@230 682 This axiom lets us convert a relational specification [R] into a function implementing that specification. We need only prove that [R] is truly a function. An alternate, stronger formulation applies to cases where [R] maps each input to one or more outputs. We also simplify the statement of the theorem by considering only non-dependent function types. *)
adamc@230 683
adamc@230 684 Require Import ClassicalChoice.
adamc@230 685 Check choice.
adamc@230 686 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 687 choice
adamc@230 688 : forall (A B : Type) (R : A -> B -> Prop),
adamc@230 689 (forall x : A, exists y : B, R x y) ->
adamc@230 690 exists f : A -> B, forall x : A, R x (f x)
adamc@230 691
adamc@230 692 ]]
adamc@230 693
adamc@230 694 This principle is proved as a theorem, based on the unique choice axiom and an additional axiom of relational choice from the [RelationalChoice] module.
adamc@230 695
adamc@230 696 In set theory, the axiom of choice is a fundamental philosophical commitment one makes about the universe of sets. In Coq, the choice axioms say something weaker. For instance, consider the simple restatement of the [choice] axiom where we replace existential quantification by its Curry-Howard analogue, subset types. *)
adamc@230 697
adamc@230 698 Definition choice_Set (A B : Type) (R : A -> B -> Prop) (H : forall x : A, {y : B | R x y})
adamc@230 699 : {f : A -> B | forall x : A, R x (f x)} :=
adamc@230 700 exist (fun f => forall x : A, R x (f x))
adamc@230 701 (fun x => proj1_sig (H x)) (fun x => proj2_sig (H x)).
adamc@230 702
adamc@230 703 (** Via the Curry-Howard correspondence, this "axiom" can be taken to have the same meaning as the original. It is implemented trivially as a transformation not much deeper than uncurrying. Thus, we see that the utility of the axioms that we mentioned earlier comes in their usage to build programs from proofs. Normal set theory has no explicit proofs, so the meaning of the usual axiom of choice is subtlely different. In Gallina, the axioms implement a controlled relaxation of the restrictions on information flow from proofs to programs.
adamc@230 704
adamc@230 705 However, when we combine an axiom of choice with the law of the excluded middle, the idea of "choice" becomes more interesting. Excluded middle gives us a highly non-computational way of constructing proofs, but it does not change the computational nature of programs. Thus, the axiom of choice is still giving us a way of translating between two different sorts of "programs," but the input programs (which are proofs) may be written in a rich language that goes beyond normal computability. This truly is more than repackaging a function with a different type.
adamc@230 706
adamc@230 707 %\bigskip%
adamc@230 708
adamc@230 709 The Coq tools support a command-line flag %\texttt{%#<tt>#-impredicative-set#</tt>#%}%, which modifies Gallina in a more fundamental way by making [Set] impredicative. A term like [forall T : Set, T] has type [Set], and inductive definitions in [Set] may have constructors that quantify over arguments of any types. To maintain consistency, an elimination restriction must be imposed, similarly to the restriction for [Prop]. The restriction only applies to large inductive types, where some constructor quantifies over a type of type [Type]. In such cases, a value in this inductive type may only be pattern-matched over to yield a result type whose type is [Set] or [Prop]. This contrasts with [Prop], where the restriction applies even to non-large inductive types, and where the result type may only have type [Prop].
adamc@230 710
adamc@230 711 In old versions of Coq, [Set] was impredicative by default. Later versions make [Set] predicative to avoid inconsistency with some classical axioms. In particular, one should watch out when using impredicative [Set] with axioms of choice. In combination with excluded middle or predicate extensionality, this can lead to inconsistency. Impredicative [Set] can be useful for modeling inherently impredicative mathematical concepts, but almost all Coq developments get by fine without it. *)
adamc@230 712
adamc@230 713 (** ** Axioms and Computation *)
adamc@230 714
adamc@230 715 (** One additional axiom-related wrinkle arises from an aspect of Gallina that is very different from set theory: a notion of %\textit{%#<i>#computational equivalence#</i>#%}% is central to the definition of the formal system. Axioms tend not to play well with computation. Consider this example. We start by implementing a function that uses a type equality proof to perform a safe type-cast. *)
adamc@230 716
adamc@230 717 Definition cast (x y : Set) (pf : x = y) (v : x) : y :=
adamc@230 718 match pf with
adamc@230 719 | refl_equal => v
adamc@230 720 end.
adamc@230 721
adamc@230 722 (** Computation over programs that use [cast] can proceed smoothly. *)
adamc@230 723
adamc@230 724 Eval compute in (cast (refl_equal (nat -> nat)) (fun n => S n)) 12.
adamc@230 725 (** [[
adamc@230 726 = 13
adamc@230 727 : nat
adamc@230 728 ]] *)
adamc@230 729
adamc@230 730 (** Things do not go as smoothly when we use [cast] with proofs that rely on axioms. *)
adamc@230 731
adamc@230 732 Theorem t3 : (forall n : nat, fin (S n)) = (forall n : nat, fin (n + 1)).
adamc@230 733 change ((forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (S n)) n) = (forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (n + 1)) n));
adamc@230 734 rewrite (functional_extensionality (fun n => fin (n + 1)) (fun n => fin (S n))); crush.
adamc@230 735 Qed.
adamc@230 736
adamc@230 737 Eval compute in (cast t3 (fun _ => First)) 12.
adamc@230 738 (** [[
adamc@230 739 = match t3 in (_ = P) return P with
adamc@230 740 | refl_equal => fun n : nat => First
adamc@230 741 end 12
adamc@230 742 : fin (12 + 1)
adamc@230 743
adamc@230 744 ]]
adamc@230 745
adamc@230 746 Computation gets stuck in a pattern-match on the proof [t3]. The structure of [t3] is not known, so the match cannot proceed. It turns out a more basic problem leads to this particular situation. We ended the proof of [t3] with [Qed], so the definition of [t3] is not available to computation. That is easily fixed. *)
adamc@230 747
adamc@230 748 Reset t3.
adamc@230 749
adamc@230 750 Theorem t3 : (forall n : nat, fin (S n)) = (forall n : nat, fin (n + 1)).
adamc@230 751 change ((forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (S n)) n) = (forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (n + 1)) n));
adamc@230 752 rewrite (functional_extensionality (fun n => fin (n + 1)) (fun n => fin (S n))); crush.
adamc@230 753 Defined.
adamc@230 754
adamc@230 755 Eval compute in (cast t3 (fun _ => First)) 12.
adamc@230 756 (** [[
adamc@230 757 = match
adamc@230 758 match
adamc@230 759 match
adamc@230 760 functional_extensionality
adamc@230 761 ....
adamc@230 762
adamc@230 763 ]]
adamc@230 764
adamc@230 765 We elide most of the details. A very unwieldy tree of nested matches on equality proofs appears. This time evaluation really %\textit{%#<i>#is#</i>#%}% stuck on a use of an axiom.
adamc@230 766
adamc@230 767 If we are careful in using tactics to prove an equality, we can still compute with casts over the proof. *)
adamc@230 768
adamc@230 769 Lemma plus1 : forall n, S n = n + 1.
adamc@230 770 induction n; simpl; intuition.
adamc@230 771 Defined.
adamc@230 772
adamc@230 773 Theorem t4 : forall n, fin (S n) = fin (n + 1).
adamc@230 774 intro; f_equal; apply plus1.
adamc@230 775 Defined.
adamc@230 776
adamc@230 777 Eval compute in cast (t4 13) First.
adamc@230 778 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
adamc@230 779 = First
adamc@230 780 : fin (13 + 1)
adamc@230 781 ]] *)