adam@343
|
1 (* Copyright (c) 2009-2011, Adam Chlipala
|
adamc@227
|
2 *
|
adamc@227
|
3 * This work is licensed under a
|
adamc@227
|
4 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
|
adamc@227
|
5 * Unported License.
|
adamc@227
|
6 * The license text is available at:
|
adamc@227
|
7 * http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
|
adamc@227
|
8 *)
|
adamc@227
|
9
|
adamc@227
|
10 (* begin hide *)
|
adam@314
|
11 Require Import DepList CpdtTactics.
|
adamc@227
|
12
|
adamc@227
|
13 Set Implicit Arguments.
|
adamc@227
|
14 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@227
|
15
|
adamc@227
|
16
|
adamc@227
|
17 (** %\chapter{Universes and Axioms}% *)
|
adamc@227
|
18
|
adam@343
|
19 (** Many traditional theorems can be proved in Coq without special knowledge of CIC, the logic behind the prover. A development just seems to be using a particular ASCII notation for standard formulas based on %\index{set theory}%set theory. Nonetheless, as we saw in Chapter 4, CIC differs from set theory in starting from fewer orthogonal primitives. It is possible to define the usual logical connectives as derived notions. The foundation of it all is a dependently typed functional programming language, based on dependent function types and inductive type families. By using the facilities of this language directly, we can accomplish some things much more easily than in mainstream math.
|
adamc@227
|
20
|
adam@343
|
21 %\index{Gallina}%Gallina, which adds features to the more theoretical CIC%~\cite{CIC}%, is the logic implemented in Coq. It has a relatively simple foundation that can be defined rigorously in a page or two of formal proof rules. Still, there are some important subtleties that have practical ramifications. This chapter focuses on those subtleties, avoiding formal metatheory in favor of example code. *)
|
adamc@227
|
22
|
adamc@227
|
23
|
adamc@227
|
24 (** * The [Type] Hierarchy *)
|
adamc@227
|
25
|
adam@343
|
26 (** %\index{type hierarchy}%Every object in Gallina has a type. *)
|
adamc@227
|
27
|
adamc@227
|
28 Check 0.
|
adamc@227
|
29 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
30 0
|
adamc@227
|
31 : nat
|
adamc@227
|
32
|
adamc@227
|
33 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
34
|
adamc@227
|
35 It is natural enough that zero be considered as a natural number. *)
|
adamc@227
|
36
|
adamc@227
|
37 Check nat.
|
adamc@227
|
38 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
39 nat
|
adamc@227
|
40 : Set
|
adamc@227
|
41
|
adamc@227
|
42 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
43
|
adam@287
|
44 From a set theory perspective, it is unsurprising to consider the natural numbers as a %``%#"#set.#"#%''% *)
|
adamc@227
|
45
|
adamc@227
|
46 Check Set.
|
adamc@227
|
47 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
48 Set
|
adamc@227
|
49 : Type
|
adamc@227
|
50
|
adamc@227
|
51 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
52
|
adam@343
|
53 The type [Set] may be considered as the set of all sets, a concept that set theory handles in terms of %\index{class (in set theory)}\textit{%#<i>#classes#</i>#%}%. In Coq, this more general notion is [Type]. *)
|
adamc@227
|
54
|
adamc@227
|
55 Check Type.
|
adamc@227
|
56 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
57 Type
|
adamc@227
|
58 : Type
|
adamc@227
|
59
|
adamc@227
|
60 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
61
|
adam@343
|
62 Strangely enough, [Type] appears to be its own type. It is known that polymorphic languages with this property are inconsistent, via %\index{Girard's paradox}%Girard's paradox%~\cite{GirardsParadox}%. That is, using such a language to encode proofs is unwise, because it is possible to %``%#"#prove#"#%''% any proposition. What is really going on here?
|
adamc@227
|
63
|
adam@343
|
64 Let us repeat some of our queries after toggling a flag related to Coq's printing behavior.%\index{Vernacular commands!Set Printing Universes}% *)
|
adamc@227
|
65
|
adamc@227
|
66 Set Printing Universes.
|
adamc@227
|
67
|
adamc@227
|
68 Check nat.
|
adamc@227
|
69 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
70 nat
|
adamc@227
|
71 : Set
|
adam@302
|
72 ]]
|
adam@302
|
73 *)
|
adamc@227
|
74
|
adamc@227
|
75 (** printing $ %({}*% #(<a/>*# *)
|
adamc@227
|
76 (** printing ^ %*{})% #*<a/>)# *)
|
adamc@227
|
77
|
adamc@227
|
78 Check Set.
|
adamc@227
|
79 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
80 Set
|
adamc@227
|
81 : Type $ (0)+1 ^
|
adamc@227
|
82
|
adam@302
|
83 ]]
|
adam@302
|
84 *)
|
adamc@227
|
85
|
adamc@227
|
86 Check Type.
|
adamc@227
|
87 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
88 Type $ Top.3 ^
|
adamc@227
|
89 : Type $ (Top.3)+1 ^
|
adamc@227
|
90
|
adamc@227
|
91 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
92
|
adam@287
|
93 Occurrences of [Type] are annotated with some additional information, inside comments. These annotations have to do with the secret behind [Type]: it really stands for an infinite hierarchy of types. The type of [Set] is [Type(0)], the type of [Type(0)] is [Type(1)], the type of [Type(1)] is [Type(2)], and so on. This is how we avoid the %``%#"#[Type : Type]#"#%''% paradox. As a convenience, the universe hierarchy drives Coq's one variety of subtyping. Any term whose type is [Type] at level [i] is automatically also described by [Type] at level [j] when [j > i].
|
adamc@227
|
94
|
adamc@227
|
95 In the outputs of our first [Check] query, we see that the type level of [Set]'s type is [(0)+1]. Here [0] stands for the level of [Set], and we increment it to arrive at the level that %\textit{%#<i>#classifies#</i>#%}% [Set].
|
adamc@227
|
96
|
adam@343
|
97 In the second query's output, we see that the occurrence of [Type] that we check is assigned a fresh %\index{universe variable}\textit{%#<i>#universe variable#</i>#%}% [Top.3]. The output type increments [Top.3] to move up a level in the universe hierarchy. As we write code that uses definitions whose types mention universe variables, unification may refine the values of those variables. Luckily, the user rarely has to worry about the details.
|
adamc@227
|
98
|
adam@343
|
99 Another crucial concept in CIC is %\index{predicativity}\textit{%#<i>#predicativity#</i>#%}%. Consider these queries. *)
|
adamc@227
|
100
|
adamc@227
|
101 Check forall T : nat, fin T.
|
adamc@227
|
102 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
103 forall T : nat, fin T
|
adamc@227
|
104 : Set
|
adam@302
|
105 ]]
|
adam@302
|
106 *)
|
adamc@227
|
107
|
adamc@227
|
108 Check forall T : Set, T.
|
adamc@227
|
109 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
110 forall T : Set, T
|
adamc@227
|
111 : Type $ max(0, (0)+1) ^
|
adam@302
|
112 ]]
|
adam@302
|
113 *)
|
adamc@227
|
114
|
adamc@227
|
115 Check forall T : Type, T.
|
adamc@227
|
116 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
117 forall T : Type $ Top.9 ^ , T
|
adamc@227
|
118 : Type $ max(Top.9, (Top.9)+1) ^
|
adamc@227
|
119
|
adamc@227
|
120 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
121
|
adamc@227
|
122 These outputs demonstrate the rule for determining which universe a [forall] type lives in. In particular, for a type [forall x : T1, T2], we take the maximum of the universes of [T1] and [T2]. In the first example query, both [T1] ([nat]) and [T2] ([fin T]) are in [Set], so the [forall] type is in [Set], too. In the second query, [T1] is [Set], which is at level [(0)+1]; and [T2] is [T], which is at level [0]. Thus, the [forall] exists at the maximum of these two levels. The third example illustrates the same outcome, where we replace [Set] with an occurrence of [Type] that is assigned universe variable [Top.9]. This universe variable appears in the places where [0] appeared in the previous query.
|
adamc@227
|
123
|
adam@287
|
124 The behind-the-scenes manipulation of universe variables gives us predicativity. Consider this simple definition of a polymorphic identity function, where the first argument [T] will automatically be marked as implicit, since it can be inferred from the type of the second argument [x]. *)
|
adamc@227
|
125
|
adamc@227
|
126 Definition id (T : Set) (x : T) : T := x.
|
adamc@227
|
127
|
adamc@227
|
128 Check id 0.
|
adamc@227
|
129 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
130 id 0
|
adamc@227
|
131 : nat
|
adamc@227
|
132
|
adamc@227
|
133 Check id Set.
|
adam@343
|
134 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
135
|
adam@343
|
136 <<
|
adamc@227
|
137 Error: Illegal application (Type Error):
|
adamc@227
|
138 ...
|
adam@343
|
139 The 1st term has type "Type (* (Top.15)+1 *)" which should be coercible to "Set".
|
adam@343
|
140 >>
|
adamc@227
|
141
|
adam@343
|
142 The parameter [T] of [id] must be instantiated with a [Set]. The type [nat] is a [Set], but [Set] is not. We can try fixing the problem by generalizing our definition of [id]. *)
|
adamc@227
|
143
|
adamc@227
|
144 Reset id.
|
adamc@227
|
145 Definition id (T : Type) (x : T) : T := x.
|
adamc@227
|
146 Check id 0.
|
adamc@227
|
147 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
148 id 0
|
adamc@227
|
149 : nat
|
adam@302
|
150 ]]
|
adam@302
|
151 *)
|
adamc@227
|
152
|
adamc@227
|
153 Check id Set.
|
adamc@227
|
154 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
155 id Set
|
adamc@227
|
156 : Type $ Top.17 ^
|
adam@302
|
157 ]]
|
adam@302
|
158 *)
|
adamc@227
|
159
|
adamc@227
|
160 Check id Type.
|
adamc@227
|
161 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
162 id Type $ Top.18 ^
|
adamc@227
|
163 : Type $ Top.19 ^
|
adam@302
|
164 ]]
|
adam@302
|
165 *)
|
adamc@227
|
166
|
adamc@227
|
167 (** So far so good. As we apply [id] to different [T] values, the inferred index for [T]'s [Type] occurrence automatically moves higher up the type hierarchy.
|
adamc@227
|
168 [[
|
adamc@227
|
169 Check id id.
|
adam@343
|
170 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
171
|
adam@343
|
172 <<
|
adamc@227
|
173 Error: Universe inconsistency (cannot enforce Top.16 < Top.16).
|
adam@343
|
174 >>
|
adamc@227
|
175
|
adam@343
|
176 %\index{universe inconsistency}%This error message reminds us that the universe variable for [T] still exists, even though it is usually hidden. To apply [id] to itself, that variable would need to be less than itself in the type hierarchy. Universe inconsistency error messages announce cases like this one where a term could only type-check by violating an implied constraint over universe variables. Such errors demonstrate that [Type] is %\textit{%#<i>#predicative#</i>#%}%, where this word has a CIC meaning closely related to its usual mathematical meaning. A predicative system enforces the constraint that, for any object of quantified type, none of those quantifiers may ever be instantiated with the object itself. %\index{impredicativity}%Impredicativity is associated with popular paradoxes in set theory, involving inconsistent constructions like %``%#"#the set of all sets that do not contain themselves#"#%''% (%\index{Russell's paradox}%Russell's paradox). Similar paradoxes would result from uncontrolled impredicativity in Coq. *)
|
adamc@227
|
177
|
adamc@227
|
178
|
adamc@227
|
179 (** ** Inductive Definitions *)
|
adamc@227
|
180
|
adamc@227
|
181 (** Predicativity restrictions also apply to inductive definitions. As an example, let us consider a type of expression trees that allows injection of any native Coq value. The idea is that an [exp T] stands for a reflected expression of type [T].
|
adamc@227
|
182
|
adamc@227
|
183 [[
|
adamc@227
|
184 Inductive exp : Set -> Set :=
|
adamc@227
|
185 | Const : forall T : Set, T -> exp T
|
adamc@227
|
186 | Pair : forall T1 T2, exp T1 -> exp T2 -> exp (T1 * T2)
|
adamc@227
|
187 | Eq : forall T, exp T -> exp T -> exp bool.
|
adam@343
|
188 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
189
|
adam@343
|
190 <<
|
adamc@227
|
191 Error: Large non-propositional inductive types must be in Type.
|
adam@343
|
192 >>
|
adamc@227
|
193
|
adam@343
|
194 This definition is %\index{large inductive types}\textit{%#<i>#large#</i>#%}% in the sense that at least one of its constructors takes an argument whose type has type [Type]. Coq would be inconsistent if we allowed definitions like this one in their full generality. Instead, we must change [exp] to live in [Type]. We will go even further and move [exp]'s index to [Type] as well. *)
|
adamc@227
|
195
|
adamc@227
|
196 Inductive exp : Type -> Type :=
|
adamc@227
|
197 | Const : forall T, T -> exp T
|
adamc@227
|
198 | Pair : forall T1 T2, exp T1 -> exp T2 -> exp (T1 * T2)
|
adamc@227
|
199 | Eq : forall T, exp T -> exp T -> exp bool.
|
adamc@227
|
200
|
adamc@228
|
201 (** Note that before we had to include an annotation [: Set] for the variable [T] in [Const]'s type, but we need no annotation now. When the type of a variable is not known, and when that variable is used in a context where only types are allowed, Coq infers that the variable is of type [Type]. That is the right behavior here, but it was wrong for the [Set] version of [exp].
|
adamc@228
|
202
|
adamc@228
|
203 Our new definition is accepted. We can build some sample expressions. *)
|
adamc@227
|
204
|
adamc@227
|
205 Check Const 0.
|
adamc@227
|
206 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
207 Const 0
|
adamc@227
|
208 : exp nat
|
adam@302
|
209 ]]
|
adam@302
|
210 *)
|
adamc@227
|
211
|
adamc@227
|
212 Check Pair (Const 0) (Const tt).
|
adamc@227
|
213 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
214 Pair (Const 0) (Const tt)
|
adamc@227
|
215 : exp (nat * unit)
|
adam@302
|
216 ]]
|
adam@302
|
217 *)
|
adamc@227
|
218
|
adamc@227
|
219 Check Eq (Const Set) (Const Type).
|
adamc@227
|
220 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@228
|
221 Eq (Const Set) (Const Type $ Top.59 ^ )
|
adamc@227
|
222 : exp bool
|
adamc@227
|
223
|
adamc@227
|
224 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
225
|
adamc@227
|
226 We can check many expressions, including fancy expressions that include types. However, it is not hard to hit a type-checking wall.
|
adamc@227
|
227
|
adamc@227
|
228 [[
|
adamc@227
|
229 Check Const (Const O).
|
adam@343
|
230 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
231
|
adam@343
|
232 <<
|
adamc@227
|
233 Error: Universe inconsistency (cannot enforce Top.42 < Top.42).
|
adam@343
|
234 >>
|
adamc@227
|
235
|
adamc@227
|
236 We are unable to instantiate the parameter [T] of [Const] with an [exp] type. To see why, it is helpful to print the annotated version of [exp]'s inductive definition. *)
|
adamc@227
|
237
|
adamc@227
|
238 Print exp.
|
adamc@227
|
239 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
240 Inductive exp
|
adamc@227
|
241 : Type $ Top.8 ^ ->
|
adamc@227
|
242 Type
|
adamc@227
|
243 $ max(0, (Top.11)+1, (Top.14)+1, (Top.15)+1, (Top.19)+1) ^ :=
|
adamc@227
|
244 Const : forall T : Type $ Top.11 ^ , T -> exp T
|
adamc@227
|
245 | Pair : forall (T1 : Type $ Top.14 ^ ) (T2 : Type $ Top.15 ^ ),
|
adamc@227
|
246 exp T1 -> exp T2 -> exp (T1 * T2)
|
adamc@227
|
247 | Eq : forall T : Type $ Top.19 ^ , exp T -> exp T -> exp bool
|
adamc@227
|
248
|
adamc@227
|
249 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
250
|
adamc@227
|
251 We see that the index type of [exp] has been assigned to universe level [Top.8]. In addition, each of the four occurrences of [Type] in the types of the constructors gets its own universe variable. Each of these variables appears explicitly in the type of [exp]. In particular, any type [exp T] lives at a universe level found by incrementing by one the maximum of the four argument variables. A consequence of this is that [exp] %\textit{%#<i>#must#</i>#%}% live at a higher universe level than any type which may be passed to one of its constructors. This consequence led to the universe inconsistency.
|
adamc@227
|
252
|
adam@343
|
253 Strangely, the universe variable [Top.8] only appears in one place. Is there no restriction imposed on which types are valid arguments to [exp]? In fact, there is a restriction, but it only appears in a global set of universe constraints that are maintained %``%#"#off to the side,#"#%''% not appearing explicitly in types. We can print the current database.%\index{Vernacular commands!Print Universes}% *)
|
adamc@227
|
254
|
adamc@227
|
255 Print Universes.
|
adamc@227
|
256 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
257 Top.19 < Top.9 <= Top.8
|
adamc@227
|
258 Top.15 < Top.9 <= Top.8 <= Coq.Init.Datatypes.38
|
adamc@227
|
259 Top.14 < Top.9 <= Top.8 <= Coq.Init.Datatypes.37
|
adamc@227
|
260 Top.11 < Top.9 <= Top.8
|
adamc@227
|
261
|
adamc@227
|
262 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
263
|
adam@343
|
264 The command outputs many more constraints, but we have collected only those that mention [Top] variables. We see one constraint for each universe variable associated with a constructor argument from [exp]'s definition. Universe variable [Top.19] is the type argument to [Eq]. The constraint for [Top.19] effectively says that [Top.19] must be less than [Top.8], the universe of [exp]'s indices; an intermediate variable [Top.9] appears as an artifact of the way the constraint was generated.
|
adamc@227
|
265
|
adamc@227
|
266 The next constraint, for [Top.15], is more complicated. This is the universe of the second argument to the [Pair] constructor. Not only must [Top.15] be less than [Top.8], but it also comes out that [Top.8] must be less than [Coq.Init.Datatypes.38]. What is this new universe variable? It is from the definition of the [prod] inductive family, to which types of the form [A * B] are desugared. *)
|
adamc@227
|
267
|
adamc@227
|
268 Print prod.
|
adamc@227
|
269 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
270 Inductive prod (A : Type $ Coq.Init.Datatypes.37 ^ )
|
adamc@227
|
271 (B : Type $ Coq.Init.Datatypes.38 ^ )
|
adamc@227
|
272 : Type $ max(Coq.Init.Datatypes.37, Coq.Init.Datatypes.38) ^ :=
|
adamc@227
|
273 pair : A -> B -> A * B
|
adamc@227
|
274
|
adamc@227
|
275 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
276
|
adamc@227
|
277 We see that the constraint is enforcing that indices to [exp] must not live in a higher universe level than [B]-indices to [prod]. The next constraint above establishes a symmetric condition for [A].
|
adamc@227
|
278
|
adamc@227
|
279 Thus it is apparent that Coq maintains a tortuous set of universe variable inequalities behind the scenes. It may look like some functions are polymorphic in the universe levels of their arguments, but what is really happening is imperative updating of a system of constraints, such that all uses of a function are consistent with a global set of universe levels. When the constraint system may not be evolved soundly, we get a universe inconsistency error.
|
adamc@227
|
280
|
adamc@227
|
281 %\medskip%
|
adamc@227
|
282
|
adamc@227
|
283 Something interesting is revealed in the annotated definition of [prod]. A type [prod A B] lives at a universe that is the maximum of the universes of [A] and [B]. From our earlier experiments, we might expect that [prod]'s universe would in fact need to be %\textit{%#<i>#one higher#</i>#%}% than the maximum. The critical difference is that, in the definition of [prod], [A] and [B] are defined as %\textit{%#<i>#parameters#</i>#%}%; that is, they appear named to the left of the main colon, rather than appearing (possibly unnamed) to the right.
|
adamc@227
|
284
|
adamc@231
|
285 Parameters are not as flexible as normal inductive type arguments. The range types of all of the constructors of a parameterized type must share the same parameters. Nonetheless, when it is possible to define a polymorphic type in this way, we gain the ability to use the new type family in more ways, without triggering universe inconsistencies. For instance, nested pairs of types are perfectly legal. *)
|
adamc@227
|
286
|
adamc@227
|
287 Check (nat, (Type, Set)).
|
adamc@227
|
288 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@227
|
289 (nat, (Type $ Top.44 ^ , Set))
|
adamc@227
|
290 : Set * (Type $ Top.45 ^ * Type $ Top.46 ^ )
|
adamc@227
|
291 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
292
|
adamc@227
|
293 The same cannot be done with a counterpart to [prod] that does not use parameters. *)
|
adamc@227
|
294
|
adamc@227
|
295 Inductive prod' : Type -> Type -> Type :=
|
adamc@227
|
296 | pair' : forall A B : Type, A -> B -> prod' A B.
|
adamc@227
|
297 (** [[
|
adamc@227
|
298 Check (pair' nat (pair' Type Set)).
|
adam@343
|
299 ]]
|
adamc@227
|
300
|
adam@343
|
301 <<
|
adamc@227
|
302 Error: Universe inconsistency (cannot enforce Top.51 < Top.51).
|
adam@343
|
303 >>
|
adamc@227
|
304
|
adamc@233
|
305 The key benefit parameters bring us is the ability to avoid quantifying over types in the types of constructors. Such quantification induces less-than constraints, while parameters only introduce less-than-or-equal-to constraints.
|
adamc@233
|
306
|
adam@343
|
307 Coq includes one more (potentially confusing) feature related to parameters. While Gallina does not support real %\index{universe polymorphism}%universe polymorphism, there is a convenience facility that mimics universe polymorphism in some cases. We can illustrate what this means with a simple example. *)
|
adamc@233
|
308
|
adamc@233
|
309 Inductive foo (A : Type) : Type :=
|
adamc@233
|
310 | Foo : A -> foo A.
|
adamc@229
|
311
|
adamc@229
|
312 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@229
|
313 Unset Printing Universes.
|
adamc@229
|
314 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@229
|
315
|
adamc@233
|
316 Check foo nat.
|
adamc@233
|
317 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@233
|
318 foo nat
|
adamc@233
|
319 : Set
|
adam@302
|
320 ]]
|
adam@302
|
321 *)
|
adamc@233
|
322
|
adamc@233
|
323 Check foo Set.
|
adamc@233
|
324 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@233
|
325 foo Set
|
adamc@233
|
326 : Type
|
adam@302
|
327 ]]
|
adam@302
|
328 *)
|
adamc@233
|
329
|
adamc@233
|
330 Check foo True.
|
adamc@233
|
331 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@233
|
332 foo True
|
adamc@233
|
333 : Prop
|
adamc@233
|
334
|
adamc@233
|
335 ]]
|
adamc@233
|
336
|
adam@287
|
337 The basic pattern here is that Coq is willing to automatically build a %``%#"#copied-and-pasted#"#%''% version of an inductive definition, where some occurrences of [Type] have been replaced by [Set] or [Prop]. In each context, the type-checker tries to find the valid replacements that are lowest in the type hierarchy. Automatic cloning of definitions can be much more convenient than manual cloning. We have already taken advantage of the fact that we may re-use the same families of tuple and list types to form values in [Set] and [Type].
|
adamc@233
|
338
|
adamc@233
|
339 Imitation polymorphism can be confusing in some contexts. For instance, it is what is responsible for this weird behavior. *)
|
adamc@233
|
340
|
adamc@233
|
341 Inductive bar : Type := Bar : bar.
|
adamc@233
|
342
|
adamc@233
|
343 Check bar.
|
adamc@233
|
344 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@233
|
345 bar
|
adamc@233
|
346 : Prop
|
adamc@233
|
347 ]]
|
adamc@233
|
348
|
adamc@233
|
349 The type that Coq comes up with may be used in strictly more contexts than the type one might have expected. *)
|
adamc@233
|
350
|
adamc@229
|
351
|
adamc@229
|
352 (** * The [Prop] Universe *)
|
adamc@229
|
353
|
adam@287
|
354 (** In Chapter 4, we saw parallel versions of useful datatypes for %``%#"#programs#"#%''% and %``%#"#proofs.#"#%''% The convention was that programs live in [Set], and proofs live in [Prop]. We gave little explanation for why it is useful to maintain this distinction. There is certainly documentation value from separating programs from proofs; in practice, different concerns apply to building the two types of objects. It turns out, however, that these concerns motivate formal differences between the two universes in Coq.
|
adamc@229
|
355
|
adamc@229
|
356 Recall the types [sig] and [ex], which are the program and proof versions of existential quantification. Their definitions differ only in one place, where [sig] uses [Type] and [ex] uses [Prop]. *)
|
adamc@229
|
357
|
adamc@229
|
358 Print sig.
|
adamc@229
|
359 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@229
|
360 Inductive sig (A : Type) (P : A -> Prop) : Type :=
|
adamc@229
|
361 exist : forall x : A, P x -> sig P
|
adam@302
|
362 ]]
|
adam@302
|
363 *)
|
adamc@229
|
364
|
adamc@229
|
365 Print ex.
|
adamc@229
|
366 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@229
|
367 Inductive ex (A : Type) (P : A -> Prop) : Prop :=
|
adamc@229
|
368 ex_intro : forall x : A, P x -> ex P
|
adamc@229
|
369 ]]
|
adamc@229
|
370
|
adamc@229
|
371 It is natural to want a function to extract the first components of data structures like these. Doing so is easy enough for [sig]. *)
|
adamc@229
|
372
|
adamc@229
|
373 Definition projS A (P : A -> Prop) (x : sig P) : A :=
|
adamc@229
|
374 match x with
|
adamc@229
|
375 | exist v _ => v
|
adamc@229
|
376 end.
|
adamc@229
|
377
|
adamc@229
|
378 (** We run into trouble with a version that has been changed to work with [ex].
|
adamc@229
|
379 [[
|
adamc@229
|
380 Definition projE A (P : A -> Prop) (x : ex P) : A :=
|
adamc@229
|
381 match x with
|
adamc@229
|
382 | ex_intro v _ => v
|
adamc@229
|
383 end.
|
adam@343
|
384 ]]
|
adamc@229
|
385
|
adam@343
|
386 <<
|
adamc@229
|
387 Error:
|
adamc@229
|
388 Incorrect elimination of "x" in the inductive type "ex":
|
adamc@229
|
389 the return type has sort "Type" while it should be "Prop".
|
adamc@229
|
390 Elimination of an inductive object of sort Prop
|
adamc@229
|
391 is not allowed on a predicate in sort Type
|
adamc@229
|
392 because proofs can be eliminated only to build proofs.
|
adam@343
|
393 >>
|
adamc@229
|
394
|
adam@343
|
395 In formal Coq parlance, %\index{elimination}``%#"#elimination#"#%''% means %``%#"#pattern-matching.#"#%''% The typing rules of Gallina forbid us from pattern-matching on a discriminee whose type belongs to [Prop], whenever the result type of the [match] has a type besides [Prop]. This is a sort of %``%#"#information flow#"#%''% policy, where the type system ensures that the details of proofs can never have any effect on parts of a development that are not also marked as proofs.
|
adamc@229
|
396
|
adamc@229
|
397 This restriction matches informal practice. We think of programs and proofs as clearly separated, and, outside of constructive logic, the idea of computing with proofs is ill-formed. The distinction also has practical importance in Coq, where it affects the behavior of extraction.
|
adamc@229
|
398
|
adam@343
|
399 Recall that %\index{program extraction}%extraction is Coq's facility for translating Coq developments into programs in general-purpose programming languages like OCaml. Extraction %\textit{%#<i>#erases#</i>#%}% proofs and leaves programs intact. A simple example with [sig] and [ex] demonstrates the distinction. *)
|
adamc@229
|
400
|
adamc@229
|
401 Definition sym_sig (x : sig (fun n => n = 0)) : sig (fun n => 0 = n) :=
|
adamc@229
|
402 match x with
|
adamc@229
|
403 | exist n pf => exist _ n (sym_eq pf)
|
adamc@229
|
404 end.
|
adamc@229
|
405
|
adamc@229
|
406 Extraction sym_sig.
|
adamc@229
|
407 (** <<
|
adamc@229
|
408 (** val sym_sig : nat -> nat **)
|
adamc@229
|
409
|
adamc@229
|
410 let sym_sig x = x
|
adamc@229
|
411 >>
|
adamc@229
|
412
|
adamc@229
|
413 Since extraction erases proofs, the second components of [sig] values are elided, making [sig] a simple identity type family. The [sym_sig] operation is thus an identity function. *)
|
adamc@229
|
414
|
adamc@229
|
415 Definition sym_ex (x : ex (fun n => n = 0)) : ex (fun n => 0 = n) :=
|
adamc@229
|
416 match x with
|
adamc@229
|
417 | ex_intro n pf => ex_intro _ n (sym_eq pf)
|
adamc@229
|
418 end.
|
adamc@229
|
419
|
adamc@229
|
420 Extraction sym_ex.
|
adamc@229
|
421 (** <<
|
adamc@229
|
422 (** val sym_ex : __ **)
|
adamc@229
|
423
|
adamc@229
|
424 let sym_ex = __
|
adamc@229
|
425 >>
|
adamc@229
|
426
|
adam@302
|
427 In this example, the [ex] type itself is in [Prop], so whole [ex] packages are erased. Coq extracts every proposition as the (Coq-specific) type %\texttt{\_\_}%#<tt>__</tt>#, whose single constructor is %\texttt{\_\_}%#<tt>__</tt>#. Not only are proofs replaced by [__], but proof arguments to functions are also removed completely, as we see here.
|
adamc@229
|
428
|
adam@343
|
429 Extraction is very helpful as an optimization over programs that contain proofs. In languages like Haskell, advanced features make it possible to program with proofs, as a way of convincing the type checker to accept particular definitions. Unfortunately, when proofs are encoded as values in GADTs%~\cite{GADT}%, these proofs exist at runtime and consume resources. In contrast, with Coq, as long as all proofs are kept within [Prop], extraction is guaranteed to erase them.
|
adamc@229
|
430
|
adam@343
|
431 Many fans of the %\index{Curry-Howard correspondence}%Curry-Howard correspondence support the idea of %\textit{%#<i>#extracting programs from proofs#</i>#%}%. In reality, few users of Coq and related tools do any such thing. Instead, extraction is better thought of as an optimization that reduces the runtime costs of expressive typing.
|
adamc@229
|
432
|
adamc@229
|
433 %\medskip%
|
adamc@229
|
434
|
adam@343
|
435 We have seen two of the differences between proofs and programs: proofs are subject to an elimination restriction and are elided by extraction. The remaining difference is that [Prop] is %\index{impredicativity}\textit{%#<i>#impredicative#</i>#%}%, as this example shows. *)
|
adamc@229
|
436
|
adamc@229
|
437 Check forall P Q : Prop, P \/ Q -> Q \/ P.
|
adamc@229
|
438 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@229
|
439 forall P Q : Prop, P \/ Q -> Q \/ P
|
adamc@229
|
440 : Prop
|
adamc@229
|
441
|
adamc@229
|
442 ]]
|
adamc@229
|
443
|
adamc@230
|
444 We see that it is possible to define a [Prop] that quantifies over other [Prop]s. This is fortunate, as we start wanting that ability even for such basic purposes as stating propositional tautologies. In the next section of this chapter, we will see some reasons why unrestricted impredicativity is undesirable. The impredicativity of [Prop] interacts crucially with the elimination restriction to avoid those pitfalls.
|
adamc@230
|
445
|
adamc@230
|
446 Impredicativity also allows us to implement a version of our earlier [exp] type that does not suffer from the weakness that we found. *)
|
adamc@230
|
447
|
adamc@230
|
448 Inductive expP : Type -> Prop :=
|
adamc@230
|
449 | ConstP : forall T, T -> expP T
|
adamc@230
|
450 | PairP : forall T1 T2, expP T1 -> expP T2 -> expP (T1 * T2)
|
adamc@230
|
451 | EqP : forall T, expP T -> expP T -> expP bool.
|
adamc@230
|
452
|
adamc@230
|
453 Check ConstP 0.
|
adamc@230
|
454 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
455 ConstP 0
|
adamc@230
|
456 : expP nat
|
adam@302
|
457 ]]
|
adam@302
|
458 *)
|
adamc@230
|
459
|
adamc@230
|
460 Check PairP (ConstP 0) (ConstP tt).
|
adamc@230
|
461 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
462 PairP (ConstP 0) (ConstP tt)
|
adamc@230
|
463 : expP (nat * unit)
|
adam@302
|
464 ]]
|
adam@302
|
465 *)
|
adamc@230
|
466
|
adamc@230
|
467 Check EqP (ConstP Set) (ConstP Type).
|
adamc@230
|
468 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
469 EqP (ConstP Set) (ConstP Type)
|
adamc@230
|
470 : expP bool
|
adam@302
|
471 ]]
|
adam@302
|
472 *)
|
adamc@230
|
473
|
adamc@230
|
474 Check ConstP (ConstP O).
|
adamc@230
|
475 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
476 ConstP (ConstP 0)
|
adamc@230
|
477 : expP (expP nat)
|
adamc@230
|
478
|
adamc@230
|
479 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
480
|
adam@287
|
481 In this case, our victory is really a shallow one. As we have marked [expP] as a family of proofs, we cannot deconstruct our expressions in the usual programmatic ways, which makes them almost useless for the usual purposes. Impredicative quantification is much more useful in defining inductive families that we really think of as judgments. For instance, this code defines a notion of equality that is strictly more permissive than the base equality [=]. *)
|
adamc@230
|
482
|
adamc@230
|
483 Inductive eqPlus : forall T, T -> T -> Prop :=
|
adamc@230
|
484 | Base : forall T (x : T), eqPlus x x
|
adamc@230
|
485 | Func : forall dom ran (f1 f2 : dom -> ran),
|
adamc@230
|
486 (forall x : dom, eqPlus (f1 x) (f2 x))
|
adamc@230
|
487 -> eqPlus f1 f2.
|
adamc@230
|
488
|
adamc@230
|
489 Check (Base 0).
|
adamc@230
|
490 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
491 Base 0
|
adamc@230
|
492 : eqPlus 0 0
|
adam@302
|
493 ]]
|
adam@302
|
494 *)
|
adamc@230
|
495
|
adamc@230
|
496 Check (Func (fun n => n) (fun n => 0 + n) (fun n => Base n)).
|
adamc@230
|
497 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
498 Func (fun n : nat => n) (fun n : nat => 0 + n) (fun n : nat => Base n)
|
adamc@230
|
499 : eqPlus (fun n : nat => n) (fun n : nat => 0 + n)
|
adam@302
|
500 ]]
|
adam@302
|
501 *)
|
adamc@230
|
502
|
adamc@230
|
503 Check (Base (Base 1)).
|
adamc@230
|
504 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
505 Base (Base 1)
|
adamc@230
|
506 : eqPlus (Base 1) (Base 1)
|
adam@302
|
507 ]]
|
adam@302
|
508 *)
|
adamc@230
|
509
|
adam@343
|
510 (** Stating equality facts about proofs may seem baroque, but we have already seen its utility in the chapter on reasoning about equality proofs. *)
|
adam@343
|
511
|
adamc@230
|
512
|
adamc@230
|
513 (** * Axioms *)
|
adamc@230
|
514
|
adam@343
|
515 (** While the specific logic Gallina is hardcoded into Coq's implementation, it is possible to add certain logical rules in a controlled way. In other words, Coq may be used to reason about many different refinements of Gallina where strictly more theorems are provable. We achieve this by asserting %\index{axioms}\textit{%#<i>#axioms#</i>#%}% without proof.
|
adamc@230
|
516
|
adamc@230
|
517 We will motivate the idea by touring through some standard axioms, as enumerated in Coq's online FAQ. I will add additional commentary as appropriate. *)
|
adamc@230
|
518
|
adamc@230
|
519 (** ** The Basics *)
|
adamc@230
|
520
|
adam@343
|
521 (** One simple example of a useful axiom is the %\index{law of the excluded middle}%law of the excluded middle. *)
|
adamc@230
|
522
|
adamc@230
|
523 Require Import Classical_Prop.
|
adamc@230
|
524 Print classic.
|
adamc@230
|
525 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
526 *** [ classic : forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P ]
|
adamc@230
|
527 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
528
|
adam@343
|
529 In the implementation of module [Classical_Prop], this axiom was defined with the command%\index{Vernacular commands!Axiom}% *)
|
adamc@230
|
530
|
adamc@230
|
531 Axiom classic : forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P.
|
adamc@230
|
532
|
adam@343
|
533 (** An [Axiom] may be declared with any type, in any of the universes. There is a synonym %\index{Vernacular commands!Parameter}%[Parameter] for [Axiom], and that synonym is often clearer for assertions not of type [Prop]. For instance, we can assert the existence of objects with certain properties. *)
|
adamc@230
|
534
|
adamc@230
|
535 Parameter n : nat.
|
adamc@230
|
536 Axiom positive : n > 0.
|
adamc@230
|
537 Reset n.
|
adamc@230
|
538
|
adam@287
|
539 (** This kind of %``%#"#axiomatic presentation#"#%''% of a theory is very common outside of higher-order logic. However, in Coq, it is almost always preferable to stick to defining your objects, functions, and predicates via inductive definitions and functional programming.
|
adamc@230
|
540
|
adam@343
|
541 In general, there is a significant burden associated with any use of axioms. It is easy to assert a set of axioms that together is %\index{inconsistent axioms}\textit{%#<i>#inconsistent#</i>#%}%. That is, a set of axioms may imply [False], which allows any theorem to proved, which defeats the purpose of a proof assistant. For example, we could assert the following axiom, which is consistent by itself but inconsistent when combined with [classic]. *)
|
adamc@230
|
542
|
adam@287
|
543 Axiom not_classic : ~ forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P.
|
adamc@230
|
544
|
adamc@230
|
545 Theorem uhoh : False.
|
adam@287
|
546 generalize classic not_classic; tauto.
|
adamc@230
|
547 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
548
|
adamc@230
|
549 Theorem uhoh_again : 1 + 1 = 3.
|
adamc@230
|
550 destruct uhoh.
|
adamc@230
|
551 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
552
|
adamc@230
|
553 Reset not_classic.
|
adamc@230
|
554
|
adam@343
|
555 (** On the subject of the law of the excluded middle itself, this axiom is usually quite harmless, and many practical Coq developments assume it. It has been proved metatheoretically to be consistent with CIC. Here, %``%#"#proved metatheoretically#"#%''% means that someone proved on paper that excluded middle holds in a %\textit{%#<i>#model#</i>#%}% of CIC in set theory%~\cite{SetsInTypes}%. All of the other axioms that we will survey in this section hold in the same model, so they are all consistent together.
|
adamc@230
|
556
|
adam@343
|
557 Recall that Coq implements %\index{constructive logic}\textit{%#<i>#constructive#</i>#%}% logic by default, where excluded middle is not provable. Proofs in constructive logic can be thought of as programs. A [forall] quantifier denotes a dependent function type, and a disjunction denotes a variant type. In such a setting, excluded middle could be interpreted as a decision procedure for arbitrary propositions, which computability theory tells us cannot exist. Thus, constructive logic with excluded middle can no longer be associated with our usual notion of programming.
|
adamc@230
|
558
|
adamc@231
|
559 Given all this, why is it all right to assert excluded middle as an axiom? The intuitive justification is that the elimination restriction for [Prop] prevents us from treating proofs as programs. An excluded middle axiom that quantified over [Set] instead of [Prop] %\textit{%#<i>#would#</i>#%}% be problematic. If a development used that axiom, we would not be able to extract the code to OCaml (soundly) without implementing a genuine universal decision procedure. In contrast, values whose types belong to [Prop] are always erased by extraction, so we sidestep the axiom's algorithmic consequences.
|
adamc@230
|
560
|
adam@343
|
561 Because the proper use of axioms is so precarious, there are helpful commands for determining which axioms a theorem relies on.%\index{Vernacular commands!Print Assumptions}% *)
|
adamc@230
|
562
|
adamc@230
|
563 Theorem t1 : forall P : Prop, P -> ~ ~ P.
|
adamc@230
|
564 tauto.
|
adamc@230
|
565 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
566
|
adamc@230
|
567 Print Assumptions t1.
|
adam@343
|
568 (** <<
|
adamc@230
|
569 Closed under the global context
|
adam@343
|
570 >>
|
adam@302
|
571 *)
|
adamc@230
|
572
|
adamc@230
|
573 Theorem t2 : forall P : Prop, ~ ~ P -> P.
|
adamc@230
|
574 (** [[
|
adamc@230
|
575 tauto.
|
adam@343
|
576 ]]
|
adam@343
|
577 <<
|
adamc@230
|
578 Error: tauto failed.
|
adam@343
|
579 >>
|
adam@302
|
580 *)
|
adamc@230
|
581 intro P; destruct (classic P); tauto.
|
adamc@230
|
582 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
583
|
adamc@230
|
584 Print Assumptions t2.
|
adamc@230
|
585 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
586 Axioms:
|
adamc@230
|
587 classic : forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P
|
adamc@230
|
588 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
589
|
adamc@231
|
590 It is possible to avoid this dependence in some specific cases, where excluded middle %\textit{%#<i>#is#</i>#%}% provable, for decidable families of propositions. *)
|
adamc@230
|
591
|
adam@287
|
592 Theorem nat_eq_dec : forall n m : nat, n = m \/ n <> m.
|
adamc@230
|
593 induction n; destruct m; intuition; generalize (IHn m); intuition.
|
adamc@230
|
594 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
595
|
adamc@230
|
596 Theorem t2' : forall n m : nat, ~ ~ (n = m) -> n = m.
|
adam@287
|
597 intros n m; destruct (nat_eq_dec n m); tauto.
|
adamc@230
|
598 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
599
|
adamc@230
|
600 Print Assumptions t2'.
|
adam@343
|
601 (** <<
|
adamc@230
|
602 Closed under the global context
|
adam@343
|
603 >>
|
adamc@230
|
604
|
adamc@230
|
605 %\bigskip%
|
adamc@230
|
606
|
adam@343
|
607 Mainstream mathematical practice assumes excluded middle, so it can be useful to have it available in Coq developments, though it is also nice to know that a theorem is proved in a simpler formal system than classical logic. There is a similar story for %\index{proof irrelevance}\textit{%#<i>#proof irrelevance#</i>#%}%, which simplifies proof issues that would not even arise in mainstream math. *)
|
adamc@230
|
608
|
adamc@230
|
609 Require Import ProofIrrelevance.
|
adamc@230
|
610 Print proof_irrelevance.
|
adamc@230
|
611 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
612 *** [ proof_irrelevance : forall (P : Prop) (p1 p2 : P), p1 = p2 ]
|
adamc@230
|
613 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
614
|
adam@350
|
615 This axiom asserts that any two proofs of the same proposition are equal. If we replaced [p1 = p2] by [p1 <-> p2], then the statement would be provable. However, equality is a stronger notion than logical equivalence. Recall this example function from Chapter 7. *)
|
adamc@230
|
616
|
adamc@230
|
617 (* begin hide *)
|
adamc@230
|
618 Lemma zgtz : 0 > 0 -> False.
|
adamc@230
|
619 crush.
|
adamc@230
|
620 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
621 (* end hide *)
|
adamc@230
|
622
|
adamc@230
|
623 Definition pred_strong1 (n : nat) : n > 0 -> nat :=
|
adamc@230
|
624 match n with
|
adamc@230
|
625 | O => fun pf : 0 > 0 => match zgtz pf with end
|
adamc@230
|
626 | S n' => fun _ => n'
|
adamc@230
|
627 end.
|
adamc@230
|
628
|
adam@343
|
629 (** We might want to prove that different proofs of [n > 0] do not lead to different results from our richly typed predecessor function. *)
|
adamc@230
|
630
|
adamc@230
|
631 Theorem pred_strong1_irrel : forall n (pf1 pf2 : n > 0), pred_strong1 pf1 = pred_strong1 pf2.
|
adamc@230
|
632 destruct n; crush.
|
adamc@230
|
633 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
634
|
adamc@230
|
635 (** The proof script is simple, but it involved peeking into the definition of [pred_strong1]. For more complicated function definitions, it can be considerably more work to prove that they do not discriminate on details of proof arguments. This can seem like a shame, since the [Prop] elimination restriction makes it impossible to write any function that does otherwise. Unfortunately, this fact is only true metatheoretically, unless we assert an axiom like [proof_irrelevance]. With that axiom, we can prove our theorem without consulting the definition of [pred_strong1]. *)
|
adamc@230
|
636
|
adamc@230
|
637 Theorem pred_strong1_irrel' : forall n (pf1 pf2 : n > 0), pred_strong1 pf1 = pred_strong1 pf2.
|
adamc@230
|
638 intros; f_equal; apply proof_irrelevance.
|
adamc@230
|
639 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
640
|
adamc@230
|
641
|
adamc@230
|
642 (** %\bigskip%
|
adamc@230
|
643
|
adamc@230
|
644 In the chapter on equality, we already discussed some axioms that are related to proof irrelevance. In particular, Coq's standard library includes this axiom: *)
|
adamc@230
|
645
|
adamc@230
|
646 Require Import Eqdep.
|
adamc@230
|
647 Import Eq_rect_eq.
|
adamc@230
|
648 Print eq_rect_eq.
|
adamc@230
|
649 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
650 *** [ eq_rect_eq :
|
adamc@230
|
651 forall (U : Type) (p : U) (Q : U -> Type) (x : Q p) (h : p = p),
|
adamc@230
|
652 x = eq_rect p Q x p h ]
|
adamc@230
|
653 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
654
|
adam@343
|
655 This axiom says that it is permissible to simplify pattern matches over proofs of equalities like [e = e]. The axiom is logically equivalent to some simpler corollaries. In the theorem names, %``%#"#UIP#"#%''% stands for %\index{unicity of identity proofs}``%#"#unicity of identity proofs#"#%''%, where %``%#"#identity#"#%''% is a synonym for %``%#"#equality.#"#%''% *)
|
adamc@230
|
656
|
adamc@230
|
657 Corollary UIP_refl : forall A (x : A) (pf : x = x), pf = refl_equal x.
|
adamc@230
|
658 intros; replace pf with (eq_rect x (eq x) (refl_equal x) x pf); [
|
adamc@230
|
659 symmetry; apply eq_rect_eq
|
adamc@230
|
660 | exact (match pf as pf' return match pf' in _ = y return x = y with
|
adamc@230
|
661 | refl_equal => refl_equal x
|
adamc@230
|
662 end = pf' with
|
adamc@230
|
663 | refl_equal => refl_equal _
|
adamc@230
|
664 end) ].
|
adamc@230
|
665 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
666
|
adamc@230
|
667 Corollary UIP : forall A (x y : A) (pf1 pf2 : x = y), pf1 = pf2.
|
adamc@230
|
668 intros; generalize pf1 pf2; subst; intros;
|
adamc@230
|
669 match goal with
|
adamc@230
|
670 | [ |- ?pf1 = ?pf2 ] => rewrite (UIP_refl pf1); rewrite (UIP_refl pf2); reflexivity
|
adamc@230
|
671 end.
|
adamc@230
|
672 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
673
|
adamc@231
|
674 (** These corollaries are special cases of proof irrelevance. In developments that only need proof irrelevance for equality, there is no need to assert full irrelevance.
|
adamc@230
|
675
|
adamc@230
|
676 Another facet of proof irrelevance is that, like excluded middle, it is often provable for specific propositions. For instance, [UIP] is provable whenever the type [A] has a decidable equality operation. The module [Eqdep_dec] of the standard library contains a proof. A similar phenomenon applies to other notable cases, including less-than proofs. Thus, it is often possible to use proof irrelevance without asserting axioms.
|
adamc@230
|
677
|
adamc@230
|
678 %\bigskip%
|
adamc@230
|
679
|
adamc@230
|
680 There are two more basic axioms that are often assumed, to avoid complications that do not arise in set theory. *)
|
adamc@230
|
681
|
adamc@230
|
682 Require Import FunctionalExtensionality.
|
adamc@230
|
683 Print functional_extensionality_dep.
|
adamc@230
|
684 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
685 *** [ functional_extensionality_dep :
|
adamc@230
|
686 forall (A : Type) (B : A -> Type) (f g : forall x : A, B x),
|
adamc@230
|
687 (forall x : A, f x = g x) -> f = g ]
|
adamc@230
|
688
|
adamc@230
|
689 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
690
|
adamc@230
|
691 This axiom says that two functions are equal if they map equal inputs to equal outputs. Such facts are not provable in general in CIC, but it is consistent to assume that they are.
|
adamc@230
|
692
|
adam@343
|
693 A simple corollary shows that the same property applies to predicates. *)
|
adamc@230
|
694
|
adamc@230
|
695 Corollary predicate_extensionality : forall (A : Type) (B : A -> Prop) (f g : forall x : A, B x),
|
adamc@230
|
696 (forall x : A, f x = g x) -> f = g.
|
adamc@230
|
697 intros; apply functional_extensionality_dep; assumption.
|
adamc@230
|
698 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
699
|
adam@343
|
700 (** In some cases, one might prefer to assert this corollary as the axiom, to restrict the consequences to proofs and not programs. *)
|
adam@343
|
701
|
adamc@230
|
702
|
adamc@230
|
703 (** ** Axioms of Choice *)
|
adamc@230
|
704
|
adam@343
|
705 (** Some Coq axioms are also points of contention in mainstream math. The most prominent example is the %\index{axiom of choice}%axiom of choice. In fact, there are multiple versions that we might consider, and, considered in isolation, none of these versions means quite what it means in classical set theory.
|
adamc@230
|
706
|
adamc@230
|
707 First, it is possible to implement a choice operator %\textit{%#<i>#without#</i>#%}% axioms in some potentially surprising cases. *)
|
adamc@230
|
708
|
adamc@230
|
709 Require Import ConstructiveEpsilon.
|
adamc@230
|
710 Check constructive_definite_description.
|
adamc@230
|
711 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
712 constructive_definite_description
|
adamc@230
|
713 : forall (A : Set) (f : A -> nat) (g : nat -> A),
|
adamc@230
|
714 (forall x : A, g (f x) = x) ->
|
adamc@230
|
715 forall P : A -> Prop,
|
adamc@230
|
716 (forall x : A, {P x} + {~ P x}) ->
|
adamc@230
|
717 (exists! x : A, P x) -> {x : A | P x}
|
adam@302
|
718 ]]
|
adam@302
|
719 *)
|
adamc@230
|
720
|
adamc@230
|
721 Print Assumptions constructive_definite_description.
|
adam@343
|
722 (** <<
|
adamc@230
|
723 Closed under the global context
|
adam@343
|
724 >>
|
adamc@230
|
725
|
adamc@231
|
726 This function transforms a decidable predicate [P] into a function that produces an element satisfying [P] from a proof that such an element exists. The functions [f] and [g], in conjunction with an associated injectivity property, are used to express the idea that the set [A] is countable. Under these conditions, a simple brute force algorithm gets the job done: we just enumerate all elements of [A], stopping when we find one satisfying [P]. The existence proof, specified in terms of %\textit{%#<i>#unique#</i>#%}% existence [exists!], guarantees termination. The definition of this operator in Coq uses some interesting techniques, as seen in the implementation of the [ConstructiveEpsilon] module.
|
adamc@230
|
727
|
adamc@230
|
728 Countable choice is provable in set theory without appealing to the general axiom of choice. To support the more general principle in Coq, we must also add an axiom. Here is a functional version of the axiom of unique choice. *)
|
adamc@230
|
729
|
adamc@230
|
730 Require Import ClassicalUniqueChoice.
|
adamc@230
|
731 Check dependent_unique_choice.
|
adamc@230
|
732 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
733 dependent_unique_choice
|
adamc@230
|
734 : forall (A : Type) (B : A -> Type) (R : forall x : A, B x -> Prop),
|
adamc@230
|
735 (forall x : A, exists! y : B x, R x y) ->
|
adam@343
|
736 exists f : forall x : A, B x,
|
adam@343
|
737 forall x : A, R x (f x)
|
adamc@230
|
738 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
739
|
adamc@230
|
740 This axiom lets us convert a relational specification [R] into a function implementing that specification. We need only prove that [R] is truly a function. An alternate, stronger formulation applies to cases where [R] maps each input to one or more outputs. We also simplify the statement of the theorem by considering only non-dependent function types. *)
|
adamc@230
|
741
|
adamc@230
|
742 Require Import ClassicalChoice.
|
adamc@230
|
743 Check choice.
|
adamc@230
|
744 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
745 choice
|
adamc@230
|
746 : forall (A B : Type) (R : A -> B -> Prop),
|
adamc@230
|
747 (forall x : A, exists y : B, R x y) ->
|
adamc@230
|
748 exists f : A -> B, forall x : A, R x (f x)
|
adamc@230
|
749
|
adamc@230
|
750 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
751
|
adamc@230
|
752 This principle is proved as a theorem, based on the unique choice axiom and an additional axiom of relational choice from the [RelationalChoice] module.
|
adamc@230
|
753
|
adamc@230
|
754 In set theory, the axiom of choice is a fundamental philosophical commitment one makes about the universe of sets. In Coq, the choice axioms say something weaker. For instance, consider the simple restatement of the [choice] axiom where we replace existential quantification by its Curry-Howard analogue, subset types. *)
|
adamc@230
|
755
|
adamc@230
|
756 Definition choice_Set (A B : Type) (R : A -> B -> Prop) (H : forall x : A, {y : B | R x y})
|
adamc@230
|
757 : {f : A -> B | forall x : A, R x (f x)} :=
|
adamc@230
|
758 exist (fun f => forall x : A, R x (f x))
|
adamc@230
|
759 (fun x => proj1_sig (H x)) (fun x => proj2_sig (H x)).
|
adamc@230
|
760
|
adam@287
|
761 (** Via the Curry-Howard correspondence, this %``%#"#axiom#"#%''% can be taken to have the same meaning as the original. It is implemented trivially as a transformation not much deeper than uncurrying. Thus, we see that the utility of the axioms that we mentioned earlier comes in their usage to build programs from proofs. Normal set theory has no explicit proofs, so the meaning of the usual axiom of choice is subtlely different. In Gallina, the axioms implement a controlled relaxation of the restrictions on information flow from proofs to programs.
|
adamc@230
|
762
|
adam@287
|
763 However, when we combine an axiom of choice with the law of the excluded middle, the idea of %``%#"#choice#"#%''% becomes more interesting. Excluded middle gives us a highly non-computational way of constructing proofs, but it does not change the computational nature of programs. Thus, the axiom of choice is still giving us a way of translating between two different sorts of %``%#"#programs,#"#%''% but the input programs (which are proofs) may be written in a rich language that goes beyond normal computability. This truly is more than repackaging a function with a different type.
|
adamc@230
|
764
|
adamc@230
|
765 %\bigskip%
|
adamc@230
|
766
|
adam@343
|
767 The Coq tools support a command-line flag %\index{impredicative Set}\texttt{%#<tt>#-impredicative-set#</tt>#%}%, which modifies Gallina in a more fundamental way by making [Set] impredicative. A term like [forall T : Set, T] has type [Set], and inductive definitions in [Set] may have constructors that quantify over arguments of any types. To maintain consistency, an elimination restriction must be imposed, similarly to the restriction for [Prop]. The restriction only applies to large inductive types, where some constructor quantifies over a type of type [Type]. In such cases, a value in this inductive type may only be pattern-matched over to yield a result type whose type is [Set] or [Prop]. This contrasts with [Prop], where the restriction applies even to non-large inductive types, and where the result type may only have type [Prop].
|
adamc@230
|
768
|
adamc@230
|
769 In old versions of Coq, [Set] was impredicative by default. Later versions make [Set] predicative to avoid inconsistency with some classical axioms. In particular, one should watch out when using impredicative [Set] with axioms of choice. In combination with excluded middle or predicate extensionality, this can lead to inconsistency. Impredicative [Set] can be useful for modeling inherently impredicative mathematical concepts, but almost all Coq developments get by fine without it. *)
|
adamc@230
|
770
|
adamc@230
|
771 (** ** Axioms and Computation *)
|
adamc@230
|
772
|
adamc@230
|
773 (** One additional axiom-related wrinkle arises from an aspect of Gallina that is very different from set theory: a notion of %\textit{%#<i>#computational equivalence#</i>#%}% is central to the definition of the formal system. Axioms tend not to play well with computation. Consider this example. We start by implementing a function that uses a type equality proof to perform a safe type-cast. *)
|
adamc@230
|
774
|
adamc@230
|
775 Definition cast (x y : Set) (pf : x = y) (v : x) : y :=
|
adamc@230
|
776 match pf with
|
adamc@230
|
777 | refl_equal => v
|
adamc@230
|
778 end.
|
adamc@230
|
779
|
adamc@230
|
780 (** Computation over programs that use [cast] can proceed smoothly. *)
|
adamc@230
|
781
|
adamc@230
|
782 Eval compute in (cast (refl_equal (nat -> nat)) (fun n => S n)) 12.
|
adam@343
|
783 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adamc@230
|
784 = 13
|
adamc@230
|
785 : nat
|
adam@302
|
786 ]]
|
adam@302
|
787 *)
|
adamc@230
|
788
|
adamc@230
|
789 (** Things do not go as smoothly when we use [cast] with proofs that rely on axioms. *)
|
adamc@230
|
790
|
adamc@230
|
791 Theorem t3 : (forall n : nat, fin (S n)) = (forall n : nat, fin (n + 1)).
|
adamc@230
|
792 change ((forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (S n)) n) = (forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (n + 1)) n));
|
adamc@230
|
793 rewrite (functional_extensionality (fun n => fin (n + 1)) (fun n => fin (S n))); crush.
|
adamc@230
|
794 Qed.
|
adamc@230
|
795
|
adamc@230
|
796 Eval compute in (cast t3 (fun _ => First)) 12.
|
adamc@230
|
797 (** [[
|
adamc@230
|
798 = match t3 in (_ = P) return P with
|
adamc@230
|
799 | refl_equal => fun n : nat => First
|
adamc@230
|
800 end 12
|
adamc@230
|
801 : fin (12 + 1)
|
adamc@230
|
802 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
803
|
adamc@230
|
804 Computation gets stuck in a pattern-match on the proof [t3]. The structure of [t3] is not known, so the match cannot proceed. It turns out a more basic problem leads to this particular situation. We ended the proof of [t3] with [Qed], so the definition of [t3] is not available to computation. That is easily fixed. *)
|
adamc@230
|
805
|
adamc@230
|
806 Reset t3.
|
adamc@230
|
807
|
adamc@230
|
808 Theorem t3 : (forall n : nat, fin (S n)) = (forall n : nat, fin (n + 1)).
|
adamc@230
|
809 change ((forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (S n)) n) = (forall n : nat, (fun n => fin (n + 1)) n));
|
adamc@230
|
810 rewrite (functional_extensionality (fun n => fin (n + 1)) (fun n => fin (S n))); crush.
|
adamc@230
|
811 Defined.
|
adamc@230
|
812
|
adamc@230
|
813 Eval compute in (cast t3 (fun _ => First)) 12.
|
adamc@230
|
814 (** [[
|
adamc@230
|
815 = match
|
adamc@230
|
816 match
|
adamc@230
|
817 match
|
adamc@230
|
818 functional_extensionality
|
adamc@230
|
819 ....
|
adamc@230
|
820 ]]
|
adamc@230
|
821
|
adamc@230
|
822 We elide most of the details. A very unwieldy tree of nested matches on equality proofs appears. This time evaluation really %\textit{%#<i>#is#</i>#%}% stuck on a use of an axiom.
|
adamc@230
|
823
|
adamc@230
|
824 If we are careful in using tactics to prove an equality, we can still compute with casts over the proof. *)
|
adamc@230
|
825
|
adamc@230
|
826 Lemma plus1 : forall n, S n = n + 1.
|
adamc@230
|
827 induction n; simpl; intuition.
|
adamc@230
|
828 Defined.
|
adamc@230
|
829
|
adamc@230
|
830 Theorem t4 : forall n, fin (S n) = fin (n + 1).
|
adamc@230
|
831 intro; f_equal; apply plus1.
|
adamc@230
|
832 Defined.
|
adamc@230
|
833
|
adamc@230
|
834 Eval compute in cast (t4 13) First.
|
adamc@230
|
835 (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
|
adamc@230
|
836 = First
|
adamc@230
|
837 : fin (13 + 1)
|
adam@302
|
838 ]]
|
adam@343
|
839
|
adam@343
|
840 This simple computational reduction hides the use of a recursive function to produce a suitable [refl_equal] proof term. The recursion originates in our use of [induction] in [t4]'s proof. *)
|
adam@343
|
841
|
adam@344
|
842
|
adam@344
|
843 (** ** Methods for Avoiding Axioms *)
|
adam@344
|
844
|
adam@344
|
845 (** The last section demonstrated one reason to avoid axioms: they interfere with computational behavior of terms. A further reason is to reduce the philosophical commitment of a theorem. The more axioms one assumes, the harder it becomes to convince oneself that the formal system corresponds appropriately to one's intuitions. A refinement of this last point, in applications like %\index{proof-carrying code}%proof-carrying code%~\cite{PCC}% in computer security, has to do with minimizing the size of a %\index{trusted code base}\emph{%#<i>#trusted code base#</i>#%}%. To convince ourselves that a theorem is true, we must convince ourselves of the correctness of the program that checks the theorem. Axioms effectively become new source code for the checking program, increasing the effort required to perform a correctness audit.
|
adam@344
|
846
|
adam@344
|
847 An earlier section gave one example of avoiding an axiom. We proved that [pred_strong1] is agnostic to details of the proofs passed to it as arguments, by unfolding the definition of the function. A %``%#"#simpler#"#%''% proof keeps the function definition opaque and instead applies a proof irrelevance axiom. By accepting a more complex proof, we reduce our philosophical commitment and trusted base. (By the way, the less-than relation that the proofs in question here prove turns out to admit proof irrelevance as a theorem provable within normal Gallina!)
|
adam@344
|
848
|
adam@344
|
849 One dark secret of the [dep_destruct] tactic that we have used several times is reliance on an axiom. Consider this simple case analysis principle for [fin] values: *)
|
adam@344
|
850
|
adam@344
|
851 Theorem fin_cases : forall n (f : fin (S n)), f = First \/ exists f', f = Next f'.
|
adam@344
|
852 intros; dep_destruct f; eauto.
|
adam@344
|
853 Qed.
|
adam@344
|
854
|
adam@344
|
855 Print Assumptions fin_cases.
|
adam@344
|
856 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@344
|
857 Axioms:
|
adam@344
|
858 JMeq.JMeq_eq : forall (A : Type) (x y : A), JMeq.JMeq x y -> x = y
|
adam@344
|
859 ]]
|
adam@344
|
860
|
adam@344
|
861 The proof depends on the [JMeq_eq] axiom that we met in the chapter on equality proofs. However, a smarter tactic could have avoided an axiom dependence. Here is an alternate proof via a slightly strange looking lemma. *)
|
adam@344
|
862
|
adam@344
|
863 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@344
|
864 Lemma fin_cases_again' : forall n (f : fin n),
|
adam@344
|
865 match n return fin n -> Prop with
|
adam@344
|
866 | O => fun _ => False
|
adam@344
|
867 | S n' => fun f => f = First \/ exists f', f = Next f'
|
adam@344
|
868 end f.
|
adam@344
|
869 destruct f; eauto.
|
adam@344
|
870 Qed.
|
adam@344
|
871
|
adam@344
|
872 (** We apply a variant of the %\index{convoy pattern}%convoy pattern, which we are used to seeing in function implementations. Here, the pattern helps us state a lemma in a form where the argument to [fin] is a variable. Recall that, thanks to basic typing rules for pattern-matching, [destruct] will only work effectively on types whose non-parameter arguments are variables. The %\index{tactics!exact}%[exact] tactic, which takes as argument a literal proof term, now gives us an easy way of proving the original theorem. *)
|
adam@344
|
873
|
adam@344
|
874 Theorem fin_cases_again : forall n (f : fin (S n)), f = First \/ exists f', f = Next f'.
|
adam@344
|
875 intros; exact (fin_cases_again' f).
|
adam@344
|
876 Qed.
|
adam@344
|
877 (* end thide *)
|
adam@344
|
878
|
adam@344
|
879 Print Assumptions fin_cases_again.
|
adam@344
|
880 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%
|
adam@344
|
881 <<
|
adam@344
|
882 Closed under the global context
|
adam@344
|
883 >>
|
adam@344
|
884
|
adam@345
|
885 *)
|
adam@345
|
886
|
adam@345
|
887 (* begin thide *)
|
adam@345
|
888 (** As the Curry-Howard correspondence might lead us to expect, the same pattern may be applied in programming as in proving. Axioms are relevant in programming, too, because, while Coq includes useful extensions like [Program] that make dependently typed programming more straightforward, in general these extensions generate code that relies on axioms about equality. We can use clever pattern matching to write our code axiom-free.
|
adam@345
|
889
|
adam@345
|
890 As an example, consider a [Set] version of [fin_cases]. We use [Set] types instead of [Prop] types, so that return values have computational content and may be used to guide the behavior of algorithms. Beside that, we are essentially writing the same %``%#"#proof#"#%''% in a more explicit way. *)
|
adam@345
|
891
|
adam@345
|
892 Definition finOut n (f : fin n) : match n return fin n -> Type with
|
adam@345
|
893 | O => fun _ => Empty_set
|
adam@345
|
894 | _ => fun f => {f' : _ | f = Next f'} + {f = First}
|
adam@345
|
895 end f :=
|
adam@345
|
896 match f with
|
adam@345
|
897 | First _ => inright _ (refl_equal _)
|
adam@345
|
898 | Next _ f' => inleft _ (exist _ f' (refl_equal _))
|
adam@345
|
899 end.
|
adam@345
|
900 (* end thide *)
|
adam@345
|
901
|
adam@345
|
902 (** As another example, consider the following type of formulas in first-order logic. The intent of the type definition will not be important in what follows, but we give a quick intuition for the curious reader. Our formulas may include [forall] quantification over arbitrary [Type]s, and we index formulas by environments telling which variables are in scope and what their types are; such an environment is a [list Type]. A constructor [Inject] lets us include any Coq [Prop] as a formula, and [VarEq] and [Lift] can be used for variable references, in what is essentially the de Bruijn index convention. (Again, the detail in this paragraph is not important to understand the discussion that follows!) *)
|
adam@344
|
903
|
adam@344
|
904 Inductive formula : list Type -> Type :=
|
adam@344
|
905 | Inject : forall Ts, Prop -> formula Ts
|
adam@344
|
906 | VarEq : forall T Ts, T -> formula (T :: Ts)
|
adam@344
|
907 | Lift : forall T Ts, formula Ts -> formula (T :: Ts)
|
adam@344
|
908 | Forall : forall T Ts, formula (T :: Ts) -> formula Ts
|
adam@344
|
909 | And : forall Ts, formula Ts -> formula Ts -> formula Ts.
|
adam@344
|
910
|
adam@344
|
911 (** This example is based on my own experiences implementing variants of a program logic called XCAP%~\cite{XCAP}%, which also includes an inductive predicate for characterizing which formulas are provable. Here I include a pared-down version of such a predicate, with only two constructors, which is sufficient to illustrate certain tricky issues. *)
|
adam@344
|
912
|
adam@344
|
913 Inductive proof : formula nil -> Prop :=
|
adam@344
|
914 | PInject : forall (P : Prop), P -> proof (Inject nil P)
|
adam@344
|
915 | PAnd : forall p q, proof p -> proof q -> proof (And p q).
|
adam@344
|
916
|
adam@344
|
917 (** Let us prove a lemma showing that a %``%#"#[P /\ Q -> P]#"#%''% rule is derivable within the rules of [proof]. *)
|
adam@344
|
918
|
adam@344
|
919 Theorem proj1 : forall p q, proof (And p q) -> proof p.
|
adam@344
|
920 destruct 1.
|
adam@344
|
921 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@344
|
922 p : formula nil
|
adam@344
|
923 q : formula nil
|
adam@344
|
924 P : Prop
|
adam@344
|
925 H : P
|
adam@344
|
926 ============================
|
adam@344
|
927 proof p
|
adam@344
|
928 ]]
|
adam@344
|
929 *)
|
adam@344
|
930
|
adam@344
|
931 (** We are reminded that [induction] and [destruct] do not work effectively on types with non-variable arguments. The first subgoal, shown above, is clearly unprovable. (Consider the case where [p = Inject nil False].)
|
adam@344
|
932
|
adam@344
|
933 An application of the %\index{tactics!dependent destruction}%[dependent destruction] tactic (the basis for [dep_destruct]) solves the problem handily. We use a shorthand with the %\index{tactics!intros}%[intros] tactic that lets us use question marks for variable names that do not matter. *)
|
adam@344
|
934
|
adam@344
|
935 Restart.
|
adam@344
|
936 Require Import Program.
|
adam@344
|
937 intros ? ? H; dependent destruction H; auto.
|
adam@344
|
938 Qed.
|
adam@344
|
939
|
adam@344
|
940 Print Assumptions proj1.
|
adam@344
|
941 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@344
|
942 Axioms:
|
adam@344
|
943 eq_rect_eq : forall (U : Type) (p : U) (Q : U -> Type) (x : Q p) (h : p = p),
|
adam@344
|
944 x = eq_rect p Q x p h
|
adam@344
|
945 ]]
|
adam@344
|
946
|
adam@344
|
947 Unfortunately, that built-in tactic appeals to an axiom. It is still possible to avoid axioms by giving the proof via another odd-looking lemma. Here is a first attempt that fails at remaining axiom-free, using a common equality-based trick for supporting induction on non-variable arguments to type families. The trick works fine without axioms for datatypes more traditional than [formula], but we run into trouble with our current type. *)
|
adam@344
|
948
|
adam@344
|
949 Lemma proj1_again' : forall r, proof r
|
adam@344
|
950 -> forall p q, r = And p q -> proof p.
|
adam@344
|
951 destruct 1; crush.
|
adam@344
|
952 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@344
|
953 H0 : Inject [] P = And p q
|
adam@344
|
954 ============================
|
adam@344
|
955 proof p
|
adam@344
|
956 ]]
|
adam@344
|
957
|
adam@344
|
958 The first goal looks reasonable. Hypothesis [H0] is clearly contradictory, as [discriminate] can show. *)
|
adam@344
|
959
|
adam@344
|
960 discriminate.
|
adam@344
|
961 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@344
|
962 H : proof p
|
adam@344
|
963 H1 : And p q = And p0 q0
|
adam@344
|
964 ============================
|
adam@344
|
965 proof p0
|
adam@344
|
966 ]]
|
adam@344
|
967
|
adam@344
|
968 It looks like we are almost done. Hypothesis [H1] gives [p = p0] by injectivity of constructors, and then [H] finishes the case. *)
|
adam@344
|
969
|
adam@344
|
970 injection H1; intros.
|
adam@344
|
971
|
adam@344
|
972 (** Unfortunately, the %``%#"#equality#"#%''% that we expected between [p] and [p0] comes in a strange form:
|
adam@344
|
973
|
adam@344
|
974 [[
|
adam@344
|
975 H3 : existT (fun Ts : list Type => formula Ts) []%list p =
|
adam@344
|
976 existT (fun Ts : list Type => formula Ts) []%list p0
|
adam@344
|
977 ============================
|
adam@344
|
978 proof p0
|
adam@344
|
979 ]]
|
adam@344
|
980
|
adam@345
|
981 It may take a bit of tinkering, but, reviewing Chapter 3's discussion of writing injection principles manually, it makes sense that an [existT] type is the most direct way to express the output of [injection] on a dependently typed constructor. The constructor [And] is dependently typed, since it takes a parameter [Ts] upon which the types of [p] and [q] depend. Let us not dwell further here on why this goal appears; the reader may like to attempt the (impossible) exercise of building a better injection lemma for [And], without using axioms.
|
adam@344
|
982
|
adam@344
|
983 How exactly does an axiom come into the picture here? Let us ask [crush] to finish the proof. *)
|
adam@344
|
984
|
adam@344
|
985 crush.
|
adam@344
|
986 Qed.
|
adam@344
|
987
|
adam@344
|
988 Print Assumptions proj1_again'.
|
adam@344
|
989 (** %\vspace{-.15in}%[[
|
adam@344
|
990 Axioms:
|
adam@344
|
991 eq_rect_eq : forall (U : Type) (p : U) (Q : U -> Type) (x : Q p) (h : p = p),
|
adam@344
|
992 x = eq_rect p Q x p h
|
adam@344
|
993 ]]
|
adam@344
|
994
|
adam@344
|
995 It turns out that this familiar axiom about equality (or some other axiom) is required to deduce [p = p0] from the hypothesis [H3] above. The soundness of that proof step is neither provable nor disprovable in Gallina.
|
adam@344
|
996
|
adam@344
|
997 Hope is not lost, however. We can produce an even stranger looking lemma, which gives us the theorem without axioms. *)
|
adam@344
|
998
|
adam@344
|
999 Lemma proj1_again'' : forall r, proof r
|
adam@344
|
1000 -> match r with
|
adam@344
|
1001 | And Ps p _ => match Ps return formula Ps -> Prop with
|
adam@344
|
1002 | nil => fun p => proof p
|
adam@344
|
1003 | _ => fun _ => True
|
adam@344
|
1004 end p
|
adam@344
|
1005 | _ => True
|
adam@344
|
1006 end.
|
adam@344
|
1007 destruct 1; auto.
|
adam@344
|
1008 Qed.
|
adam@344
|
1009
|
adam@344
|
1010 Theorem proj1_again : forall p q, proof (And p q) -> proof p.
|
adam@344
|
1011 intros ? ? H; exact (proj1_again'' H).
|
adam@344
|
1012 Qed.
|
adam@344
|
1013
|
adam@344
|
1014 Print Assumptions proj1_again.
|
adam@344
|
1015 (** <<
|
adam@344
|
1016 Closed under the global context
|
adam@344
|
1017 >>
|
adam@344
|
1018
|
adam@344
|
1019 This example illustrates again how some of the same design patterns we learned for dependently typed programming can be used fruitfully in theorem statements. *)
|