view src/Equality.v @ 294:1b6c81e51799

Fixes added while proofreading JFR camera-ready
author Adam Chlipala <adam@chlipala.net>
date Thu, 09 Dec 2010 13:44:57 -0500
parents 2c88fc1dbe33
children 559ec7328410
line wrap: on
line source
(* Copyright (c) 2008-2010, Adam Chlipala
 * 
 * This work is licensed under a
 * Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0
 * Unported License.
 * The license text is available at:
 *   http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
 *)

(* begin hide *)
Require Import Eqdep JMeq List.

Require Import Tactics.

Set Implicit Arguments.
(* end hide *)


(** %\chapter{Reasoning About Equality Proofs}% *)

(** In traditional mathematics, the concept of equality is usually taken as a given.  On the other hand, in type theory, equality is a very contentious subject.  There are at least three different notions of equality that are important, and researchers are actively investigating new definitions of what it means for two terms to be equal.  Even once we fix a notion of equality, there are inevitably tricky issues that arise in proving properties of programs that manipulate equality proofs explicitly.  In this chapter, I will focus on design patterns for circumventing these tricky issues, and I will introduce the different notions of equality as they are germane. *)


(** * The Definitional Equality *)

(** We have seen many examples so far where proof goals follow %``%#"#by computation.#"#%''%  That is, we apply computational reduction rules to reduce the goal to a normal form, at which point it follows trivially.  Exactly when this works and when it does not depends on the details of Coq's %\textit{%#<i>#definitional equality#</i>#%}%.  This is an untyped binary relation appearing in the formal metatheory of CIC.  CIC contains a typing rule allowing the conclusion $E : T$ from the premise $E : T'$ and a proof that $T$ and $T'$ are definitionally equal.

   The [cbv] tactic will help us illustrate the rules of Coq's definitional equality.  We redefine the natural number predecessor function in a somewhat convoluted way and construct a manual proof that it returns [0] when applied to [1]. *)

Definition pred' (x : nat) :=
  match x with
    | O => O
    | S n' => let y := n' in y
  end.

Theorem reduce_me : pred' 1 = 0.

(* begin thide *)
  (** CIC follows the traditions of lambda calculus in associating reduction rules with Greek letters.  Coq can certainly be said to support the familiar alpha reduction rule, which allows capture-avoiding renaming of bound variables, but we never need to apply alpha explicitly, since Coq uses a de Bruijn representation that encodes terms canonically.

     The delta rule is for unfolding global definitions.  We can use it here to unfold the definition of [pred'].  We do this with the [cbv] tactic, which takes a list of reduction rules and makes as many call-by-value reduction steps as possible, using only those rules.  There is an analogous tactic [lazy] for call-by-need reduction. *)

  cbv delta.
  (** [[
  ============================
   (fun x : nat => match x with
                   | 0 => 0
                   | S n' => let y := n' in y
                   end) 1 = 0
 
      ]]

      At this point, we want to apply the famous beta reduction of lambda calculus, to simplify the application of a known function abstraction. *)

  cbv beta.
  (** [[
  ============================
   match 1 with
   | 0 => 0
   | S n' => let y := n' in y
   end = 0
 
   ]]

   Next on the list is the iota reduction, which simplifies a single [match] term by determining which pattern matches. *)

  cbv iota.
  (** [[
  ============================
   (fun n' : nat => let y := n' in y) 0 = 0
 
      ]]

   Now we need another beta reduction. *)

  cbv beta.
  (** [[
  ============================
   (let y := 0 in y) = 0
 
      ]]
   
      The final reduction rule is zeta, which replaces a [let] expression by its body with the appropriate term subsituted. *)

  cbv zeta.
  (** [[
  ============================
   0 = 0
 
   ]] *)

  reflexivity.
Qed.
(* end thide *)

(** The standard [eq] relation is critically dependent on the definitional equality.  [eq] is often called a %\textit{%#<i>#propositional equality#</i>#%}%, because it reifies definitional equality as a proposition that may or may not hold.  Standard axiomatizations of an equality predicate in first-order logic define equality in terms of properties it has, like reflexivity, symmetry, and transitivity.  In contrast, for [eq] in Coq, those properties are implicit in the properties of the definitional equality, which are built into CIC's metatheory and the implementation of Gallina.  We could add new rules to the definitional equality, and [eq] would keep its definition and methods of use.

   This all may make it sound like the choice of [eq]'s definition is unimportant.  To the contrary, in this chapter, we will see examples where alternate definitions may simplify proofs.  Before that point, I will introduce proof methods for goals that use proofs of the standard propositional equality %``%#"#as data.#"#%''% *)


(** * Heterogeneous Lists Revisited *)

(** One of our example dependent data structures from the last chapter was heterogeneous lists and their associated %``%#"#cursor#"#%''% type.  The recursive version poses some special challenges related to equality proofs, since it uses such proofs in its definition of [member] types. *)

Section fhlist.
  Variable A : Type.
  Variable B : A -> Type.

  Fixpoint fhlist (ls : list A) : Type :=
    match ls with
      | nil => unit
      | x :: ls' => B x * fhlist ls'
    end%type.

  Variable elm : A.

  Fixpoint fmember (ls : list A) : Type :=
    match ls with
      | nil => Empty_set
      | x :: ls' => (x = elm) + fmember ls'
    end%type.

  Fixpoint fhget (ls : list A) : fhlist ls -> fmember ls -> B elm :=
    match ls return fhlist ls -> fmember ls -> B elm with
      | nil => fun _ idx => match idx with end
      | _ :: ls' => fun mls idx =>
        match idx with
          | inl pf => match pf with
                        | refl_equal => fst mls
                      end
          | inr idx' => fhget ls' (snd mls) idx'
        end
    end.
End fhlist.

Implicit Arguments fhget [A B elm ls].

(** We can define a [map]-like function for [fhlist]s. *)

Section fhlist_map.
  Variables A : Type.
  Variables B C : A -> Type.
  Variable f : forall x, B x -> C x.

  Fixpoint fhmap (ls : list A) : fhlist B ls -> fhlist C ls :=
    match ls return fhlist B ls -> fhlist C ls with
      | nil => fun _ => tt
      | _ :: _ => fun hls => (f (fst hls), fhmap _ (snd hls))
    end.

  Implicit Arguments fhmap [ls].

  (** For the inductive versions of the [ilist] definitions, we proved a lemma about the interaction of [get] and [imap].  It was a strategic choice not to attempt such a proof for the definitions that we just gave, because that sets us on a collision course with the problems that are the subject of this chapter. *)

  Variable elm : A.

  Theorem get_imap : forall ls (mem : fmember elm ls) (hls : fhlist B ls),
    fhget (fhmap hls) mem = f (fhget hls mem).
(* begin thide *)
    induction ls; crush.

    (** Part of our single remaining subgoal is:

       [[
  a0 : a = elm
  ============================
   match a0 in (_ = a2) return (C a2) with
   | refl_equal => f a1
   end = f match a0 in (_ = a2) return (B a2) with
           | refl_equal => a1
           end
 
       ]]

   This seems like a trivial enough obligation.  The equality proof [a0] must be [refl_equal], since that is the only constructor of [eq].  Therefore, both the [match]es reduce to the point where the conclusion follows by reflexivity.

    [[
    destruct a0.

User error: Cannot solve a second-order unification problem
 
]]

    This is one of Coq's standard error messages for informing us that its heuristics for attempting an instance of an undecidable problem about dependent typing have failed.  We might try to nudge things in the right direction by stating the lemma that we believe makes the conclusion trivial.

    [[
    assert (a0 = refl_equal _).

The term "refl_equal ?98" has type "?98 = ?98"
 while it is expected to have type "a = elm"
 
    ]]

    In retrospect, the problem is not so hard to see.  Reflexivity proofs only show [x = x] for particular values of [x], whereas here we are thinking in terms of a proof of [a = elm], where the two sides of the equality are not equal syntactically.  Thus, the essential lemma we need does not even type-check!

    Is it time to throw in the towel?  Luckily, the answer is %``%#"#no.#"#%''%  In this chapter, we will see several useful patterns for proving obligations like this.

    For this particular example, the solution is surprisingly straightforward.  [destruct] has a simpler sibling [case] which should behave identically for any inductive type with one constructor of no arguments. *)

    case a0.
    (** [[
  ============================
   f a1 = f a1
 
   ]]

    It seems that [destruct] was trying to be too smart for its own good. *)

    reflexivity.
  Qed.
(* end thide *)

  (** It will be helpful to examine the proof terms generated by this sort of strategy.  A simpler example illustrates what is going on. *)

  Lemma lemma1 : forall x (pf : x = elm), O = match pf with refl_equal => O end.
(* begin thide *)
    simple destruct pf; reflexivity.
  Qed.
(* end thide *)

  (** [simple destruct pf] is a convenient form for applying [case].  It runs [intro] to bring into scope all quantified variables up to its argument. *)

  Print lemma1.
  (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
lemma1 = 
fun (x : A) (pf : x = elm) =>
match pf as e in (_ = y) return (0 = match e with
                                     | refl_equal => 0
                                     end) with
| refl_equal => refl_equal 0
end
     : forall (x : A) (pf : x = elm), 0 = match pf with
                                          | refl_equal => 0
                                          end
 
    ]]

    Using what we know about shorthands for [match] annotations, we can write this proof in shorter form manually. *)

(* begin thide *)
  Definition lemma1' :=
    fun (x : A) (pf : x = elm) =>
      match pf return (0 = match pf with
                             | refl_equal => 0
                           end) with
        | refl_equal => refl_equal 0
      end.
(* end thide *)

  (** Surprisingly, what seems at first like a %\textit{%#<i>#simpler#</i>#%}% lemma is harder to prove. *)

  Lemma lemma2 : forall (x : A) (pf : x = x), O = match pf with refl_equal => O end.
(* begin thide *)
    (** [[
    simple destruct pf.

User error: Cannot solve a second-order unification problem
 
      ]] *)
  Abort.

  (** Nonetheless, we can adapt the last manual proof to handle this theorem. *)

(* begin thide *)
  Definition lemma2 :=
    fun (x : A) (pf : x = x) =>
      match pf return (0 = match pf with
                             | refl_equal => 0
                           end) with
        | refl_equal => refl_equal 0
      end.
(* end thide *)

  (** We can try to prove a lemma that would simplify proofs of many facts like [lemma2]: *)

  Lemma lemma3 : forall (x : A) (pf : x = x), pf = refl_equal x.
(* begin thide *)
    (** [[
    simple destruct pf.

User error: Cannot solve a second-order unification problem
      ]] *)

  Abort.

  (** This time, even our manual attempt fails.

     [[
  Definition lemma3' :=
    fun (x : A) (pf : x = x) =>
      match pf as pf' in (_ = x') return (pf' = refl_equal x') with
        | refl_equal => refl_equal _
      end.

The term "refl_equal x'" has type "x' = x'" while it is expected to have type
 "x = x'"
 
     ]]

     The type error comes from our [return] annotation.  In that annotation, the [as]-bound variable [pf'] has type [x = x'], refering to the [in]-bound variable [x'].  To do a dependent [match], we %\textit{%#<i>#must#</i>#%}% choose a fresh name for the second argument of [eq].  We are just as constrained to use the %``%#"#real#"#%''% value [x] for the first argument.  Thus, within the [return] clause, the proof we are matching on %\textit{%#<i>#must#</i>#%}% equate two non-matching terms, which makes it impossible to equate that proof with reflexivity.

     Nonetheless, it turns out that, with one catch, we %\textit{%#<i>#can#</i>#%}% prove this lemma. *)

  Lemma lemma3 : forall (x : A) (pf : x = x), pf = refl_equal x.
    intros; apply UIP_refl.
  Qed.

  Check UIP_refl.
  (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
UIP_refl
     : forall (U : Type) (x : U) (p : x = x), p = refl_equal x
 
     ]]

     [UIP_refl] comes from the [Eqdep] module of the standard library.  Do the Coq authors know of some clever trick for building such proofs that we have not seen yet?  If they do, they did not use it for this proof.  Rather, the proof is based on an %\textit{%#<i>#axiom#</i>#%}%. *)

  Print eq_rect_eq.
  (** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
eq_rect_eq = 
fun U : Type => Eq_rect_eq.eq_rect_eq U
     : forall (U : Type) (p : U) (Q : U -> Type) (x : Q p) (h : p = p),
       x = eq_rect p Q x p h
 
      ]]

      [eq_rect_eq] states a %``%#"#fact#"#%''% that seems like common sense, once the notation is deciphered.  [eq_rect] is the automatically-generated recursion principle for [eq].  Calling [eq_rect] is another way of [match]ing on an equality proof.  The proof we match on is the argument [h], and [x] is the body of the [match].  [eq_rect_eq] just says that [match]es on proofs of [p = p], for any [p], are superfluous and may be removed.

      Perhaps surprisingly, we cannot prove [eq_rect_eq] from within Coq.  This proposition is introduced as an axiom; that is, a proposition asserted as true without proof.  We cannot assert just any statement without proof.  Adding [False] as an axiom would allow us to prove any proposition, for instance, defeating the point of using a proof assistant.  In general, we need to be sure that we never assert %\textit{%#<i>#inconsistent#</i>#%}% sets of axioms.  A set of axioms is inconsistent if its conjunction implies [False].  For the case of [eq_rect_eq], consistency has been verified outside of Coq via %``%#"#informal#"#%''% metatheory.

      This axiom is equivalent to another that is more commonly known and mentioned in type theory circles. *)

  Print Streicher_K.
(* end thide *)
(** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
Streicher_K = 
fun U : Type => UIP_refl__Streicher_K U (UIP_refl U)
     : forall (U : Type) (x : U) (P : x = x -> Prop),
       P (refl_equal x) -> forall p : x = x, P p
 
  ]]

  This is the unfortunately-named %``%#"#Streicher's axiom K,#"#%''% which says that a predicate on properly-typed equality proofs holds of all such proofs if it holds of reflexivity. *)

End fhlist_map.


(** * Type-Casts in Theorem Statements *)

(** Sometimes we need to use tricks with equality just to state the theorems that we care about.  To illustrate, we start by defining a concatenation function for [fhlist]s. *)

Section fhapp.
  Variable A : Type.
  Variable B : A -> Type.

  Fixpoint fhapp (ls1 ls2 : list A)
    : fhlist B ls1 -> fhlist B ls2 -> fhlist B (ls1 ++ ls2) :=
    match ls1 with
      | nil => fun _ hls2 => hls2
      | _ :: _ => fun hls1 hls2 => (fst hls1, fhapp _ _ (snd hls1) hls2)
    end.

  Implicit Arguments fhapp [ls1 ls2].

  (* EX: Prove that fhapp is associative. *)
(* begin thide *)

  (** We might like to prove that [fhapp] is associative.

     [[
  Theorem fhapp_ass : forall ls1 ls2 ls3
    (hls1 : fhlist B ls1) (hls2 : fhlist B ls2) (hls3 : fhlist B ls3),
    fhapp hls1 (fhapp hls2 hls3) = fhapp (fhapp hls1 hls2) hls3.

The term
 "fhapp (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3) (fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) hls1 hls2)
    hls3" has type "fhlist B ((ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3)"
 while it is expected to have type "fhlist B (ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)"
 
     ]]

     This first cut at the theorem statement does not even type-check.  We know that the two [fhlist] types appearing in the error message are always equal, by associativity of normal list append, but this fact is not apparent to the type checker.  This stems from the fact that Coq's equality is %\textit{%#<i>#intensional#</i>#%}%, in the sense that type equality theorems can never be applied after the fact to get a term to type-check.  Instead, we need to make use of equality explicitly in the theorem statement. *)

  Theorem fhapp_ass : forall ls1 ls2 ls3
    (pf : (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = ls1 ++ (ls2 ++ ls3))
    (hls1 : fhlist B ls1) (hls2 : fhlist B ls2) (hls3 : fhlist B ls3),
    fhapp hls1 (fhapp hls2 hls3)
    = match pf in (_ = ls) return fhlist _ ls with
        | refl_equal => fhapp (fhapp hls1 hls2) hls3
      end.
    induction ls1; crush.

    (** The first remaining subgoal looks trivial enough:

       [[
  ============================
   fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3 =
   match pf in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
   | refl_equal => fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3
   end
 
       ]]

       We can try what worked in previous examples.

       [[
    case pf.

User error: Cannot solve a second-order unification problem
 
         ]]

        It seems we have reached another case where it is unclear how to use a dependent [match] to implement case analysis on our proof.  The [UIP_refl] theorem can come to our rescue again. *)

    rewrite (UIP_refl _ _ pf).
    (** [[
  ============================
   fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3 =
   fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3
 
        ]] *)

    reflexivity.

    (** Our second subgoal is trickier.

       [[
  pf : a :: (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3
  ============================
   (a0,
   fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2 ++ ls3) b
     (fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3)) =
   match pf in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
   | refl_equal =>
       (a0,
       fhapp (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3)
         (fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) b hls2) hls3)
   end

    rewrite (UIP_refl _ _ pf).

The term "pf" has type "a :: (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3"
 while it is expected to have type "?556 = ?556"
 
       ]]

       We can only apply [UIP_refl] on proofs of equality with syntactically equal operands, which is not the case of [pf] here.  We will need to manipulate the form of this subgoal to get us to a point where we may use [UIP_refl].  A first step is obtaining a proof suitable to use in applying the induction hypothesis.  Inversion on the structure of [pf] is sufficient for that. *)

    injection pf; intro pf'.
    (** [[
  pf : a :: (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3
  pf' : (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3
  ============================
   (a0,
   fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2 ++ ls3) b
     (fhapp (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3)) =
   match pf in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
   | refl_equal =>
       (a0,
       fhapp (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3)
         (fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) b hls2) hls3)
   end
 
   ]]

   Now we can rewrite using the inductive hypothesis. *)

    rewrite (IHls1 _ _ pf').
    (** [[
  ============================
   (a0,
   match pf' in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
   | refl_equal =>
       fhapp (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3)
         (fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) b hls2) hls3
   end) =
   match pf in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
   | refl_equal =>
       (a0,
       fhapp (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3)
         (fhapp (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) b hls2) hls3)
   end
 
        ]]

        We have made an important bit of progress, as now only a single call to [fhapp] appears in the conclusion, repeated twice.  Trying case analysis on our proofs still will not work, but there is a move we can make to enable it.  Not only does just one call to [fhapp] matter to us now, but it also %\textit{%#<i>#does not matter what the result of the call is#</i>#%}%.  In other words, the subgoal should remain true if we replace this [fhapp] call with a fresh variable.  The [generalize] tactic helps us do exactly that. *)

    generalize (fhapp (fhapp b hls2) hls3).
    (** [[
   forall f : fhlist B ((ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3),
   (a0,
   match pf' in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
   | refl_equal => f
   end) =
   match pf in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
   | refl_equal => (a0, f)
   end
 
        ]]

        The conclusion has gotten markedly simpler.  It seems counterintuitive that we can have an easier time of proving a more general theorem, but that is exactly the case here and for many other proofs that use dependent types heavily.  Speaking informally, the reason why this kind of activity helps is that [match] annotations only support variables in certain positions.  By reducing more elements of a goal to variables, built-in tactics can have more success building [match] terms under the hood.

        In this case, it is helpful to generalize over our two proofs as well. *)

    generalize pf pf'.
    (** [[
   forall (pf0 : a :: (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)
     (pf'0 : (ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3 = ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)
     (f : fhlist B ((ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3)),
   (a0,
   match pf'0 in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
   | refl_equal => f
   end) =
   match pf0 in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
   | refl_equal => (a0, f)
   end
 
        ]]

        To an experienced dependent types hacker, the appearance of this goal term calls for a celebration.  The formula has a critical property that indicates that our problems are over.  To get our proofs into the right form to apply [UIP_refl], we need to use associativity of list append to rewrite their types.  We could not do that before because other parts of the goal require the proofs to retain their original types.  In particular, the call to [fhapp] that we generalized must have type [(ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3], for some values of the list variables.  If we rewrite the type of the proof used to type-cast this value to something like [ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3 = ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3], then the lefthand side of the equality would no longer match the type of the term we are trying to cast.

        However, now that we have generalized over the [fhapp] call, the type of the term being type-cast appears explicitly in the goal and %\textit{%#<i>#may be rewritten as well#</i>#%}%.  In particular, the final masterstroke is rewriting everywhere in our goal using associativity of list append. *)

    rewrite app_ass.
    (** [[
  ============================
   forall (pf0 : a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3 = a :: ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)
     (pf'0 : ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3 = ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)
     (f : fhlist B (ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3)),
   (a0,
   match pf'0 in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
   | refl_equal => f
   end) =
   match pf0 in (_ = ls) return (fhlist B ls) with
   | refl_equal => (a0, f)
   end
 
        ]]

        We can see that we have achieved the crucial property: the type of each generalized equality proof has syntactically equal operands.  This makes it easy to finish the proof with [UIP_refl]. *)

    intros.
    rewrite (UIP_refl _ _ pf0).
    rewrite (UIP_refl _ _ pf'0).
    reflexivity.
  Qed.
(* end thide *)
End fhapp.

Implicit Arguments fhapp [A B ls1 ls2].


(** * Heterogeneous Equality *)

(** There is another equality predicate, defined in the [JMeq] module of the standard library, implementing %\textit{%#<i>#heterogeneous equality#</i>#%}%. *)

Print JMeq.
(** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
Inductive JMeq (A : Type) (x : A) : forall B : Type, B -> Prop :=
    JMeq_refl : JMeq x x
 
    ]]

[JMeq] stands for %``%#"#John Major equality,#"#%''% a name coined by Conor McBride as a sort of pun about British politics.  [JMeq] starts out looking a lot like [eq].  The crucial difference is that we may use [JMeq] %\textit{%#<i>#on arguments of different types#</i>#%}%.  For instance, a lemma that we failed to establish before is trivial with [JMeq].  It makes for prettier theorem statements to define some syntactic shorthand first. *)

Infix "==" := JMeq (at level 70, no associativity).

(* EX: Prove UIP_refl' : forall (A : Type) (x : A) (pf : x = x), pf == refl_equal x *)
(* begin thide *)
Definition UIP_refl' (A : Type) (x : A) (pf : x = x) : pf == refl_equal x :=
  match pf return (pf == refl_equal _) with
    | refl_equal => JMeq_refl _
  end.
(* end thide *)

(** There is no quick way to write such a proof by tactics, but the underlying proof term that we want is trivial.

   Suppose that we want to use [UIP_refl'] to establish another lemma of the kind we have run into several times so far. *)

Lemma lemma4 : forall (A : Type) (x : A) (pf : x = x),
  O = match pf with refl_equal => O end.
(* begin thide *)
  intros; rewrite (UIP_refl' pf); reflexivity.
Qed.
(* end thide *)

(** All in all, refreshingly straightforward, but there really is no such thing as a free lunch.  The use of [rewrite] is implemented in terms of an axiom: *)

Check JMeq_eq.
(** %\vspace{-.15in}% [[
JMeq_eq
     : forall (A : Type) (x y : A), x == y -> x = y
 
    ]]

    It may be surprising that we cannot prove that heterogeneous equality implies normal equality.  The difficulties are the same kind we have seen so far, based on limitations of [match] annotations.

   We can redo our [fhapp] associativity proof based around [JMeq]. *)

Section fhapp'.
  Variable A : Type.
  Variable B : A -> Type.

  (** This time, the naive theorem statement type-checks. *)

  (* EX: Prove [fhapp] associativity using [JMeq]. *)

(* begin thide *)
  Theorem fhapp_ass' : forall ls1 ls2 ls3
    (hls1 : fhlist B ls1) (hls2 : fhlist B ls2) (hls3 : fhlist B ls3),
    fhapp hls1 (fhapp hls2 hls3) == fhapp (fhapp hls1 hls2) hls3.
    induction ls1; crush.

    (** Even better, [crush] discharges the first subgoal automatically.  The second subgoal is:

       [[
  ============================
   (a0,
   fhapp (B:=B) (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2 ++ ls3) b
     (fhapp (B:=B) (ls1:=ls2) (ls2:=ls3) hls2 hls3)) ==
   (a0,
   fhapp (B:=B) (ls1:=ls1 ++ ls2) (ls2:=ls3)
     (fhapp (B:=B) (ls1:=ls1) (ls2:=ls2) b hls2) hls3)
 
       ]]

       It looks like one rewrite with the inductive hypothesis should be enough to make the goal trivial.

       [[
    rewrite IHls1.

Error: Impossible to unify "fhlist B ((ls1 ++ ?1572) ++ ?1573)" with
 "fhlist B (ls1 ++ ?1572 ++ ?1573)"
 
       ]]

       We see that [JMeq] is not a silver bullet.  We can use it to simplify the statements of equality facts, but the Coq type-checker uses non-trivial heterogeneous equality facts no more readily than it uses standard equality facts.  Here, the problem is that the form [(e1, e2)] is syntactic sugar for an explicit application of a constructor of an inductive type.  That application mentions the type of each tuple element explicitly, and our [rewrite] tries to change one of those elements without updating the corresponding type argument.

       We can get around this problem by another multiple use of [generalize].  We want to bring into the goal the proper instance of the inductive hypothesis, and we also want to generalize the two relevant uses of [fhapp]. *)

    generalize (fhapp b (fhapp hls2 hls3))
      (fhapp (fhapp b hls2) hls3)
      (IHls1 _ _ b hls2 hls3).
    (** [[
  ============================
   forall (f : fhlist B (ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3))
     (f0 : fhlist B ((ls1 ++ ls2) ++ ls3)), f == f0 -> (a0, f) == (a0, f0)
 
        ]]

        Now we can rewrite with append associativity, as before. *)

    rewrite app_ass.
    (** [[
  ============================
   forall f f0 : fhlist B (ls1 ++ ls2 ++ ls3), f == f0 -> (a0, f) == (a0, f0)
 
       ]]

       From this point, the goal is trivial. *)

    intros f f0 H; rewrite H; reflexivity.
  Qed.
(* end thide *)
End fhapp'.


(** * Equivalence of Equality Axioms *)

(* EX: Show that the approaches based on K and JMeq are equivalent logically. *)

(* begin thide *)
(** Assuming axioms (like axiom K and [JMeq_eq]) is a hazardous business.  The due diligence associated with it is necessarily global in scope, since two axioms may be consistent alone but inconsistent together.  It turns out that all of the major axioms proposed for reasoning about equality in Coq are logically equivalent, so that we only need to pick one to assert without proof.  In this section, we demonstrate this by showing how each of the previous two sections' approaches reduces to the other logically.

   To show that [JMeq] and its axiom let us prove [UIP_refl], we start from the lemma [UIP_refl'] from the previous section.  The rest of the proof is trivial. *)

Lemma UIP_refl'' : forall (A : Type) (x : A) (pf : x = x), pf = refl_equal x.
  intros; rewrite (UIP_refl' pf); reflexivity.
Qed.

(** The other direction is perhaps more interesting.  Assume that we only have the axiom of the [Eqdep] module available.  We can define [JMeq] in a way that satisfies the same interface as the combination of the [JMeq] module's inductive definition and axiom. *)

Definition JMeq' (A : Type) (x : A) (B : Type) (y : B) : Prop :=
  exists pf : B = A, x = match pf with refl_equal => y end.

Infix "===" := JMeq' (at level 70, no associativity).

(** We say that, by definition, [x] and [y] are equal if and only if there exists a proof [pf] that their types are equal, such that [x] equals the result of casting [y] with [pf].  This statement can look strange from the standpoint of classical math, where we almost never mention proofs explicitly with quantifiers in formulas, but it is perfectly legal Coq code.

   We can easily prove a theorem with the same type as that of the [JMeq_refl] constructor of [JMeq]. *)

(** remove printing exists *)
Theorem JMeq_refl' : forall (A : Type) (x : A), x === x.
  intros; unfold JMeq'; exists (refl_equal A); reflexivity.
Qed.

(** printing exists $\exists$ *)

(** The proof of an analogue to [JMeq_eq] is a little more interesting, but most of the action is in appealing to [UIP_refl]. *)

Theorem JMeq_eq' : forall (A : Type) (x y : A),
  x === y -> x = y.
  unfold JMeq'; intros.
  (** [[
  H : exists pf : A = A,
        x = match pf in (_ = T) return T with
            | refl_equal => y
            end
  ============================
   x = y
 
      ]] *)

  destruct H.
  (** [[
  x0 : A = A
  H : x = match x0 in (_ = T) return T with
          | refl_equal => y
          end
  ============================
   x = y
 
      ]] *)

  rewrite H.
  (** [[
  x0 : A = A
  ============================
   match x0 in (_ = T) return T with
   | refl_equal => y
   end = y
 
      ]] *)

  rewrite (UIP_refl _ _ x0); reflexivity.
Qed.

(** We see that, in a very formal sense, we are free to switch back and forth between the two styles of proofs about equality proofs.  One style may be more convenient than the other for some proofs, but we can always interconvert between our results.  The style that does not use heterogeneous equality may be preferable in cases where many results do not require the tricks of this chapter, since then the use of axioms is avoided altogether for the simple cases, and a wider audience will be able to follow those %``%#"#simple#"#%''% proofs.  On the other hand, heterogeneous equality often makes for shorter and more readable theorem statements.

   It is worth remarking that it is possible to avoid axioms altogether for equalities on types with decidable equality.  The [Eqdep_dec] module of the standard library contains a parametric proof of [UIP_refl] for such cases. *)
(* end thide *)


(** * Equality of Functions *)

(** The following seems like a reasonable theorem to want to hold, and it does hold in set theory. [[
   Theorem S_eta : S = (fun n => S n).
 
   ]]

   Unfortunately, this theorem is not provable in CIC without additional axioms.  None of the definitional equality rules force function equality to be %\textit{%#<i>#extensional#</i>#%}%.  That is, the fact that two functions return equal results on equal inputs does not imply that the functions are equal.  We %\textit{%#<i>#can#</i>#%}% assert function extensionality as an axiom. *)

(* begin thide *)
Axiom ext_eq : forall A B (f g : A -> B),
  (forall x, f x = g x)
  -> f = g.
(* end thide *)

(** This axiom has been verified metatheoretically to be consistent with CIC and the two equality axioms we considered previously.  With it, the proof of [S_eta] is trivial. *)

Theorem S_eta : S = (fun n => S n).
(* begin thide *)
  apply ext_eq; reflexivity.
Qed.
(* end thide *)

(** The same axiom can help us prove equality of types, where we need to %``%#"#reason under quantifiers.#"#%''% *)

Theorem forall_eq : (forall x : nat, match x with
                                      | O => True
                                      | S _ => True
                                    end)
  = (forall _ : nat, True).

  (** There are no immediate opportunities to apply [ext_eq], but we can use [change] to fix that. *)

(* begin thide *)
  change ((forall x : nat, (fun x => match x with
                                       | 0 => True
                                       | S _ => True
                                     end) x) = (nat -> True)).
  rewrite (ext_eq (fun x => match x with
                              | 0 => True
                              | S _ => True
                            end) (fun _ => True)).
  (** [[
2 subgoals
  
  ============================
   (nat -> True) = (nat -> True)

subgoal 2 is:
 forall x : nat, match x with
                 | 0 => True
                 | S _ => True
                 end = True
      ]] *)

  reflexivity.

  destruct x; constructor.
Qed.
(* end thide *)


(** * Exercises *)

(** %\begin{enumerate}%#<ol>#

%\item%#<li># Implement and prove correct a substitution function for simply-typed lambda calculus.  In particular:
%\begin{enumerate}%#<ol>#
  %\item%#<li># Define a datatype [type] of lambda types, including just booleans and function types.#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Define a type family [exp : list type -> type -> Type] of lambda expressions, including boolean constants, variables, and function application and abstraction.#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Implement a definitional interpreter for [exp]s, by way of a recursive function over expressions and substitutions for free variables, like in the related example from the last chapter.#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Implement a function [subst : forall t' ts t, exp (t' :: ts) t -> exp ts t' -> exp ts t].  The type of the first expression indicates that its most recently bound free variable has type [t'].  The second expression also has type [t'], and the job of [subst] is to substitute the second expression for every occurrence of the %``%#"#first#"#%''% variable of the first expression.#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Prove that [subst] preserves program meanings.  That is, prove
  [[
forall t' ts t (e : exp (t' :: ts) t) (e' : exp ts t') (s : hlist typeDenote ts),
  expDenote (subst e e') s = expDenote e (expDenote e' s ::: s)
 
  ]]
  where [:::] is an infix operator for heterogeneous %``%#"#cons#"#%''% that is defined in the book's [DepList] module.#</li>#
#</ol>#%\end{enumerate}%
  The material presented up to this point should be sufficient to enable a good solution of this exercise, with enough ingenuity.  If you get stuck, it may be helpful to use the following structure.  None of these elements need to appear in your solution, but we can at least guarantee that there is a reasonable solution based on them.
%\begin{enumerate}%#<ol>#
  %\item%#<li># The [DepList] module will be useful.  You can get the standard dependent list definitions there, instead of copying-and-pasting from the last chapter.  It is worth reading the source for that module over, since it defines some new helpful functions and notations that we did not use last chapter.#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Define a recursive function [liftVar : forall ts1 ts2 t t', member t (ts1 ++ ts2) -> member t (ts1 ++ t' :: ts2)].  This function should %``%#"#lift#"#%''% a de Bruijn variable so that its type refers to a new variable inserted somewhere in the index list.#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Define a recursive function [lift' : forall ts t (e : exp ts t) ts1 ts2 t', ts = ts1 ++ ts2 -> exp (ts1 ++ t' :: ts2) t] which performs a similar lifting on an [exp].  The convoluted type is to get around restrictions on [match] annotations.  We delay %``%#"#realizing#"#%''% that the first index of [e] is built with list concatenation until after a dependent [match], and the new explicit proof argument must be used to cast some terms that come up in the [match] body.#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Define a function [lift : forall ts t t', exp ts t -> exp (t' :: ts) t], which handles simpler top-level lifts.  This should be an easy one-liner based on [lift'].#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Define a recursive function [substVar : forall ts1 ts2 t t', member t (ts1 ++ t' :: ts2) -> (t' = t) + member t (ts1 ++ ts2)].  This function is the workhorse behind substitution applied to a variable.  It returns [inl] to indicate that the variable we pass to it is the variable that we are substituting for, and it returns [inr] to indicate that the variable we are examining is %\textit{%#<i>#not#</i>#%}% the one we are substituting for.  In the first case, we get a proof that the necessary typing relationship holds, and, in the second case, we get the original variable modified to reflect the removal of the substitutee from the typing context.#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Define a recursive function [subst' : forall ts t (e : exp ts t) ts1 t' ts2, ts = ts1 ++ t' :: ts2 -> exp (ts1 ++ ts2) t' -> exp (ts1 ++ ts2) t].  This is the workhorse of substitution in expressions, employing the same proof-passing trick as for [lift'].  You will probably want to use [lift] somewhere in the definition of [subst'].#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Now [subst] should be a one-liner, defined in terms of [subst'].#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Prove a correctness theorem for each auxiliary function, leading up to the proof of [subst] correctness.#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># All of the reasoning about equality proofs in these theorems follows a regular pattern.  If you have an equality proof that you want to replace with [refl_equal] somehow, run [generalize] on that proof variable.  Your goal is to get to the point where you can [rewrite] with the original proof to change the type of the generalized version.  To avoid type errors (the infamous %``%#"#second-order unification#"#%''% failure messages), it will be helpful to run [generalize] on other pieces of the proof context that mention the equality's lefthand side.  You might also want to use [generalize dependent], which generalizes not just one variable but also all variables whose types depend on it.  [generalize dependent] has the sometimes-helpful property of removing from the context all variables that it generalizes.  Once you do manage the mind-bending trick of using the equality proof to rewrite its own type, you will be able to rewrite with [UIP_refl].#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># A variant of the [ext_eq] axiom from the end of this chapter is available in the book module [Axioms], and you will probably want to use it in the [lift'] and [subst'] correctness proofs.#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># The [change] tactic should come in handy in the proofs about [lift] and [subst], where you want to introduce %``%#"#extraneous#"#%''% list concatenations with [nil] to match the forms of earlier theorems.#</li>#
  %\item%#<li># Be careful about [destruct]ing a term %``%#"#too early.#"#%''%  You can use [generalize] on proof terms to bring into the proof context any important propositions about the term.  Then, when you [destruct] the term, it is updated in the extra propositions, too.  The [case_eq] tactic is another alternative to this approach, based on saving an equality between the original term and its new form.#</li>#
#</ol>#%\end{enumerate}%
#</li>#
   
#</ol>#%\end{enumerate}% *)